Chapter 1 SYNOPSIS: MODALITY and EXPLANATORY REASONING

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Chapter 1 SYNOPSIS: MODALITY and EXPLANATORY REASONING Chapter 1 SYNOPSIS: MODALITY AND EXPLANATORY REASONING I aim to shed light on a broad family of modal notions whose most widely discussed representative is the concept of metaphysical necessity. This choice of topic requires little justification or explanation. Since the work of Lewis, Kripke and others ushered in the modal turn in analytic philosophy, the concept of necessity has been at the forefront of the communal philosophical mind. Today, modality is one of the most active areas of research in metaphysics, and modal notions are central to philosophical theorizing across the board—from the foundations of logic to moral theory. Given this trend, it seems to be more important than ever to gain a clear philosophical understanding of modality, not least in order to determine whether modal concepts can bear the weight that so much of recent philosophical practice has placed on them. There are different ways of elucidating a concept. For example, one can shed some light on it by clarifying its formal and logical properties, and its inferential and analytic connections to other notions. A lot of excellent work like this has been done on modal concepts. More ambitiously, one can try to give a full-blown analysis of modal notions. This task has been attempted less frequently and, in my opinion, less successfully. David Lewis’ account is the most developed and famous, but it rests on problematic ontological assumptions and it runs counter to actualist intuitions that are widely shared and, in my opinion, correct. Consequently, I think that we should look for a different analysis of necessity. We do not start this project with a guarantee of success. It may turn out that no informative analysis of modal concepts is possible, and that we should be primitivists or eliminativists about modality. But at this stage it is too early to throw in the towel. It is an important aim of this book is to advertise a new analysis of modal concepts. I will combine this objective with two other goals. Firstly, I think that a comprehensive theory of the modal domain should not stop at analyzing modal notions. It should also explain why we go in for modal thinking at all. What purpose does this practice serve? Why have creatures with our concerns and interests developed the capacity for modal thought? A comprehensive account should offer both a theory of modality and a theory of the practice of modalizing. It should, as it were, combine an internal with an external viewpoint on this practice. Before we start to philosophize about modality, we have a set of (often implicit) assumptions about modality. Philosophers provide this pre-philosophical system of beliefs with a foundation, and refine, extend and correct it from within. They act as participants of our practice of modalizing, i.e. their standpoint is internal to this practice. But philosophers should also make the practice of modalizing itself an object of study. They should, so to speak, take a standpoint external to the practice, in order to describe the practice, and explain what its function is, i.e. why it exists. It is a familiar fact that these two interests can pull in opposite directions. If we concentrate exclusively on giving a metaphysical account of modality, we might end up with a theory that makes it hard to explain why we are interested in modality. It is a common charge, justified or not, against Lewis’ account that it fails in this way.1 Even if there were other possible worlds in Lewis’ sense, so the objection goes, we would have no reason to be interested in them, and Lewis’ account therefore makes it a mystery why we should bother to have modal thoughts at all. At the other end of the spectrum there are theories that do well at explaining the purpose of our modal notions, but at the expense of giving implausible metaphysical accounts of the nature of modality. One example is the theory that for a proposition to be necessary is for it to owe its truth to a convention, perhaps the convention to regard it as true come what may. If some propositions are indeed conventionally exempted from empirical testing, then a concept that singles them out is undeniably useful for our epistemic practices. It is therefore easy for the conventionalist to explain the point of our modal notions. But this advantage is purchased at the price of an implausible theory of what necessity is. 1 For discussions of the point, see Kripke 1980, p. 45, Hazen 1979, pp. 320ff., Blackburn 1984, pp. 214f., Hale 1986, p. 77, McFetridge 1990, sct. 2, and Rosen 1990, pp. 349ff. 2 The task before us, then, is to develop a theory that permits us to achieve both goals, a credible metaphysical account of modality and a plausible account of the practice of modalizing. The best way of doing this is to integrate the two goals in a single enterprise: an account of the nature of modality can be guided by a hypothesis about the ordinary- life practice in which modal concepts originated, while assumptions about the nature of modality can in turn suggest ways of developing one’s ideas about the practice of modalizing. That is what I will try to do in this book. Secondly, it will be one of my aims to illuminate the relationship of modal notions to another family of concepts that are of central interest to metaphysics: the class of notions that contains the concept of causation and related explanatory notions. These concepts have had a career in philosophy that is similar to that of modal notions. The notion of causation was once subjected to a rigorous empiricist critique that convinced many philosophers that we can make sense of causal talk, if at all, only if we construe it as derived talk about regular succession, nomic entailment, or something of that kind. Consequently, for a long time causal notions were made to do very little work in philosophical theorizing. That changed around the 1960’s, when causal theories began to proliferate in many areas in the philosophy of mind, epistemology, metaphysics, and related fields. Suddenly, causation was used in theories about mental states, perception, knowledge, explanation, reference, persistence, the direction of time, and many other topics. It would not be exaggerated to talk of a ‘causal turn.’ This historical trend also has a second, more recent chapter: the rise to prominence of another group of concepts that have an important affinity to that of causation, such as metaphysical explanation and grounding, and related notions like essence, real definition and fundamentality. A cursory glance at the literatures on modality and on causation and explanation leaves little doubt that there are important connections between the two areas, but the nature of these ties and their philosophical implications are controversial. While many philosophers have tried to exploit the connections to give modal accounts of causation and explanation (often counterfactual temrs), I will argue for the opposite order of explanation. Many philosophers have taken Kripke’s work to demonstrate a deep and important distinction between epistemic necessity or a prioricity on the one hand and metaphysical 3 necessity on the other. I essentially agree with this assessment, but I would describe the fundamental divide as separating, not just two notions of necessity, but two broad families of modal notions, one epistemic and metaphysical or ontic. The ontic modalities include, not merely what is commonly known as metaphysical necessity, but an entire spectrum of other notions of necessity as well. It is the ontic modal notions that form the subject matter of this book. I will argue that, just as the notions of a prioricity and epistemic necessity are constitutively tied to the epistemic domain, the notions of ontic necessity are constitutively connected to the realm of causation and explanation. As we will see, the dependence of the modal on the causal and explanatory takes several different forms. Causal and explanatory concepts figure in the analyses of the various forms of ontic necessity. The ontic modal status of individual facts derives to a large extent from their position in the network of causal and explanatory relationships. And our practice of ontic modal thinking has its origin at least in part in causal and explanatory reasoning: notions like metaphysical necessity developed as useful auxiliaries to such reasoning. What follows is a brief synopsis of the main elements of my position. My exposition in this summary will be sketchy and occasionally a little dogmatic. Detailed arguments will be given in later chapters. 1.1 Ontic modality To say that a proposition is necessary, in either an epistemic or an ontic sense, is to say that, in some sense, its truth is very secure, firm or unshakable. How this thought is to be spelled out in detail depends on the form of modality that is under consideration. To say that a proposition is epistemically necessary is to say that its truth is, in some sense, very epistemically secure. To say that a proposition is metaphysically necessary, by contrast, is to say that its truth is very firm or secure in a metaphysical, non-epistemic sense. We can approach the task of analyzing ontic necessity by trying to develop a non-metaphorical way of understanding this idea of metaphysical security or unshakability. I will argue in Chapter 2 that it is the same notion that we are operating with when we raise the question, concerning some fact, how easily it could have failed to obtain: the less easily P could have been otherwise, the more secure its truth. To say that P is necessary, i.e.
Recommended publications
  • Why Essentialism Requires Two Senses of Necessity’, Ratio 19 (2006): 77–91
    Please cite the official published version of this article: ‘Why Essentialism Requires Two Senses of Necessity’, Ratio 19 (2006): 77–91. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9329.2006.00310.x WHY ESSENTIALISM REQUIRES TWO SENSES OF NECESSITY1 Stephen K. McLeod Abstract I set up a dilemma, concerning metaphysical modality de re, for the essentialist opponent of a ‘two senses’ view of necessity. I focus specifically on Frank Jackson’s two- dimensional account in his From Metaphysics to Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998). I set out the background to Jackson’s conception of conceptual analysis and his rejection of a two senses view. I proceed to outline two purportedly objective (as opposed to epistemic) differences between metaphysical and logical necessity. I conclude that since one of these differences must hold and since each requires the adoption of a two senses view of necessity, essentialism is not consistent with the rejection of a two senses view. I. Terminological Preliminaries The essentialist holds that some but not all of a concrete object’s properties are had necessarily and that necessary properties include properties that are, unlike the property 1 Thanks to John Divers, audiences at the Open University Regional Centre, Leeds and the University of Glasgow and an anonymous referee for comments. 2 of being such that logical and mathematical truths hold, non-trivially necessary. It is a necessary condition on a property’s being essential to an object that it is had of necessity. In the case of concrete objects, some such properties are discoverable by partly empirical means.
