Quick viewing(Text Mode)

The Skeptical Challenge: A

The Skeptical Challenge: A

CEU eTD Collection THE SKEPTICAL CHALLENGE In partial fulfillment Doctor of in Philosophy Prof. Nenad Miscevic (secondary) Prof. Alvin Plantinga (external) Central European University Department of Philosophy Prof. Katalin Farkas Budapest, Hungary APPROACH Ksenija Puskaric

of the requirements for the degree of Submitted to Super 2009 By visors:

:

A CARTESIAN

CEU eTD Collection diploma in any university. thesis contains no material which has been accepted for the award of any other degree or published by except person any whe other previously material no contains thesis this belief and knowledge my of best the To

re due acknowledgement made. been duere This has ii

CEU eTD Collection ruled out. The main claim is that skeptical challenge can be answered. argument from incomprehensibility of the idea of , the deceive of Descartes‘ for the , which is defended as an . It offers a Cartesian response to the skeptical deceiver argument. On the basis imaginative model of experiences bears affect on the plausibility of compares how different theories of perception lead to skepticism, and how the perceptual knowledge This dissertation explores the plausibility of the Cartesian skeptical chal –

the presuppositions of the dream and deceiver arguments.It ABSTRACT iii

r error lenge regarding

- possibility is

the dream

CEU eTD Collection Chapter IV A Defense Of The Trademark Argument...... 113

Chapter I Chapter II Chapter III

Cartesian Skepticism And The Nature Of Perception...... Conclusion Of ChapterIII...... Conclusion Of ChapterII...... 69 Introduction...... The ...... 4.2. Is Th 4.1. The CartesianIdea Of God As The ActualInfinite...... 114 2.3. Intentionalism, The Common Factor, And The Possibility Of Skepticism....59 1.1. Cartesian Skepticism: The Dream And The Deceiver Argument...... 7 Conclusion O 1.2. The Structure Of The Cartesian Skeptical Arguments...... 12 2.2. Arguments That We Are Aware Of (Mere) Appearances: The Argument 2.1. Arguments That We Are Aware Of (Mere) Appearances: The Argument 3. 3. Non 3.1. Cartesian Steps Of The Dream Argument...... 73 3. 2. Sosa On The Dream Argument...... 88 Argument...... 88 Dream The On 3. 2.Sosa 2.4. Disjunctivism And Skepticism......

From Hallucination...... From ...... 20

God...... 4.2.1. The Argument From Doubt To The Priority Of The Idea Of e Idea Of God A Human Construct?...... 124 2.1.1. A Fe 2.2.2. Cou 2.1.2. The ‗Generalized‘ Argument From Illusion...... 32 Illusion...... 32 From Argument ‗Generalized‘ 2.1.2. The 3. 2. 1. A Response To The The To AResponse 3. 2.1. 2.2.3. A Thought Experiment Argument...... 47 2.2.1. Considerations Based On The Subjective Indistinguishability 3. 1. 3. The Criteria Of Wakefulness...... 82 Wakefulness...... 82 Of Criteria The 3. 1. Relation And The ‗Common Factor‘...... 41 3. 1. 2. What Is The Scope Of The Cartesian Dream Ar 3. 1. 1. The Dream Argument Is Self - Cartesian Steps Of The Dream Argument...... 104 f The Argument FromIllusion And Hallucination...... 57 2.2.3.1. The Objection From Conceivability...... 52 Conceivability...... 52 From Objection The 2.2.3.1. ntering the Phenomenal Sorites Argument...... 43 w Thoughts On Robinson‘s Datum Theory...... 28 ...... 36 CONTENTS iv Dream Argument...... 99

- Defeating (Moore)...... 77

...... 17 gument?...... 79 ...... 111 ...... 72

...... 125

...... 62

.....1

CEU eTD Collection Bibliography...... Conclusion......

Conclusion Of ChapterIV...... 4.3. The Argument For The Existence Of God...... 146 4. 2. 2. The Argument For Distinctness Of The Material and Objective Idea Of God...... 132 4. 2. 2. 2. The Incomprehensibility Of The Idea Of God...... 139 4. 2. 2. 1. The Unity Of The Idea Of God...... 157 v

...... 150 ...... 133 ....152

CEU eTD Collection achieve rather lived in accordance with nature and custom. The final goal of such a ―practice‖ was to Pyrrhonia which the mind is lead toward regarding things beyond appearances. famously defended by (160 inadequate to propositions concerning how things really are, on the grounds that there is insufficient and c. 100 Pyrrhonian skepticism and . origin in ancient Greece. Its teaching was established in two forms, famously known as "enquiry". As a development of skepticism and the importance of Descartes‘ project of problems proposed answer reaches back to this original framework, and is at the same time tuned to the guided by the religious tradition in which the original Cartesian challenge arises. My should be persuasive by the constraints that are rarely observed in recent attempts at answering. On the one hand, it response developed in Descartes‘ challenge with respect to perceptual knowledge, and The first school began with of El The word ―skepticism‖ comes from the Greek word The goal of my dissertation is to propose an interpretation of the Cartesian skeptical ataraxia

ns would not commit themselves to any judgment beyond how things seem. They and methods of the contemporary debate. Let me briefly explain the historic philosophical position skepticism of course predates Descartes, having its , quietude in which the mind remains undisturbed, and free from do – 40 b.c.e. The main thesis of was to suspend judgment on all

determine whether this knowledge is possible. The teaching was

standards of contemporary debate, on the other it should be

Meditations INTRODUCTION CHAPTER . I hope that the answer will satisfy a pair of - 210 AD) in a series of ―tropes‖, or ways by 1 is, c. 360

to propose a new defense of the theistic I Ŏ – 275 b.c.e., and was formulated by Ȯ ȿ ȷ ȸȮɂ

( skepsis Meditations ) meaning .

gmatism.

CEU eTD Collection skepticism in the sixteenth century, and he focuses on its development and impact1 from Savonarola to Bayle. intellectual life of the West. Not only religious, but more general skepticism, could no longer skeptical Pandora‘s box in theological domain. That had an immense undermine the authority of the pope and Church councils, and thereby opened up the skepticism. Church rebels and the Reformation used the skeptical pyrrhonian arguments to between the Reformation and the Church of Rome, that awoke an interest the notions following the lead of Popkin‘s (2003) perceptive analysis are merely historically related, are in also related methodologically the framework for my Cartesian project and its theistic aims. The two topics that seem to be brings to t to my main point. The historical context in which Descartes‘ (Cartesian) skepticism arose that time skeptical arguments had a different role than in ancient Greece, and this brings me during the intellectual crisis brought emerged in and Early Modern Periods. The revival of Greek skepticism occurred mainly through St. Augustine‘s t be on the basis of probabilities. Academic skepticism became known in the Western world can judge about things that refer beyond the immediately accessible content of our minds can unreliable, and that there was no criterion for determini could be known. They formulated arguments to show that and reasoning were on the issue of whether truths may be known, Academics positively asserted that nothing nothing could be known. Unlike Pyrrhonians who suspended judgme and , c. 213

In the History of Skepticism It was the of truth concerning faith that was raised in quarrels In the post Academic skepticism started in the Platonic Academy by Arcesilas, c. 315 he fore an important link between skepticism and religion, which will also serve as - Hellenistic period skepticism was not a very influential view, and it re – 129 b.c.e., who formulated arguments against Stoics, to show that

(2003) Popkin discusses historical and religious backgr

reatment of it in up by the Reformation in sixteenth century. However, at 2 Contra Academicos

ng what is true or false. The best we . 1

nt on all matters, even ound of the revival of impact on the whole .

. Let me expand on

in ancient – 241 b.b.e.,

-

CEU eTD Collection form. authority of the traditi be defeated, he embraced it. Our inability to attain knowledge on our own, he skepticalargued, givesdefense us reasonof faith to trust the authority of the Church, of Rotterdam proposed a strategy that seemsintellectual outrageously circles paradoxical of religious philosophers. While Catholic theologians offered2 historical evidence to justify pyrrhoniens engender a world. Popkin points out that ―only when skepticism had been carried to this extreme, to about things that seem most certain dreaming, and then introduces the possibility to bring skepticism to its highest peak, he first points out the danger that he might be unreliable not only at times, like in cases of and hallucinations, but always. In order Cartesian project of the full force of the method of doubt. Thus, the Cartesian skepticism was born. Let me sketch the reinforced skeptical arguments and unexpectedly, instead of rebuking the skeptics at first, Descartes created a new battery of means to solve the crisis. For that purpose he left Paris to meditate in Holland. Surprisingly mathematician, encouraged by Cardinal Bérulle began his own search for philosophic about the new trend ( centuries century. The quest for was a natural reaction that dominated through next two knowledge, and thereby generated the so called origins the early modern py be stopped neither by Reformed thinkers nor by the . From its theological

As Popkin (2003) interestinglypoints out, the skeptical arguments g

In the Moved 2 . crise pyrr

, could one overcome the force of skepticism‖ (2003, pp.148). Meditations

by the intellectual situation in Paris in which young minds were enthusiastic on (Church, Scripture). M. Montaigne further developed such an idea to its most radical nouveaux pyrrhoniens honienne -

that dominated the French Counter Meditations Descartes introduced the possibility that t rrhonian skepticism expanded to philosophy and natural

greater than that ever dreamed of by the -

the dream and the deceiv

in the briefest outline. -

mathematical truths, or the existence of the material ), Descartes, at that time respected scientist and

of being deceived by a powerful evil God, even crise pyrrhonienne 3

- Reformation. Realizing that skepticism could not er argument ave rise to different reactions in

of the early sixteenth he senses might be

-

nouveaux which disclosed the

al

-

a

CEU eTD Collection certain and indubitable just as carefully as I do from those which are patently3 false.‖ (AT VII 18: CSM 17) a cause that contains as much as the idea it represents, because truth, and existence. By the God, an idea of an infinitely supreme being who is presented a intellect is ―tuned‖ to truth in the right way. accident‖? Descartes needs to ensure that tru with his cognitive habits and ways is clearly and distinctly perceived by the mind is true? What if the Meditator is deceive the Meditator even about the most certain things? What guar both ways: how can such an epistemic principle be certain if the powerful evil God can criterion of truth. However, the edge of Descartes‘ weapon against skepticism threatens to cut distinctness by which he has arrived to that first indubitable truth gives him subsequently th doubts, and to reach awareness of oneself as essentially a thinking thing. Clearness and the process of dou states ―I think‖, and proceeds to ―I think therefore I am‖, as a conclusion of doubt. Namely, doubtful ―outer‖ realm presented by the senses, inward to arguments is neither to unsettle certainty nor to lead one to between Cartesian and ancient Greek skepticism; the purpose of Cartesian skeptical purgation by which the mind prepares itself to reach t false judgment, Descartes famously begins his inquiry with rejecting all uncertain opinions as by