    [Show full text]
  • On Categories and a Posteriori Necessity: a Phenomenological Echo
    © 2012 The Author Metaphilosophy © 2012 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd Published by Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK, and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA METAPHILOSOPHY Vol. 43, Nos. 1–2, January 2012 0026-1068 ON CATEGORIES AND A POSTERIORI NECESSITY: A PHENOMENOLOGICAL ECHO M. J. GARCIA-ENCINAS Abstract: This article argues for two related theses. First, it defends a general thesis: any kind of necessity, including metaphysical necessity, can only be known a priori. Second, however, it also argues that the sort of a priori involved in modal metaphysical knowledge is not related to imagination or any sort of so-called epistemic possibility. Imagination is neither a proof of possibility nor a limit to necessity. Rather, modal metaphysical knowledge is built on intuition of philo- sophical categories and the structures they form. Keywords: a priori, categories, intuition, metaphysical necessity. Fantasy abandoned by reason produces impossible monsters. —Francisco de Goya (1746–1828), The Caprices, plate 43, The Sleep of Reason Produces Monsters 1. Introduction Statements of fact are necessarily true when their truth-maker facts cannot but be the case. Statements of fact are contingently true when their truth-maker facts might not have been the case. I shall argue that modal knowledge, that is, knowledge that a (true/false) statement is necessarily/ contingently true, must be a priori knowledge, even if knowledge that the statement is true or false can be a posteriori. In particular, justified accept- ance of necessary facts requires a priori modal insight concerning some category which they instantiate. In this introduction, the first part of the article, I maintain that Kripke claimed that the knowledge that a statement has its truth-value as a matter of necessity/contingency is a priori founded—even when knowl- edge of its truth/falsehood is a posteriori.
    [Show full text]
  • The Transience of Possibility Reina Hayaki
    Forthcoming in the European Journal of Analytic Philosophy (2006). The Transience of Possibility Reina Hayaki ABSTRACT. The standard view of metaphysical necessity is that it is truth in all possible worlds, and therefore that the correct modal logic for metaphysical necessity is S5, in models of which all worlds are accessible from each other. I argue that S5 cannot be the correct logic for metaphysical necessity because accessibility is not symmetric: there are possible worlds that are accessible from ours but from which our world is not accessible. There are (or could be) some individuals who, if they had not existed, could not have existed. Once the possibility of such individuals is lost, it is gone forever. 1. Truth in all possible worlds? It is now widely (though not universally) accepted that metaphysical necessity is to be distinguished from logical necessity. A proposition is logically necessary if it is a theorem of logic. The notion of logical necessity is not without its problems. When we say “a theorem of logic”, which logic is appropriate for this definition? Should we use mere first-order logic, or something more powerful? (Are axioms of second-order logic logically necessary truths?) What if the relevant logic is not complete, so that some true sentences are not theorems? Are all mathematical truths logically necessary? Or, given the apparent failure of efforts to reduce mathematics to logic, should we say that some 1 mathematical propositions are not logically necessary but perhaps “mathematically necessary”, relative to a particular system of mathematics? How should we adjudicate wrangling between adherents of mutually incompatible logics, such as classical and non- classical logics? Regardless of how we answer these questions, the notion of logical necessity is at heart a syntactic one.
    [Show full text]
  • Ither Metaphysical Necessity?