―Reason now leads me to think that I should hold back my assent from opinions which are not completely - step, each step separately followed by an act of suspension of th 3 . Such process of radically emptying one‘s mind ultimately serves as a method of Descartes then proceeds to investigate the content of his mind, and finds the idea of The now already overworked pa Whereas ancient skeptics presented doubtfulness of various beliefs and opinions step

bting enables Descartes to recognize his own existence as the one who natural light

-

merely a product of an evil God, fate or ―cosmic th of , as he sees it, he realizes that such an idea must have

th is the Meditations 4

telos he indubitable truth. This is a difference

leads the Meditator from the cogito of our cognitive faculties, that the ataraxia s the ultimate source of good, , the very first truth that e particular target , but to reach certainty. antees that whatever that ex nihilo nihil fit -

together

. The

e

-

CEU eTD Collection without acknowledging God as the source of our capacities, and truth itself. 4 existence of God presented by Descartes in the perceptual knowledge. I propose a new defense of the so called ―trademark argument‖ for the know that I am not a victim of the deceiver. Hence, the ex defense of a Cartesian anti the problem concerning skeptical challenge that targets perceptual knowledge. I propose a skepticism concerning mathematical and intuitive knowledge, but is restricted to answe (knowledge of) God. However, my aim here is not to argue against or Cartesi Cartesian answer to skepticism regarding perceptual knowledge. I defend the basic tenet of converge. pure system essentially theistic in its outcome and its motivation. Instead of leaping into fideism or The ontological and epistemological priority of God makes the Cartesian philosophical the knowledge of the other objects of th I now have before me a road which will lead us from the contemplation of the true God . . . to known: Ultimately, Descartes‘ view is that all other knowledge proceeds after the existence of God is fiats, forever guaranteed by our realization that the Almightypeace cannot and deceive. security of seen as a , our ideas Onlyand our by truthsha seen as divine summarizes Descartes‘ path in rule. Inner certitude of the existence

By ―pure rationalism‖ I mean ―atheistic rationalism‖ that absolutely relies on our intellectual capacities, an (and theistic) , namely, that perceptual knowledge depends on Inspired by his admirable project, in this dissertation I present a version of the

of God who left his ―trademark‖ in the human mind secures reliability of the truth

ving walked through the valley of complete doubt could one be swept on to the 4 , Descartes‘ ans

cogito - skeptical strategy

Meditations wer to the

now receives objective support in God. Popkin poetically e universe. (AT VII 53: CSM 37)

crise pyrrhonienne in the following way: -

since I know that all Third Meditation 5

istence of God guarantees

shows how faith and reason

. My argument takes a novel

- perfect God exists then I

(2003 , pp. 155)

ring

-

CEU eTD Collection problem of establishing competence, and thereby argument defended by Ernest Sosa. I believe that the crux of the dream argument is the Cartesian and non an anti argument. I conclude that the internalist conception of evidence and knowledge, coupled with denies the ―common factor‖ is also vulnerable to a less committing version of the skepti matches‖ genuine perception. However, I argue that the disjunctivist theory of perception that framework to formul of skepticism because they posit a ―common factor‖ thesis which gives the skeptic a McDowell (1982) that both sense debate. I also take into account t argument from hallucination that addresses some objections raised in the contemporary theory, which are traditionally regarded as ―skeptic friendly‖. I present a thought experiment discuss the plausibility of arguments from illusion and h focusing on theories of perceptions that lead to, or are vulnerable to Cartesian skepticism. I introduce a brief preview of contemporary point of view, bringing up attempts to make a contribution in the area. Let me Meditations of God. comprehend about God. Hence, I propose an argument from incomprehensibility of the idea God, it rather dissolves the mind approach: it does not proceed from what we can compre - In chapter III, I discuss the dream skeptical argument, analyz In chapter II, I investigate the argumentative background of the skeptical threat, In method and to some exten epistemic luck requirement, renders the Cartesian skeptical challenge threatening.

. However, the Cartesian project is addressed and defended from the - Cartesian steps. In the first part I discuss a prominent reply to the dream ate the possibility of a non

the chapters. he intentionalist theory of perception. I conclude with - reality gap by way of dissimilitude - datum theory and intentionalism are open to the possibility t in content the current project follows Descartes‘

- 6 veridical experience that ―phenomenally knowing

allucination supporting sense hend about God to the existence of

that the criterion of wakefulness is ing it in two parts: –

by what we do not

- datum

cal

CEU eTD Collection of them within the ―epistemic luck‖ framework, defended by Pritchard (2005), and5 Sosa (2005). argument. Cartesian skeptical arguments that will be in our focus: the dream argument and the deceiver these arguments will occupy us throughout two chapters). There are two we way in which the Cartesian skeptical arguments are usually brief. Let me make good for this by presenting a slightly longer summary of the standard . Descartes‘, but cannot know negative counterpart, giving us enough understanding of God to know it is still clear, distinct and coherent. Such the idea cannot originate in the human mind. Although the idea of God is incomprehensible, argue that the unity and incomprehensibility of the idea of God gives us reason to believe that of God, which aims at responding the deceiving God ( intuitions. promis externalism. I conclude that the anti the dream argument, and contrast two epistemological positions imagining. In the secon destructive dilemma against the skeptic which is based on Sosa‘s view that dreaming is satisfied, even when it is satisfied. In response to thus presented argument, I propose a

I rely on reconstruction of the arguments originally introduced by Descartes, and conte 1.1. Cartesian Skepticism: The Dream And The Deceiver Argument ing prospect of a response that can (in principle) account for both epistemological The sketch of the Cartesian skeptical arguments I have presented has been extremely In chapter IV, I discuss and defend Descartes‘ trademark argument for the existence

what

it is also following the standards of the contemporary analytic approach in

He is. The argument I will defend is faithful to the religious tradition of d part of the chapter II I extrapolate premises and presuppositions of

- dream skepticism provided by Sosa‘s theory provides a

positive epistemic element balances its apparently 7

deus deceptor 5

presented (the discussion of –

internalism and ) ske that ptical argument. I mporary interpretations

He is, although we ll - known

CEU eTD Collection the senses is still not a good enough reason for universal doubt about the senses. That is why but he didn‘t think that this is strong e Descartes admitted that the phenomena of illusions show that senses 17) winter dressing they are deceived from the senses or in the distance, there are many other beliefs which doubt isYet quite althou impossible, even though Descartes mentions the phenomena of illusions at the beginning of his enquiry: the purpose of purging all opinions it suffices to find a reason to doubt sense have acquired either from foundations. Descartes observes that ―whatever I have up till now accepted as most true I foundations, the most efficient strategy that occurred to him was to question those very Given that Descartes believed that knowledge i But the system of beliefs is too large, examining one by one belief would be an endless task. false‖ (AT VII 18: CSM 17). completely c suspend judgment from all things that are uncertain: the edifice of knowledge from its very foundation. The principle leading him in this task is to certainty, he believes that he has to closely examine the whole system of beliefs and re realization, Descartes begins to seek a firm foundation of knowledge. In order to achieve he had adopted Reason now leads me to think I should hold back my assent from opinions which are not

At the beginning of the (i) The Dream Argument

gh the senses occasionally deceive us with respect to objects which are very small ertain and indubitable just as carefully as I do from those which are apparently

- a ―large amount of falsehoods‖ (AT VII 18: CSM 17). Struck by that gown, holding this piece of paper in my hands, and so on. (AT VII 18: CSM the senses or through the senses‖ (AT VII 18: CSM 17). Then, for First Meditation

for example, that I am here, sitting by t nough to lead us into . Fallibility of

Descartes observes that in the course of his life s structured like an edifice supported by its 8

occasionally he fire, wearing a - based beliefs.

deceive us,

- build

CEU eTD Collection Since experience is not sufficient to distinguish a ―good‖ from a ―bad‖ epistemic situation, not about the real chairs, fire, arms, etc., and consequently you h cannot tell whether you are dreaming or awake. If you are dreaming then the experience is r Descartes‘ conclusion is that there is no experiential criterion to distinguish waking from myself as sometimes having while asleep‖. (AT VII 77: CSM 53) that you pinched yourself, etc. As Descartes further says: whether they are awake, but all these things could happen in a dream; you may only dream wakefulness by pinching yourself, exercising the power of your will, asking other people waking experiences. Perhaps now you can think of performing a test t experiences you may notice that vivid and distinct are subjectively exactly like generalizes the conclusion; when reflecting upon the phenomenal character of dream beliefs were false. Nobody denies that we can be deceived in dreams. However, believe that they are real, until we finally wake up and realize it was just a dream and our had the same conviction while dreaming? You may try to appeal to your conviction that you are awake now. But how often have you experience is not a dream? Don‘t you think it is possible that you are about to wake up soon? woke up and realized that it was a mere dream? How do we all have had. How often did you believe that the plot of the dream was real, until you extending t Descartes needed a stronger argument [E]very sensory experience I have ever thought I was having while awake I can also think of

ealistic and vivid dream experiences. From this it follows that on the basis of the senses you While dreaming we don‘t know that images we have are not about real objects, we Descartes‘ starting point of the dream argument is provided by experiences of the kind he scope of doubt.