    This is a repository copy of W(h)ither Metaphysical Necessity?. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/131388/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Divers, J orcid.org/0000-0002-1286-6587 (2018) W(h)ither Metaphysical Necessity? Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 92 (1). pp. 1-25. ISSN 0309-7013 https://doi.org/10.1093/arisup/aky008 (c) 2018 The Aristotelian Society This is a pre-copyedited, author-produced PDF of an article accepted for publication in Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume xcii following peer review. The version of record Divers, J (2018) W(h)ither Metaphysical Necessity? Aristotelean Society Supplementary Volume, 92 (1). pp. 1-25. ISSN 0309-7013 is available online at: https://doi.org/10.1093/arisup/aky008. Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ W(H)ITHER METAPHYSICAL NECESSITY? By John Divers G20, Michael Sadler Building, University of Leeds, Leeds LS2 9JT Abstract I argue that a pragmatic scepticism about metaphysical modality is a perfectly reasonable position to maintain.
    [Show full text]
  • "Metaphysical" Possibility Revisited
    Justin Clarke-Doane Columbia University “Metaphysical” Possibility Revisited Metaphysical Possibility: That alethic, non-deontic, modality whose necessities are supposed to include the likes of conceptual truths, (pure) mathematical truths, truths of fundamental ontology (such as that there are, or are not, propositions, properties, or possible worlds), mereological truths, identity truths, explanatorily basic normative truths, and grounding truths. o Sider: “We are told that logic…is metaphysically necessary. We are told that laws of nature are not….[I]t is metaphysically necessary that “nothing can be in two places at once”, and so on. This conception falls…short of a full criterion. But a thin conception is not in itself problematic. For when a notion is taken to be fundamental, one often assumes that the facts involving the notion will outrun one's conception [2011, 266].” It is widely agreed that the intelligibility of metaphysical modality has been vindicated. o Quine: “I do not myself make sense…of metaphysical necessity [1990, 224].” o Williamson: “[M]etaphysical modality is only one member of the extended family of objective modalities. Arguments for scepticism about metaphysical modality tend [implausibly] to generalize to other objective modalities [2016, 462].” But even if metaphysical modality is intelligible, it could lack much metaphysical significance. I will argue that this is the case, and will conclude with an alternative conception of possibility. Extant “Deflationist” Critiques Sidelle [1989] & Unger [2014]: “Twin Earth” thought experiments just concern the meaning of a word. We all agree what worlds there are. We just disagree about how to describe them. Problem: This critique is quite limited.
    [Show full text]
  • Causal Necessity in Aristotle (Final Version)
    Causal Necessity in Aristotle Nathanael Stein [to appear in the British Journal for the History of Philosophy] 1. Introduction Recent discussions of causation have seen a revival of several concepts after a period in which Humean and neo-Humean views and critiques had rendered them suspect: causal powers, dispositions, and causal necessitation.1 Along these lines, for example, some theorists appeal to causal powers as genuine features of objects which enable them to act on other things, while others explicate the idea of causal determination by appealing to and defending the idea of causal necessitation.2 In general, the redeployments of these concepts figure in attempts to understand the relation of causation as one in which causes determine or bring about their effects in virtue of their intrinsic 1 The notion of causal necessity, for example, has been defended by several theorists: the so-called Dretske- Tooley-Armstrong (Dretske (1977), Tooley (1977), Armstrong (1983)) theory of natural laws posits nomological (as distinct from metaphysical) necessitation relations between universals, while Shoemaker (1998) argues that causal necessity simply is a kind of metaphysical necessity, one which is rooted in the causal powers of certain properties. Powers and dispositions, once widely ridiculed as explanatorily vacuous, have been defended by Harré (1970), Shoemaker (1980), Cartwright (1994), Heil (2005), and Martin (1994), among others. These views contrast with so-called counterfactual analyses of causation, the most well-known of which is that of David Lewis (1973), (1994), and (2000), attempt to account for causation without appealing to causal necessitation, often citing Hume as the reason for their doing so, as Lewis does.