-

the dream argument makes a step forward in

9

you know that your present

ave false perceptual beliefs.

o check your the skeptic

CEU eTD Collection Descartes‘ position see S. Menn (1998). throughout the ―valley of skepticism‖, eventually lead him to indubitable kn doesn‘t by any means imply that correctness of his faith in God was ever under7 question. Faith in God, 6 following question (ii) The hyperbolical doubt. CSM 14). Hence, Descartes will need ―For whether I am awake or asleep two and three added together are five…‖(AT VII 20: and the truth of geometry and arithmetics are not within the scope of the dream skepticism. argument can question. The existence of the physical the mind creatively ―shuffles‖ into novel phantasms, there are limits to what the dream and having two hands. Since dreams are made of ―images‖ received from the senses, which dreams, even though I can not be certain at this very moment whether I‘ general properties (extension, shape, number) which provided the basic ―material‖ of my direction: even if I am dreaming now there has to be the external world ―out there‖ with most questioning the existence of the external world. Descartes says something in the following external world? One passage have two hands, that I‘ do with its scope. If I‘m dreaming now then I don't know that I‘m sitting by the fire, that I that ―I have two hands‖. senses cannot provide knowledge even about propositions that we find obv

Although this skeptical hypoth AT VII 20: CSM 13 In 1647 Leiden theologians accused Descartes of blasphemy for raising the One question about the ―Cartesian dream argument‖ as it is usually referred to, has to Deus Deceptor

7 :

m holding a paper, and so on. But, is it possible that there is no

Argument

esis was religiously inspired, Descartes‘ doubts whether God is a deceiver 6

in the

First Meditation

a stronger argument to reach the peak of the 10

suggests that the dream argument is not world with its most general properties owledge of God. For this defense of m sitting by the fire iously true, e.g.

CEU eTD Collection skeptical strategy. method almost equally well, the difference bet that the refers to t deceiver that is ―less offensive‖ (AT VII 23: CSM 15). Z. Janowski (2000) pointedKenny out (1968,that Descartespp. 35) thinks never that Descartes decides to introduce the evil geniusKennington hypothesis, (1987) a new argues version that of they the actually differ. In order to avoid any further8 troub intelligent directed toward truth, not merely accidentally, but intentionally so. Thus, only God the have epis that we are systematically deceived about things that seem to be most certain. In order to prove that there is a benevolent omnipotent God who would not deceive, nor create us such particular. this dissertation I will focus on the possibility (or impossibility) of perceptual knowledge in we know that things are the way they appear to the senses? How can we know anything? In If we grant the existence of a powerful epistemic threat, personif and three or count the sides of a square…?‖ (AT VII 21: CSM 14) certain faculties, the Meditator must concede that he might be deceived about things that seem most Assuming the possibility that the deceiving God created him together with his cognitive His question has to do with the possi VII 21: CSM 14) the same time ensuring that all these things appear to me to existabout just that as there they isdo nonow? earth, (AT no sky, no extended thing, no shape,God who no madesize, me no the place, kind whileof creature at that I am. How do I know that he has not br …how do I know that God has not brought it about that I too go wrong every time I add two And yet firmly rooted in my mind is the long

The so called deus deceptor - In order to get out of th he as

eve temological guarantor that our cognitive faculties are trustworthy they have to be Creator

n about mathematical truths. evil demon

could do, which evil genius could not. Although both hypotheses serve the skeptical ( Nous

hypothesis is often identified with omnipotens ), a , can secure us from the

e depths of the deceiver skepticism , but rather as bility that an omnipotent and creator God is a deceiver. ween them is significant for Cartesian theodicy and the anti

summe potens - standing opinion that there is an omnipotent 11

deus deceptor , thereby implying that there are some things

hypothesis. But Richard M. ied as a deceiver, how can 8

deus deceptor Descartes will need to

les with theologians,

skeptical ought it

-

CEU eTD Collection imperfection of creation with respect impact upon his epistemology 9 the fire‖). conclusion. (SH stands for ―skeptical hypothesis‖, and p for the propositi a form of a , consisting of two plausible premises that yield an unacceptable the ―dogmatic‖ to show that skeptical hypotheses can be ruled out (or are known to be fal on. All the skeptic needs is a coherent error the dialectical situation, the quite sure that I woke up this morning. So why bother with skepticism at all?‖ To make clear we believe that any of them obtains? There is no such thing as evil god (deceiver), and I am radically contradict common sense. A natural reaction to The two skeptical hypotheses raise alternative explanations of everyday experiences, which universal level. Radical skepticism concerning senses is of my particular of their formulations, both skeptical arguments question perceptual knowledge on a very epistemological project argument. The question of Meditator‘s origin is thus made crucial for Descartes‘

The deus deceptor The Cartesian skeptical arguments share a common structure; they can be presented in Needless to elaborate much, radical skepticism is as counter Although significantly differing in the extent of doubt they raise and presuppositions 2. 1. I don't know that I'm not deceived /dreaming. ( If I don‘t know that I'm not deceived /dreaming then I don‘t know that I am sitting by fire.( the 1.2. The Structure Of The Cartesian Skeptical Argument

hypothesis will ultimately lead Descartes to discuss theodicy in a way that bears direct 9 . ¬K ¬K ¬SH -

the problem of the apparent discrepancy between the power of God and skeptic need not ague that skeptical hypotheses are actually going

to human proneness to error. ŗ ¬Kp )

- possibility that 12

¬K¬SH this would be to ask ―Why would might . The burden of proof is on )

- intuitive as it can get.

on ―I am sitting by interest here. s

se).

CEU eTD Collection can be justifiers (BonJour, Davidson). 10 You believe that you are sitting by the fire the fire‖, justification that you apparently have for believing p is your sensory experience I am going to bear in mind, which relies on the following presuppositions have put the argument, I will sketch one way of understanding its more general structure that argu clarifications. me expand on the notion and introduce some necessary preliminary terminological - sense, I would like to emphasize Pritchard‘s (2005) point that Although Cartesian skepticism is a philosophical position that is in conflict with common near to being strong enough to support such a counter probably best refined to the claim that, however strong the argumentcounter may be, it's nowhere however strong the argument may be, it's not strong enough Theto adequatelyreaction that supp the skeptical argument is weak is probably best refined to the claim that, be found ―in the middle‖: Others would say ―Aw, come on!‖. K. a real problem about the human condition. (1984, pp.we find39) it immediately gripping. It appeals to something deep Iin thinkour nature that whenand seemswe first to raiseencou the arguments ―gripping‖: Reactions of contemporary thinkers to this argument are divided. Some, like B. Stroud find

skepticism itself relies on a There are epistemologists (―coherentists‖) who deny this claim, and argue that only ments can be presented. Instead of exploring all possible ways in which philosophers When empirical propositions (p) are concerned, e.g. the proposition ―I‘m sitting by There are many ways, theoretically more or less committing, in which the skeptical - 3. intuitive conclusion. And the reaction that the skeptical argument is absurdly weak is Therefore, I don't know that I am sitting by the fire. (

very sober intuition, namely, that knowledge excludes luck. Let

nter the sceptical reasoning outlined in the previous chapter DeRose‘s opinion is that the appropriate reaction is to because 13

you feel the he - int uitive conclusion. (1999, pp. 3)

-

paradoxically as it may seem ¬Kp at, your body, you see the )

beliefs

.

about experience ort such a

10

.

CEU eTD Collection (2005). ―Internalism‖ 11 principle. Hence, we are faced with the following disturbing argument: knows that premise, which gets enfolded through the following closure principle: luck. Let me elaborate on this point. it follows that there is no fire), the perceptual belief is opened to being undermined by bad that are incompatible with what we believe (e.g. if the deceiver skeptical possibilities obtain, method does not enable us to eli justification component is accessible by reflection alone. Given that the required reflective know that I'm not deceived‖. deceived. Therefore, the first premise of the skeptical deceiver argument follows: ―I experience right now. Then, you don‘t have internalist justification to believe that you are not least on the basis of re experience phenomenally exactly like genuine perception in the deceiver‘s world, then at experience important for justification, and for the skeptical arguments. If you could have an aspect of the experience is essentially bound to is only you who can report ―what is it like‖ to have such an experience. The phenomenal state just by deploying reflective faculties which the skeptic relies is of sensory experience chair, and so on. O

However, this is only one way of defining internalism about justification. For more options see Pappas, G. 1. I know that if I am sitting by the fire then I am not deceived. Pritchard (2005) argues that in the heart of the skeptical argument we find an anti The concept of knowledge at stake is of a particularly internalist sort, such that its p entails . In the n the traditional foundationalist account, such justification for believing p - q

is accessible by reflection alone. Here, the notion of justification on , flection you can not tell that you are not having such a non then Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

S internalist

know

minate the skeptic‘s error possibilities for which we know s

q. The skeptic uses the

kind; it is something that a subject 11 .

When you have a perceptual experience of fire, it

14 subject‘s view. And this is the aspect of

.

modus tollens

If

S

form of the closure would be able to

knows - p veridical ,

and don't

-

luck

-

CEU eTD Collection presuppositions of the skeptical argument. Apart from a ―direct‖ anti which premise of the argument is false, and an ―indirect‖ strategy that undermines premise of the skeptical arguments (if any) is false? arguments have some initial plausibility. However, the hard question to answer is which rendered merely lucky, from t impossible) to eliminate. In the face of such error illustrated by different skeptical scenarios that seem very far if you are sitting by the fire you cannot out that perceptual beliefs are contaminated by you are not. And knowledge should not be l question. You could be deceived by an evil god, as far as you know by reflection, but luckily exactly the same as in the skeptical scenarios, you can‘t rule out the error impossible. From what you can tell about how things seem to you, wh you have to eliminate the skeptical hypotheses. However, the skeptic argues that this is In order for your belief that you express by ―I‘m sitting by the fire‖ to be free from bad luck undermined by the bad epistemic luck that this possibility of oferror error obtains‖ since to(2005, leave pp. a possibility17). of error uneliminated is to leave one's belief open to being nicely formulates the point: Pritchard‘s view derived from the ―epistemic luck platitude‖ (2005, pp. 1 Plausibility of such application of the closure principle in the skeptical argument is in If knowledge is incompatible with luc

3. Therefore, I don‘t know that p deceived. I'm not that 2. Idon'tknow There are two kinds of anti The skeptical point that we could be mistaken about o

he subject‘s point of view. This explains why the skeptical - skeptical strategie . k, then it must also be incompatible with the possibility

know

eft ―open to chance‖. Hence, the skeptic points

that. reflective luck 15 - possibilities our perceptual beliefs are

s: a ―direct‖ response that addresses -

fetched, and yet hard (if not (Pritchard 2005, pp.10) ur ordinary perceptual beliefs is - skeptical response to ich is - et passim possibilities in ex hypothesi

). He -

even

CEU eTD Collection skeptical argument. skepticism which is based on Sosa‘s view, which undermines the first premise of the context of discussing disjunctivism. In chapter III I propose a ―direct‖ answer to dream assumption in the skeptical argument. In chapter II I discuss an ―indirect‖ approach hypothesis ―matches‖ genuine perceptual experience, which figures as an essential s going to discuss how different theories of perception lead to, or are vulnerable to Cartesian answer arguing that the first premise of the skeptical argument is false, in chapter II I am deceiver skepticism that I am g kepticism, and see how exactly the non

oing to address in chapter IV, in which I present a Cartesian - veridical experience in the skeptical deceiver 16

in the

CEU eTD Collection (E) solely the nature of the external world. (L) Propositions solely about the contents of the mind are logically independentworld relation:of propositions solely about 15 inevitable. For more on this view see Okasha‘s paper ―Skepticism and its Sources‖independently (2003). existing objects. Stroud, Davidson, and Williams think that if we14 grant this thesis, skepticism is 13 12 hypotheses. The indirect realist‘s gap between appearance and reality renders radical consequence of such a view is that perceptual beliefs are open to be undermined by skeptical screens of its pur beliefs because nothing about the content of our mind, the sensory ―directly given‖ which perception, i.e. from how things appear beliefs about the world on the basi knowledge is at best inferential (―sense ideas‖ or ―sense datum‖) rather than physical objects indirect realism McDowell (1982), the main figure of the ―traditionalist‖, stresses that a consequence of disastrous, break with scholastic tradition of direct realism‖ (1980, 49 note, 45 convinced that ―Descartes doctrine of representative perception was by and presents a threat only for certain views of perception. For example, R. Rorty was the skeptical problem, thought that skepticism concerning perceptual knowledge is enabled Putnam, McDowell, and recently Huemer of perception, and epistemology in general, for good or bad. Many philosophers it is expected

This inference is usually minimally conscious, and automatic.I take this term from D. Macarthur (2003). A similar view is often formulated as the problem of ―epistemic priority‖ of sensory experi Ludwig says that radical skepticism about Our main source of ordinary knowledge about the external world is perception. Thus C ARTESIAN SKEPTICISM AND NATURE OFPERCEPTION THE

that a theory of perception that one endorses has consequences on epistemology about the contents of our minds are all our evidence for facts about the external world. - ported object, entails true propositions about the external world

the view that in perception we are

13

and defeasible. From this view it follows that we form s of inference from what is directly given to us in

the external world is founded on two assumptions about the mind 14 C . But there can be no certainty in such perceptual HAPTER -

who gave shape to the ―traditional‖ 17

directly aware of ―mere‖ appearances

II

-

is that our perceptual

a sharp and perhaps

ence over – 12 51). 15 -

criticism . A Ayer,

of

-

CEU eTD Collection 17 aware of appearances (the so called ‗veil o will keep our focus on what is common to both views, namely, the thesis that inideali perception we are directly example, Foster and Robinson deny the existence of physical world, and they are known16 as a transition from sheer fallibility…to a ‗veil of ideas‘ skepticism possibilities. McDowell says that ―the argument [from illusion and hallucination] effects a appearances‖, and our perceptual beliefs can always be undermined by the skeptical error access is not directly putting us in touch with reality, we are placed behind the ―veil perceptual access to external reality. However, such a solution has a high price. If perceptual perception‖ way of directly accessing external reality? Their answer to this so called ―problem of we see them, the puzzling question is how perception can be what it intuitively seems to be, a address them here, linking them directly with my main topic. arguments supporting such view are the arguments from illusion and hallucination. Let me object which (at best Robinson (1994) ―mere‖ appearances theories of perception and skepticism. of perception lead to skepticism, in this chapter I need to explore the relation between know that we ar may be responsible for our experience. Then, the difficult question to answer is how do we impressions‖, or we could be having dreams as of the external world. A quite different cause experience, we could be deceive skepticism about perceptual knowledge a live option: as far as we can tell on the basis of our

Crane‘s term is made explicit Some sense sts

about perception. The difference between indirect realism and idealism is metaphysical. However, we Given the phenomena of illusions in which we According to one theory that primarily st - 17 datum theorists are

is: perception e not victims of such skeptical scenarios? Since it seems that certain theories -

in perception we are directly aware of a sense datum, a mind 16 -

) mediates o sense datum theory defended by Price (1932), Foster (2000), and ―The Problem of Perception‖ (

is indirect realists not

d by an evil deceiver who nourishes us with ―false

what it intuitively seems to be because we don‘t have direct ur perceptual awareness of the physical world. The main f perception‘).

, they hold that perception is mediated by sense 18 resses our directs perceptual awareness of

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

are aware of things that are not the way

‖ (1982, pp. 472). According phenomenalists - - dependent data. For , 2005).

of

- or

CEU eTD Collection illusion and hallucination, and skeptic 18 it is natural to think that certai lead to skepticism (or are at least vulnerable to it). If a certain theory leads to skepticism, then a chance to evade skepticism. friendly‖ arguments. Perception puts us in a direct contact with reality. Consequently, there is McDowell, Snowdon, Martin, and Neta, which also denies successfulness of the ―skeptic also discuss d soundness of the argument from illusion, and promises to lift the corresponding ―veil‖. I will doctrine, the direct object of perception is the physical object itself. Crane denies the the argument from illusion and hallucinat Armstrong, Dretske, Tye, Crane and others, as a view opposed to sense with physical reality. I will consider intentionalism, the view defended by Anscombe, or even defending so vulnerable to skeptical attack(s). Both of these views present themselves as compatible with two of its rivals perception‖, and have traditionally inspired the sense in making certain pre hallucination inevitably lead to skepticism. Thus, I need to discuss their plausibili to Ayer, Putnam, McDowell, Bennett, and many others

Here is how David Macarthur (2003, pp. 177) presents the logical connection between the arguments from In this chapter I shall assess how the above mentioned three theories of perception Apart from the arguments from illusion and hallucination that create the‖veil of (iv) Therefore, in experiencing an object one is directly aware of a sensory isof directly ide object one experiencingan aware in Therefore, (iv) m we indistinguishability phenomenal such explain to order In (iii) (ii)In dreaming or hallucinatingan object one is not aware of a real or existent object. experience Any (i) isjunctivism about perception, a prominent view defended by Hinton, -

which forms a defeasible basis for judging that there is an object there. or dreaming and object an hallucinatingperceiving to the samecommon in thing. Callsomething thisof sensoryaware idea of anperceptually object. hallucinating that object. disjunctivism and intentionalism - - called direct realism, the view that perce conditions for Cartesian skepticism to arise.

n assumptions in these theories enable the problem to arise.

of an object may be phenomenally indistinguishable from dreaming or or dreaming from indistinguishable phenomenally be may object an of - friendly indirect realism:

ion. According to Tim Crane‘s (2001) version of the 19

-

and inquire whether these views are

- datum theory, I am going to discu 18 , the arguments from illusion and ption puts us in a direct contact

- datum theory and to ust suppose that one is is one that suppose ust

a of that object, a of ty and role

ss

CEU eTD Collection make the most plausible defense of the argument, which is divided in two parts: (to me at least) seem plausible. My approach will be pro 2005) reconstruction of the argument from illusion, and attempt to offer interpr the forth section is devoted to disjunctivism and its anti datum theory. The third section discusses intentionalism and its relation to skepticism, and of (mere) app which is an assumption presupposed in the skeptical arguments. the expe of perception are susceptible to skepticism, and (ii) what is the ―matching‖ relation between which are going to be in our focus throughout the present chapter: (i) how different theories hallucination which carries such claim versions. This point will be especially important in connection with the argument from carrying with them different degrees of logical strength, from more to less committing exactly matches skeptical arguments, namely, the point that that sensory experience in the skeptical scenario senses, and it will aim to estimate how compelling they are. The presupposition of the assumptions about the nature of perception that enable Cartesian s Thus, my inquiry on theories of perception will help to diagnose if there are essential 2.1. Arguments That We Are Aware Of (Mere) Appearances: The Argument Argument The Appearances: (Mere) Of We AreAware That 2.1. Arguments In this section I discuss and analyze Howard Robinson‘s (1994) and Tim Crane‘s (2001, The first two major sections discuss arguments to the effect that we are directly aware rience in the ―bad‖ case (skeptical scenario or in hallucination) and the ―good‖ case, earances: the argument from illusion

genuine perception, is going to b as a premise. In short, there are two important issues From Illusion 20 e considered in various formulations

and hallucination, and the attendant sense - skeptical strategy. - skeptical in method; I will try to

kepticism concerning

etations that

-

CEU eTD Collection illusion‖. Let me start with the following ―simple‖ version of the argument from illusion: other cases of illusions figure moon near the horizon looks larger than when the same object is high on the sky. Such and is‖. For example, a white wall appears red under red lights, or in the ―moon illusion‖ the object is actually perceived, but in which that object per A. D. Smith (2002, pp. 23) defines illusion as ―any perceptual situation in which a physical 3. If I‘m appeared to something el 2. The coin is really round. 1. A coin appears to be elliptical. (ii) (i) 8. 7. 6. If x has Fness and y does not have Fness then x is not identical to y. ( 5. The object of my awareness is elliptical and the coin is not elliptical. 4. If I‘m directly aware of something having ellipticalness then there