    [Show full text]
  • CAUSAL and METAPHYSICAL NECESSITY 61 Possibility
    CAUSAL AND METAPHYSICAL View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk NECESSITY brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers BY SYDNEY SHOEMAKER Abstract: Any property has two sorts of causal features: “forward-looking” ones, having to do with what its instantiation can contribute to causing, and “backward-looking” ones, having to do with how its instantiation can be caused. Such features of a property are essential to it, and properties sharing all of their causal features are identical. Causal necessity is thus a special case of metaphysical necessity. Appeals to imaginability have no more force against this view than they do against the Kripkean view that statements like “Gold is an element” are metaphysically necessary. 1. There was a time, within the memory of some of us, when it was widely accepted that there are just two kinds of necessity. There was logical necessity, which was generally construed as including the necessity of analytic truths. This was assumed to be something to which we have an a priori access. And there was causal necessity, to which our only access is empirical. Since the dominant views about causality then current were Humean in inspiration, there was some question as to how so-called causal necessity, the distinctive status of causal laws and their consequences, deserved the name of “necessity” at all. But that was what it was frequently called. Since then the boat has been radically rocked, first by Quine and then by Kripke. The intended effects of their attacks on the traditional view were of course very different.
    [Show full text]
  • How to Make Possibility Safe for Empiricists Abstract 1. Introduction
    Draft commenced August 31, 2020. Version of October 16, 26, November 4, 2020; January 12, February 21, March 1, 2021. Typo corrections, August 26, 2021 How to Make Possibility Safe for Empiricists John D. Norton1 Department of History and Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh http://www.pitt.edu/~jdnorton Abstract What is possible, according to the empiricist conception, is what our evidence positively allows; and what is necessary is what it compels. These notions, along with logical possibility, are the only defensible notions of possibility and necessity. In so far as nomic and metaphysical possibilities are defensible, they fall within empirical possibility. These empirical conceptions are incompatible with traditional possible world semantics. Empirically necessary propositions cannot be defined as those true in all possible worlds. There can be empirical possibilities without empirical necessities. The duality of possibility and necessity can be degenerate and can even be falsified. 1. Introduction What are “small-e” empiricist2 philosophers of science, like me, to make of possibilities? They are central to science. Our best theories of gravity and stellar structure tell us that it is 1 My thanks to Yemima Ben-Menahem, Jeremy Butterfield, Patrick Dürr, Carl Hoefer, Edouard Machery, Brian McLoone, James Norton, Matt Parker, Bryan Roberts, Margot Strohminger and Jim Woodward for helpful discussion. They bear no responsibility for the content of this paper other than for failing to talk me out of it. 2 A “small-e” empiricist holds that we can only learn contingent truths of the world from experiences of the world. A “big-E” Empiricist holds the stronger view that these experiences are all we can learn.
    [Show full text]
  • Necessity and Contingency in Leibniz. G
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 1-1-1974 Necessity and contingency in Leibniz. G. W. Fitch University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1 Recommended Citation Fitch, G. W., "Necessity and contingency in Leibniz." (1974). Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014. 2083. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1/2083 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. NECESSITY AND CONTINGENCY IN LEIBNIZ A Dissertation Presented By GREGORY WERNER FITCH Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY September 1974 Philosophy (c) Gregory Werner Fitch 1974 All Rights Reserved iii NECESSITY AND CONTINGENCY IN LEIBNIZ A Dissertation By GREGORY WERNER FITCH Approved as to style and content by: clJLl -i Robert C. Sle'igh'Jr., Ph.D., Chairman of Committee Vere C. Chappell, Ph.D., Member /) t Fred A. Feldman, Ph.D. , Member % U* r rank W. Heny, Ph.D. Member \14ajL C, Vere C. Chappell, Ph.D., Department Head Department of Philosophy September 1974 Necessity and Contingency in Leibniz (September 1974) Gregory W. Fitch, B.A. , Western Washington State College M.A, , University of Massachusetts Directed by: Robert C. Sleigh Jr., Ph.D. Among the objections raised against Leibniz's metaphysical views, the problem of contingency is one of the most crucial and difficult problems Leibniz faced.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz on Contingency and Freedom: a Molinism Friendly Account
    Leibniz on Contingency and Freedom: A Molinism Friendly Account Dissertation Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Juan Garcia, MA Graduate Program in Philosophy The Ohio State University 2018 Dissertation Committee: Tamar Rudavsky, Advisor Julia Jorati, Advisor Lisa Downing William Taschek © 2018 by Juan Garcia All rights reserved. Abstract: Some philosophical ideas, like metals, reveal their most interesting qualities when stretched. As I see it, the intelligibility and plausibility of the concept of contingency, as a condition for freedom, is stretched significantly by three of Leibniz’s major philosophical commitments: i) a robust version of the principle of sufficient reason; ii) strong theological commitments like divine foreknowledge and robust providence; and iii) Leibniz’s distinctive thesis of complete individual concepts – the doctrine that every substance has an individual concept which includes predicates denoting everything that will ever happen to it. Many interpreters think that these Leibnizian commitments stretch contingency to the breaking point: Leibniz cannot retain a genuine type of contingency. In this dissertation, I argue that these interpreters are mistaken and that Leibniz can accommodate a plausible type of contingency. Two important steps in reaching this conclusion are the following. First, I identify a kind of explanation of rational action according to which the explanans does not necessitate the explanandum. Second, I develop an account that makes sense of individual concepts including contingent truths as contingent. This account both sheds new light on some of Leibniz’s central views on contingency and freedom, and expands our substantive understanding of contingency as a condition for freedom.
    [Show full text]
  • Logical Combinatorialism
    Logical Combinatorialism Andrew Bacon* July 13, 2020 Abstract In explaining the notion of a fundamental property or relation, metaphysicians will often draw an analogy with languages. The fundamental properties and relations stand to reality as the primitive predicates and relations stand to a language: the smallest set of vocabulary God would need in order to write the `book of the world'. In this paper I attempt to make good on this metaphor. In order to do this I introduce a modality that, put informally, stands to propositions as logical truth stands to sentences. The resulting theory, formulated in higher-order logic, also vindicates the Humean idea that fundamental properties and relations are freely recombinable and a variant of the structural idea that propositions can be decomposed into their fundamental constituents via logical operations. Indeed, it is seen that, although these ideas are seemingly distinct, they are not independent, and fall out of a natural and general theory about the granularity of reality. Metaphysicians often theorize in terms of the notion of a property or relation being fundamental. When it comes to spelling out what this means, metaphors abound. According to one gloss, the fundamental properties and relations are the primitive constants in the language of reality, from which all other properties and relations can be defined; they are the vocabulary God would need in order to write the `book of the world' (Sider (2011)). The metaphor of reality as a language is one that is hard to make precise, and, taken too literally, has been shown to be subject to paradoxes.1 I take this as a warning to proceed cautiously, by codifying our metaphysics in a precise formal language where possible | in this case, higher-order logic | and employing model theoretic techniques to check for consistency.
    [Show full text]
  • Certainty, Necessity, and Knowledge in Hume's Treatise
    Certainty, Necessity, and Knowledge in Hume’s Treatise Miren Boehm Abstract: Hume appeals to different kinds of certainties and necessities in the Treatise. He contrasts the certainty that arises from intuition and demonstrative reasoning with the certainty that arises from causal reasoning. He denies that the causal maxim is absolutely or metaphysically necessary, but he nonetheless takes the causal maxim and ‘proofs’ to be necessary. The focus of this paper is the certainty and necessity involved in Hume’s concept of knowledge. I defend the view that intuitive certainty, in particular, is certainty of the invariability or necessity of relations between ideas. Against David Owen and Helen Beebee, I argue that the certainty involved in intuition depends on the activity of the mind. I argue, further, that understanding this activity helps us understand more clearly one of Hume’s most important theses, namely that experience is the source of a distinct kind of certainty and of necessity. Hume acknowledges that the general maxim in philosophy: “whatever begins to exist, must have a cause of existence” is “suppos’d to be founded on intuition, and to be one of those maxims, which […] ’tis impossible for men in their hearts really to doubt of” (T 1.3.3.1).1 But he maintains that, if we examine the maxim by his “idea of knowledge,” “we shall discover in it no mark of any such intuitive certainty; but on the contrary shall find, that ‘tis of a nature quite foreign to that species of 1. David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed.
    [Show full text]