LL) something which I‘m directly aware that has the property of being elliptical, i.e. there elipticalness. I‘m directly aware of a non The coin is not identical to the object of my direct awareness. From (5) and (6) also aware of appearances. ―Generalized‖ version appearances. ―Simple‖ version

that instantiates this property. (Instance of the

– as a good starting point for the so called ―argument from

concluding that in cases of illusions we are aware of

concluding t - physical object

liptical then I am directly aware of something having

21 hat in cases of veridical perception we are

-

a sense ceptually appears other than it really - datum. Phenomenal Principle

is Lebniz’s law,

something of

is

, PP)

CEU eTD Collection are of different kinds, is of the same kind. But elipticalness is just apparent and roundness is real. These properties that that there is real elipticalness, rather than possesses this quality; there is some x which has F. But why would we be compelled to think fourth premises) further extrapolates an ontological claim that there that one is not directly aware of the coin. cannot have incompatible properties of the same kind (roundness and elipticalness), it follows there Thus, (2004b, pp. 30) reflection on one‘s o one, and that one can test just by reflection on how things do appearit is to true one. or Hence, not. Butsimple the proposition in question concerns appearances,all one has howto go things on is appearreflection to on the proposit While the principle is not self of the principle in the following way: which does possess that sensib possesses a particular sensible quality then there is something of which the subject is aware principle brownness‖ (1932, pp. 63). H. Robinson gives a n appears brown to me‘ it is quite plain that I am acquainted with an actual instance of and many found controversial. For example, H.H. Price says that ―When I say ‗this table crux of the argument is the 3 ordinary object, as we would naturally though of to be (on the basis of how things seem). The

x has Fness and y doesn’t have Fness then x is not identical to y is

if the coin appears to be elliptical and the PP is true, then

The first premise states that a coin The conclusion of the argument is that in cases of illusions we are not aware of an something elliptical which makes the application of LL legit

(PP) states that ―If there sensibly appears to a subject to be something which

wn case should show one whether the principle in question is true. and are compatible with each other. rd -

and 4 evident, it is nonetheless le quality‖ th

premise, which many ph

illusionary (1994, pp. 32). M. G. F. Martin explains plausibility

appears to be 22 ion itself, then one cannot determine whether ame to such intuition. His

elipti

evident in the light of experience elliptical calness? One might further object

ilosophers took as obvious, seems elliptical , and the PP (the third and

holds only if property F is imate. Since the coin

something real that phenomenal

implies that

. If

CEU eTD Collection certain constraints on my experience. Namely, I cannot see it as being elephant table about it is not constrained in any way by how the table is at this moment. I could think of a the creator of the imagined scene. Take for example a thought about the table. My thought the experience, whereas in the case called ―order of experienced determination‖; in perception it seems that the object determines degree. whereas in case of thinking, I voluntarily control what I am go before my mind doesn‘t seem to be ―there‖ as if it were voluntarily brought up by my mind, the experience itself‖ (Robinson 1994, experientially as it is because of the apparent presence of the empirical features of things in 165). However, in sensory experience, objects have a different role: ―Perception is of the presence of the object, but in the manner of subject‘s re perceptual experience. The nature of emotions ―do not consist in any difference in the manner differences between perceptual experience and other intentional states. Emotions differ from touch‖ only with what is given at the present moment. Robinson argues that there are ―giveness‖ to the senses objects of per experience. I will compare Robinson‘s sense are given to the perceiver is. This leads us to two further deeper questions about the nature of perception: how objects

as being covered with flowers. On the contrary, how the table is now when I see it puts The difference between perception and thought (or imagination) is also in the so Furthermore, objects seem to be mind A component of our ordinary conception of perceptual experience is the intuition that Since the PP is essential for the argument, we need to see how plausible the principle

ception appear to be ―there‖. This is so called ―presence to the mind‖ or -

, and what can be concluded from the phenomenology of perceptual objects seem to be present.

of thinking it seems that I determine the object, e.g. I am

pp. 166). - - datum theory and Crane‘s intentionalism. independent. The red patch which appears to be 23

Unlike thought, perception puts us ―in sponse to the object‖ (1994, pp. ing to think, at least to a - shape

-

like.

CEU eTD Collection However, the PP implies infallibility of direct perceptual awareness, whenever one is phenomenal principle. For example, if by the real presence of its objects, whereas thinking is not. This view is encapsulated by the e should be a difference in their natures. According to the sense phenomenological differences between thinking and perceiving, it is expected that there question nature experiences from other intentional states. and immediacy. These phenomenal and presentational features disting to the mind, mind because nothing seems to be an epistemic mediator between my mind and the o ordinary conception of perception. E.g., ellipticalness seems to be directly before my mind, argume the experience and seem to determine the nature of experience. The 3 thinking about it. This vividness is derived from the fact that objects appear to be presented in immediacy. The table that I se datum theory, is explained by the fact that there experience. The feeling that I‘m not the auth perceptual experience itself the apparent presence of objects to the mind seems to ―shape‖ our appears now. So how what explains this difference between perception and thought? Within My perception intuitively seems to be an immediate response to ho xplanation of such differences is the following: perceptual experience is essentially tailored

of perceptual experience, which brings us closer to the importance of the PP. The So far, I have discussed the apparent features of objects, but now I am interested in the Our ordinary conception of perception thus includes the following features: presence The last but not the least features of perceptual experience are vividness and nt accounts for the is what is essential for perceptual experience? Since there are significant - independency, the specific order of experienced determination, vividness immediacy e is more vividly present to my mind than in my imagining or

of perceptual experiences, which is also a part of our something appears to be

or of the perceived scene, according to sense 24 is

an object that determines the experience.

- datum view, the best F then w the object, table, rd

uish perceptual there is something F

premise of the bject.

.

CEU eTD Collection phenomenal are two don‘t fully individuate the mental state. You may imagine Budapest or remember it. These of a state, we thereby inevitably in states the intentional object is presented from a certain aspect. When we specify the content and about Budapest. Similarly, we always think or perceive something i how impressing the Hero‘s Square is. These are two aspects under which you may think about Budapest you can think how good bean soup they have there, or you may think about sense. own. They are not substantial things like sense data, they are real merely in a schematic unicorns). Ac objects can be real objects (e.g. people, sun, trees), but sometimes they don‘t really exist (e.g. Intentional states thus exhibit directedness in virtue of having intentional objects. Such say that we usually perceive something to be the Thoughts are always about something, even when they don‘t reach to real things. And we can The objects of thoughts are known as ‗things‘ It is natural to say that a thought about Pegasus and a thought about Zeus are about different focus on Crane‘s (2001) version of intentionalism, let me start with his observation: others present the position in more detail. implication? Intentionalists straigh appeared to x and thereby aware of x, then one is aware of x as it is. How plausible is that - such. Insofar a mental state has aspectual shape, it has intentional content. In intentional -

Another feature of intentionality is The intentionalists

intentional modes claim that thoughts and perceptual experiences exhibit intentional

Pegasus and Zeus, respectively

character of a mental state, like perception or pain, is thus exhausted both by its cording to Crane (2001, pp. 16) intentional objects don‘t have a nature of their ; they are ways by which you relate to intentional content. The -

Armstrong, Anscombe, Dretske, Peacocke, Harman, Crane, and dividuate its object, but by giving the content of a state we tforwardly deny the principle. Let me use this chance to

intentional objects – aspectual shape

or alter 25

case (e.g. I see people walking on the street).

natively that they have different ‗objects‘. . (2004) . For example, when

n some way, or ity. Since I will

you think as

such

-

CEU eTD Collection conception of it. If perceptual experience is like thought, an intentional state which is not about the nature of perceptual experience and about theoretically interpreting our ordinary intentionalist is merely about premises in the a premise of the argument. T case of illusion, the property of being elliptical can be regarded as a non something non are simply misrepre is something say that the coin appears to be elliptical, but he would deny the temptation to infer that there although in certain circumstances it may appear differe our main debate. The Crane ties the relational structure of perceptual experience to its content rather than object. intentional state is that it has an intentional structure: subject intentional state that it has an existi intentional state, a relation to intentional content…it is not essential to something‘sWe should being andeny that perception is a relation to real object. Rather, perception is an explains the intentionality of perc (Crane, 2001, pp.32). Similarly, perception always has content, rather than object. Crane hallucinations, don‘t have real objects (but merely intentional ones), the content must exist intentional structure. content and mode. ‖What is it like‖ to be in a mental state is explained in terms of such an

hus, the intentionalist blocks the argument from illusion by denying the PP, the 3 refore, the PP finds no place in the intentionalist theory. This being said, we may return to Although it might have seemed that the debate between the sense Intentionalists would typically argue that we are directly aware of a physical coin Although some mental states like thinking a really - existent, we can also have an experience of something non

elliptical. Elipticalness is an aspect of the misrepresented coin; illusions sentations. As Anscombe once pointed out, just as we can think of

eption in the following way: ng object. What is essential to something‘s being an rgument, the disagreement is much deeper, it is 26

bout unicorns, phantom pain or ntly than it actually is. Crane would - mode

- content. (2001, pp. 137) - existent property. - datum theorist and - existent. In the rd

and 4

th

CEU eTD Collection Philosophy more on this issue see ―Crane on intentionality and consciousness:content whereas A few perceptionsquest have and perceiving can be explained in terms o 19 would certainly be contrary to it. perception has to acco object determines the character of the experience because it actually are our ordinary conception of perceptual experien explanation seems to be the best because it is the most intuitive one, namely, it saves much of and vividness, are best explained by the real presence of objects is perception. Such experience has a real object. Presence to the mind, the order of expe experience is seems to be a more intuitive explanation of the apparent relation because perceptual perceptual experience is a relation to a real object. From this vantage the sense them differently, and our ordinary conception of perceptual experience suggests that presentational diff not clear what explains their phenomenological differences thinking and perceiving. If perceiving is essentially like thought, an intentional state, then it is that intentionalism fails to adequately there is something missing in the explanation. relation to a real o the PP is true? Why should one insist that perception is bound for its real object, but rather to its content, then why should one insist on the claim that

For example, in the

present, experience is vivid because objects are present to the mind, and it seems that the

Sense 4.11 (2004): 219

- a relation. Since relation entails the existence of datum theorists, Robinson in particular, take such a line of argument, insisting bject? The burden of proof is on the intentionalist‘s opponent to show that erences between those states make plausible the idea that we should treat Elements of Mind mmodate for the common sense views, and denying reality of objects - 222. non

- conceptual (2001)

f the difference in their kind of content. Thoughts have propositional

explain the difference in the phenomenology of

Crane argues that the phenomenal difference between thinking

content. However, this view has some questions open. For ce. Objects

27

unlike seem 19 . Phenomenological and

relata thought, constituted by a

to be present because they ions.― , then every perceptual does rienced determination, Croatian Journal of . Any view of - datum theory

CEU eTD Collection somewhere. Crane obser objects, but the phenomena of illusion and hallucination force us to make a compromise theory has to sacrifice some of its plausibility because it denies mind more problematic position. Here is sense independent. Then, arguing from common sense doesn‘t end up in contradicting it. But, the independent sense data explains our common sense intu sense data are mind datum theory be reconciled in a coherent way? The sense show that common sense is misleading. How can the motivation and out there seems to be something problematic about arguing from the common sense in order to objects appear to be mind object. The outcome is that ―taking appearances at face value‖ is misleading in this case illusion appeals to the PP in order to show that we are value‖. But, accounts for the presence of objects. The motto seems to be to ―take appearance at face point, and raise a potential difficulty concerning what sense data are for Rob illusion then seems to conflict the initial motivation for the PP. Let me say more about this with how conception. Crucially, sense - datum theorist like Robinson who argues that sense data are mind The PP accounts for the intuition that we can see only what is actually ―there‖ However, the sense

objects of perception are presented to us. The conclusion of the argument from

on the other hand, the theory contradicts common sense. The argument from 2.1.1. A Few Thoughts OnRobinson’s Sense Datum Theory - in dependent (Moore) may be in a better position. The existence of mind ves that: - independent although they are not mind - datum theory won‘t give justice to all features of the ordinary - datum theory denies mind

how the objection can be addressed. The sense 28

not - dependence, which actually conflicts ition that objects appear to be mind

- aware of a mind datum theorist who argues that - independent. But then, - independence of - come of the sense de - independent pendent is in a inson. - datum

-

: the it

-

-

-

CEU eTD Collection existent object, and yet the conscious episode is real in a psychological sense. Even though example a perception shape. And this bundle of properties constitutes a real object of which we are aware of in Usually, sensible qualities come ac In Robinson‘s view, sensible qualities are qualities of a sense datum or a mental image. conditions (1994, pp. 1, 2): sense data have in Robinso say. the question is which theory of perception can ―save phenomena‖ at the lowest price, so to (McDowell, Martin).The puzzle of perceptual experien between perception and thought (Robinson), and preserving ―openness to the world‖ On the other hand, the intentionalists are charged of inadequately explaining the difference defended against the arguments from illusion and hallucina and illusion, and try instead to see how much of our conceptionThe of dominantperception approaches can be to the problem of perception accept the possibility of hallucination

2. They are non 1. Sense data are what we are aware of. 5. They posses no intrinsic intentionality; their sensory qualities do not refer beyond 4. They possess sensible qualitie 3. They are logically private occurrences to a single subject.

Now I want to pass to a different difficulty, which concerns the question of what role themselves. thought about a non -

the sense datum. However, sense data also seem to play a different role. Take for -

physical. n‘s theory. According to Robinson, sense data meet five

-

existent, a unicorn. This thought is a thought about a non companied with other qualities, e.g. color comes with s (shape, color, etc.)

29

ce does not have an easy solution, and

tion (Crane, 2005).

-

CEU eTD Collection psychological vehicle of a H and veridical perception too. That is why the above quotation suggests that there is a common analysis suggests that the same vehicle must be responsible for the psychological reality of that in the case of hallucination sense datum is the psycho psychological kind then the same kind of thing explains their psychological reality. Given kind of experience without being aware of a real object. Now, if H and VPs are of the same sensory experience and there is a real object that we see, but in case of a H, we have belong to the same psychological type, or a kind of experiences. In case of a VP we have a According to cases is also present in veridical cases. What is the argument for that claim? The passage seems to suggest that the same psychological vehicle present in hallucinatory is phenomenally logical object of thought. (1994, pp. 166). The psychologicallythe real psychologically vehicle of the real mental vehicle act of thought … the element common to real perception a psychologically real. Robinson says that: experience is psychologically real. So, something has to explain in virtue of what H is experiences. thinking. Sense data, in Robinson‘s view play a role of psychological vehicles of perceptual performs the thinking. Thus, psychological vehicles are means by which we are doing the i.e. by a mental image of a unicorn, or an episo psychological reality of a thought about a unicorn is explained by its psychological vehicle, psychological reality of such a thought needs to be explained. In Robinson‘s view, the the thought is about a non

In cases of

the so called realized object, and not a distinct vehicle at all.(1994, pp. 167)

hallucinations (H), one is not seeing anything real, and yet, a hallucinatory - common factor analysis existent, an episode of thinking certainly is n

VP, a phenomenally realized object

- the words one says in one‘s heart nd veridical hallucination de of inner speech, by which one actually 30

which Robinson endorses, Hs and VPs logical vehicle, the common factor - –

sense datum. seems more similar to ot non -

than like the - existent. The

the same

CEU eTD Collection proceed from the ―s aware of physical objects in cases of illusions, but also in veridical cases. Let me now ambition to generalize the argument, which is purported to show that we are not directly illusions we are directly aware of a s of our ordinary conception of perception, you may be inclined to believe that in the cases of sense phenomenal principle which plays an essential role in the argument appropriately account for the required distinction between psychological vehicles and objects. vehicles, and leads into a serious problem. The question is then how can Ro psychological vehicles of VP and H blurs the distinction between objects and psychological tree is not identical to the tree out there, that I‘m aware of. Treating sense data as having a certain appearance or mental representation of the tree. But the appearance of the existent object is distinct from the object of thought. Similarly, when I see a tree I see it by think about the physical tree. itself, although when I actually think about it I entertain a mental image of a tree by which I Suppose that I think about a tree in front of my house. The object of my thinking is the tree object problematic, as Huemer (2001, pp. 85) points out. If one would identify sense data with the 3. Therefore, we are aware of the means 2. We are perceiving by means of having sense data (psychological vehicle). 1. In perception, we are aware of sense data (object). - datum theory. If you find convincing the view which preserves a lot (but not the whole) and In the previous section I have discussed the motivation and difficulties for the However, I think that conflating objects of perceptions with psychological vehicles is

the

psychological vehicle, the result would be the following implausible argument: imple‖ to the ―generalized‖ version of the argument from illusion. Clearly, means by which I am doing the thinking in case of an ense datum. However, the sense

by which we are perceiving. 31

from illusion, and the - datum theorist has an

binson

CEU eTD Collection 20 we have to see in order to Seeing veridically gradually changes into seeing very blurry, and we cannot tell how blurry short sighted, and hence we cannot tell when seeing a bit blurry starts to be an illusion. that there is no ― distinction‖ for example b grounded on two considerations: we perceive them in veri sense datum. The sense is mediated by a causal process which includes stimulation argument from illusion shows that that is an illusion. Apart from being metaphysically aware of the moon by being aware of the ―image‖ of moon. At least, this is how it seems. The

Here is Robinson‘s original formulation: epistemically mediated Robinson (1994 pp.57, 58) (ii) (i) 7. 6. There is such 5. 4. If a possesses a sensible qualitywhich b lacks, then a is 3. 2. Whenever something appears to a subject to possess a sensible quality, there is something of which the 1. In some cases of perception, physical objects appear other than they actually are

In perception it seems that nothing mediates our awareness of realit

subject is purportedly perceiving cases of veridical perception that the same analysis of perception must apply to both object the subject is purportedly perceiving sensible qualities which the physical object the subject is purportedly perceiving does not posses subject is aware which does possess the quality (the PP) possess sensible qualities that they do not actually posses Insome cases of perceptionthat ofwhich the subject isaware issomething other than the physical Insome cases of perceptionthere issomething ofwhich the subject isaware which possesses In all cases of perception that of which the subject is aware is other than the physical object the indistinguishability thesis (Crane) continuity thesis (Robinson) continuity 2.1.2. The ‘Generalized’ Argument From Illusion - datum theorist argues that if in illusions we perceive sense data, then dical perception as well. The argument for this transition can be : we are (at best) aware of physical objects by being aware of a

call it an illusion. The fact is that our vision almost never between those cases in which objects appear other than t

20

generalizes the argument by appeal to

32

etween seeing sharply and being slightly

not identical to b

of retina, brain state, etc., perception

continuity – hey actually are and that is, t y; we are not

. He says hey appear to

CEU eTD Collection Of course, this doesn‘t have to be true for every case of illusion. As Austin pointed out, to discriminate having an illusion from veridic This interpretation seems to amount to indistinguishability thesis, namely, that one is not able experience, between the phenomenology of perception and illusionThere (2005). is no non and one strategy for generalizing the argument. Now, let me consider an alternative way. both cases must be the same kind of thing both, illusions and veridical perceptions. In other words, Therefore, the continuity thesis makes plausible the view that the same analysis must apply to blurry there is no point where the object veridical perception is see a physical object while in case of illusion we see a sense datum. As the picture becomes Robinson argues, it is impl arbitrarily. Therefore, illusions and veridical cases should be analyzed in the same way. As logically possible to set a sharp distinction, but it is hard to see how that can be done non sharp distinction between veridically perceiving a and being bald. There is it‘s not possible to tell who is right because there is no sharp distinction between being hairy someone else may say ―No, loosing 110000 makes a man bald‖. Who is right? It se arbitrary answer can be given here. I can say that loosing 100000 hairs makes one bald, and hair i one by one, until he becomes bald. Now, we are asked at which point S became bald, which the continuity thesis consider the following analogy. Suppose that S looses hairs gradually, possibly detect. So it is hard to tell accurately presents things as they are. Physical surfaces are certainly finer than our eyes can

Crane interprets the continuity claim in the following way: s ―bald making‖? Does the question have a plausible answer? It seems that no non - arbitrary way of distinguishing, from the poin continuity ausible to claim that in the case of veridical perception we directly

what seeing between being hairy and being bald. Similarly, there is no . That is one int ally seeing, merely on the basis of reflection. absolutely 33

nd non erpretation of the continuity thesis the objects of direct awareness in

- sharply is at all. To further clarify veridically perceiving. It is t of view of the subject of an replaced

by a sense datu

ems that

m. -

-

CEU eTD Collection encompasses two discussed strategies: of direct awareness then neither it is in the case of VP. from illusion easily generalizes; since in cases of illusions the physical object is not the object kind of object of awareness explains their indisti and illusions are indistinguishable in virtue of their general features then postulating the same appeal to indistinguishability of these general features of perceptu immediacy, and giveness. So, perhaps the argument from illusion can be generalized by phenomenology of all VPs and illusions is indistinguishable with respect vividness, VP or not. When I see an elliptical thing, I cannot tell whether it is a VP or no and seeing the elliptical thing strikes me in the same way, from the point of view of being a When I see a rou differ qualitatively, but experiences are indistinguishable in virtue of their general features. object‘s qualitative aspect. E.g. apparent elipticalness of a coin and its ―real‖ ellipticalness interpretation, illusions may be after all disting but rather to general phenomenological features of the experience. According to this indistinguishability might not apply to qualitative properties presented in VPs and illusions, qualitative features. However, there is another way of interpreting C elliptical. So, it is not true that for every illusion there is an object of VP which has the same Similarly, seeing a bent stick in the water is different from seeing a straight stick which appears bent. 1. In some actual cases of perceptions Consider the following reconstruction of the gene The argument from illusion can proceed in the following way. One can argue that if VP they actually are; they appear to be F although they are not really F.

seeing an elliptical coin is different from seeing a round coin which only appears nd coin it strikes me as the coin is actually immediately present to my mind,

physical uishable from VPs with respect to their 34 nguishability relation. Then the argument

objects appear differently from the way ralized argument from illusion which

al experiences. rane‘s thesis. The

t. Thus, the

CEU eTD Collection that it doesn‘t follow that their direct objects are of the same kind. One might accept (8), and one can consistently accept th possible that different kinds of object give raise to equally vivid appearances? It seems that possible that a hologram of a cat is subjectively indistinguishable from a real cat? Isn‘t it I think that (8) and (8*) and (9*) are plausible premises. But, 9. If general phenomenological features of illusions and VP are subjectively 8. General phenomenological features of illusions and VP are 7. In some cases of perceptions I‘m directly aware of a sense datum. 6. 5. 4. 3. 2. 11. 10. If x has Fness and y doesn‘t have Fness then x is not identic I If an object appears to be F then I am directly aware of something having Fness.

f I am directly aware of something having Fness indistinguishable, then in both cases their direct objects are of the same kind , or 9*: if where things appear other than they actually are. indistinguishable the physical object. Fness while the physical object doesn‘t posses Fness. directly aware of which has Fness. (the (8*), (9* ). than they actually are, then their direct objects are of the same kind. there is a continuity between VPs and cases of perception where things appear other

In some cases of perceptions I‘m directly aware of something which possesses

In all cases of perceptions I‘m directly aware of a sense datum. From (7), (10). In both cases I‘m directly aware of the same kind of direct object. From (8), (9) or In some cases of perceptions the object of my direct awareness is not identical to

, or 8*: there is a

e ―subjective indistinguishability of appearances‖ and maintain continuity PP) 35

betwee

then

n VPs and cases of perception

there (9) is controversial. Isn‘t it al to y. is subjectively

something which I am

(Leibniz’s law)

CEU eTD Collection least in general, for hallucinations as they actually occur. (2008,indistinguishable pp. 1) to the subject from the correspondin by the usual external objects. This would give, it is supposed,were a hallucinationstimulated in the just the way it is stimulated in genuinethey perception, are, it isbut argued, directly the andhallucinations not that would occur ifhallucinations‖. the percep These are not, as far as we know, hallucinationsPhilosophers as they actuallyare (mainly, occur, at butleast) interested in what I shall call ―philosophers‘ ―philosophers‘ hallucinations‖ perception, it suffices to take into account such possible hallucinations. Robinson calls them exactly like veridical perception. Since my main interest here are necessary features of hallucinations, but also conditions. However, I am interested in phenomenology of not merely actual states of are usually induced by drugs, alcohol, or abnormal neurological and psychological see something although there is no physical object being present to vi mere appearances or sense data same conclusion as the argument from illusion For now I proceed with the argument from hallucination, which is purported to support the the argument from hallucination because that objecti object. I will discuss this objection in more detail when I consider the generalized version of sensible properties, but maintain that while having a VP the objects of awareness is a physical accept that in cases of illusion we see a sense datum, since nothing physical instant

In all cases of hallucinations one has a kind of a perceptual experience; one 2.2. Arguments That We Are Aware Of (Mere) Appearances: The possible : .

hallucinations which are

Argument From Hallucination 36 -

in all cases of VP we are directly aware of

on tends to undermine both arguments. g perception, which is not the case, at

for the subject phenomenologically sual senses. Such states tual system and brain

iates

seems

to

CEU eTD Collection genuine perception, it is possible to produce the same phenomenological state skeptic‘sby a different methodology cause. is justified. However, there are empirical considerationsperception suggesting is quitethat fordifferent every than case ofhallucination under the influence of drugs 21 D. Smith points out the following: In order to be appeared by redness one has to be directly ‖in co Here is a formulation of the first part of the argument: we are directly aware of a sense datum, (2) in VP we are directly aware of a sense datum. is generalized through a thought experiment. The argument proceeds in two steps: (1) in H is why I will discuss this topic in great detail. of formulating the ―matching‖ relation between the veridical and n deceiver world, where our perceptual beliefs are false. Both arguments converge at the point possibility that we have phenomenally exactly the same, yet non from hallucination directly to the skeptical hypothesis in which we are asked to conceive a one that you could hallucinate Suppose that you have a visual experience of fire burning in the fireplace. What does it mean

Now, a skeptical reader may wonder how do we know that such hallucinations are possible? After all, genuine -

phenomenologically I propose an argument from hallucination based on the phenomenal principle, which 4. 3. There is no physical object (no patch) which is red. 2. If I‘m appeared by something red, the 1. While having a hallucination I‘m appeared to something red.

which instantiates redness. which instantiates redness (an instance of the PP). When hallucinating I‘m directly aware of a non it? It means that you could have an experience just like the present -

without there being a fireplace

37 n there

is 21

a direct object of my awareness . This point ties the argument . So, the question is whether the -

ntact‖ with something red. A. physical object (sense datum) -

veridical experience in the on - veridical case. And this

CEU eTD Collection does cases of VP, and denies it in the case of hallucinations, has to give reasons why the principle formulation of the PP includes hallucinations too. I think that someone who affirms the PP in In hallucinations something certainly appears quality.‖ (1994, p. 32) quality then there is something of which the subject is aware Ifwhich the does possess that sensible both, to H and VP. Robinson confirms this point: phenomenologically, then the PP naturally generalizes with genuine perception. Once one grants that hallucinations and VPs are alike explanatory relation should hold for hallucinations which share – application of the PP in cases of hallucinat Since much about it has been said in the section about illusions, I will elaborate more on the sense datum. However, this is not to say that the PP is based on grammatical considerations. direct object of my awareness which instantiates redness must be a non Since properties must be instantiated, and there is nothing red ―outside‖, it follows that the If nothin pp. 224 other than that the subject is, as the Argument requires, awarecognizance of a non of, indeed fully attend to, sensory presentations. Butattentive if so, whatand focused, else can wewe need say to do justice to the fact situation need to be accounted for… If we take as our example understanding‘,subjects who are butfully can there be an illusion of awareness?... thereThe sensory really features be such ofa thingthe as mock sensory awareness? Perhapssituation there c dramatically. Perhaps we can make sense of there beingTo ‗mocksay simply thoughts‘, that ourbut subject can is not aware of anything is surely to under

its presence, order of experienced determination, vividness and immediacy not re sensibly appears to a subject to be something which possesses a particular sensible - If the PP is justified as a principle that accounts for the phenomenology of perception 5)

g red really strikes me perceptually then what explains the quality of the experience? apply.

ions. such 38

- and

that such subjects in some sense take - – such, and hence the original

they same analysis should apply to the same phenomenology - - normal object? (2002, physical object, a an be ‗an illusion of - describe this –

then the same

CEU eTD Collection plausible explanation is th what shared property Hs and VPs are subjectively indistinguishable? The most simple and something that both eggs share. Similarly, the question I want to raise now is in virtue of indistinguishable because they look very common. For example, a real Easter egg and a plastic egg might easily be subjectively seeing. Usually, things are subjectively indistinguishable in virtue of having something in (2008, pp.58) subject is not in a position to know by ‗introspection‘ alone Wethat may he isdefine not in the good case. Byrne and Logue define subjective indistinguishability as follows: (2008, pp. 182) am hallucinating because I regard the apparently presented scene amas hallucinatingphysically impossible. by being informe certainly be discriminated from perceptions in other ways. Ior might, ‗what for it isexample, like‘ tolearn have that the Iexperience, is obviously required,The since restriction hallucinations that such can discrimination should be solely on the subjectively indistinguishable from the appearance of real letters. A.D.Smith points out that: being presented with an appearance which is phenomenologically just like the real object philosopher‘s hallucination; it is conceivable that you hallucinate reading these letters by you are now veridically perceiving letters on a piece of paper. But you might be having a what subjective indisting is possible that hallucinations are subjectively indistinguishable from VPs positions involved in the debate. us throughout the next few sections in which I will introduce the background and conclusion that in cases of VP we are also aware of a sense datum. This topic will preoccupy In such a perfect hallucination, you wouldn‘t be able to te

Let me begin the second part of the argument from hallucination with the thesis that Now let me pass to the second part of the argument, toward generalizing the

a case

ŋ

to be subjectively indistinguishable from the good case iff, in uishability relation is, and why it has to be explained. For example, at appearances share their properties. For example, seeing a red

d of the fact by someone who knows; or I might infer that I

much alike. The ―egg looking property‖ is 39

ll that you are not veridically

basis of the experience itself,

, and let me discuss

main

ŋ , the

it

CEU eTD Collection appearances‖ are ―phenomenal properties‖ 22 positions involved in the debate. challenged in contemporary philosophy of perception, I will introduce the m possibility stated by the 1 nature neutral and non I will refer to ―(properties of) appearance‖ shared by H and VP because the term is theory proceed with the following formulatio appearance then it is possible that in both cases (properties of) appearances are the same. I aware of. If it is conceivable that H appearance is subjectively indistinguishable from V of its properties of appearance conceivable to be in a mental state which is subjectively indistinguishable from a VP in virtue indistinguishable experiences. Thus, let me make a more general point: for every VP, it is way, by introducing a ―common factor‖, it is possible to obtain a unified explanation of patch and hallucinating a red patch have something in common

By feature or ―property of appearances‖ I mean ―sensible qualities‖. I don‘t want to say that ―properties of of the real object (if any). The 2 2. If hallucinatory appearances are subjectively indistinguishable from veridical 1. There are hallucinatory appearances that are subjectively indistinguishable from appearance veridical appearances. - committing; it screens how the purported object appears, ―bracketing‖ the s then (properties of) appearances in both cases are the same. st

premise. Since such a view is in a great length discussed and 22

, although there is no physical

The thesis about “philosophers’ hallucinations” , i.e. properties of experience. n: nd

premise figures as the best explanation of the 40

object that one is directly –

a red looking property. This ain issues and

CEU eTD Collection key question is whether your experience has changed after the lemon is removed? The As Johnston nothing amiss. (2009, pp. 1) lemon, the because the lemon is not around seen. be to Yet visual cortex, for instance, firing are the in same pattern. After the removal, you see donot t was lemon the when in was it as states physical local same the minor removes some theyou, lemon,to whileunbeknownst preservingthat, suppose itsNow proximalovoid. and neuralyellow looks effects. it and Yourlemon, the brain is in Imagine that you are looking at an ordinary lemon in good light. Your vision is good example introduced by Bryan and Louge: objects are direct objects of perception and essentially constitute the experience. Consider an that H and VP share the common kind. Let me introduce the main theses of disjunctivism. Such view is seriously questioned by the disjunctivists who (for one reason or another) deny shared by an H and its corresponding VP which explains their subjective indistingu The so called ―common factor view‖ (or ―conjunctivism‖) posits a common factor, a kind mental episode which occurs in both cases. (2004b, ampp. merely 7) hallucinating one, there need not be a difference in differencethe in the world between a situation in which I am seeingnerves an orange are suitably and one artificiallyin which I stimulated. For such a view, samealthough kind thereof episode can be canall occurthe when I am merely having an hallucination,occurring when as when I am my veridically optic perceiving I shall call The Comm VP is explained in terms of their common kind. M. G. F. Martin says that: explained by something that things share in common. Similarly, indistinguishability of H and both belong to the same spec Disjunctivism Let me begin with an example. A tiger looks very much like a big cat because they

2.2.1. Considerations Based On The Subjective Indistinguishability (2004) says, you have undergone a ―subjectively seamless transition‖. Now, the - on Kind Assumption: that whatever kind of mental episode it is that is

a version of direct realism

ies Relation And The ‘Common Factor’ –

cats. Being alike or being indistinguishable is usually

say when I am seeing the orange as it is 41

-

is the vie

w according to which physical — we can all grant kind of experience or here: the neurons in your your in neurons the here:

— you notice ishability. : you see –

that

CEU eTD Collection forms of disjuctivism. conjunctivist position can be sufficiently weakened in order to be compatible with some and/or objects, appearances (Alston), introspectively detectable features (Neta) common factor can be individuated in terms of sameness of their contents (Robinson, Crane), there are v disjunctivism) is usually at best epistemic rather than metaphysical. However, nowadays from each other, from a certain vantage point. Thus, the common factor (in case of experience is VP or it is a H. they do have something in common, they both fall under a between H and VP are like similarities between a real tiger and a hologram of a tiger. Yet one between two kinds of tigers, e.g. between a B pp. 472). Or, to use Neta‘s (2008) example, the difference between H and VP is not like that the fact that such to McDowell ―[A]n appearance that such the real nature of those experiences. They reject the ―common kind assumption‖. According VP just su not change, to be essential for perception. On the other hand, the disjunctivists say that H and after the lemon is removed. They regard the subjective part, the internal component that did mental kind shared by H and VP, which essential for lemon change. By removing the lemon the object is changed, not the experience itself. What is object. The common factor theorists argues the contrary perception; there is a H of lemon. Your experience cannot be identified independently of its there‖ constitutes your lemon disjunctivist says ―yes‖, because the lemon is essential for the experience. The l bjectively seem to be the same experience, but this criterion is not telling us about arious ways in which the common factor view can be spelled out: for example the - and - perception is not the lemon itself, but the perceptual experience or the -

such is the case making itself perceptually manifest to someone‖ (1982,

They also share the epistemic fact that they are indistinguishable - perception. Once the lemon is removed, there is no lemon

figures as the common factor and remains the same - and - such is the case is either a mere 42 engal and Siberian one. Similarities

-

th disjunctive description e experience didn‘t essentially appearance or . And the emon ―out : either an

-

CEU eTD Collection knowledge. 23 B=C. From the transitivity of identity it further follows tha and she judges that they look the same. Therefore, from the above implication it follows that subjective indistinguishability). Then she is presented again with two blue cards, B and C, implies sameness of appearances and B, and she judges that they look the same. Thus, if sorites argument‖ (PSA). empirical consideration about subjective indistinguishability (1999, pp.130) presented an argument a indistinguishability to the common factor thesis, I will focus on only one argument. thereby indirectly undermine the skeptic‘s presuppo subjective indistinguishability implies that appearances in H and VP case are the same, and the skeptical hypotheses. On the other hand, the disjunctivists try to undermine the claim that that provides the skeptic a framework for formulating the ―matching‖ relation es formulation of the skeptical assumption. On the one hand there is the common factor view subjective ind in the skeptical hypothesis. The discussion concerning the question of how to explain individuates with theories of perception. The co

For example, McDowell and Williamson argue that the argument relies on an erroneous theoryof self The subject of the phenomenal sorit Although there are many arguments The debate about the common factor is important because it directly links skepticism

-

istinguishability then bears direct impact on the strength and plausibility of the the ―matching‖ relation between non 2.2.2. Countering the Phenomenal Sorites Argument

, then A=B (―=‖ denotes sameness of appearances, and ― mmon factor shared by an H and VP explains gainst conjunctivism which is partially based on 23 es experiment is presented with two blue cards, A

challenging the inference from subjective 43

- veridical and veridical sensory experience sition that there is a ―matching‖ relation. subjectively indistinguishability t A=C. However, when presented -

the so - called ―phenomenal

sential for -

or exactly

Putnam

-

CEU eTD Collection make the PSA argument directed against more versions of conjunctivism24 change gradually so that one can‘t notice the change. transitive; it is not the case that A Although A On the left side of the implication we are tracking subjective indistinguisha ¬(A (B (A subjective indistinguishability ( Here is the paradox: distinguishable then the appearance of A card is with A and C cards, she judges that they

Here one can substitute ―sameness of appearance‖ with ―sameness of objects‘‖ or ―sameness of content‖, to is

¬(subjective indistinguishability C) not

B) C)

transitive =

( B=C) B=C

¬ (A=C) (A=B) A=B

B and B

C, the relation of ―subjective indistinguishability‖ fails to be

) ã C. Consequently, sameness of appearances

sameness of appearances) don’t

look t 44 not

he same. But, If A and C are is identical to the appearance of C card. A=C ¬ (A=C).

Assuming that subjective transitive

.

24

In the experiment appearances

(=)

bility relation.

CEU eTD Collection brain I would have the same visual experience as I have when he induces it. Suppose that I the same perceptual experience that that every 5 seconds of my veridical perception an evil colleague induces my brain to have the point more clear. Suppose that I‘m giving a talk at the prospectus seminar. Now, suppose two appearances differ in potentially weaken the PSA argument as an objection. If we make mistakes when kinds matter of change gr disanalogy between phenomenal sorites case and Hs appear our judgments, or that our discriminative powers are not reliable indicators of how generally unreliable change gradually. Howe that our judgments about how things appear to are not infallible in cases where appearances (Crane). that subjective indistinguishability implies appearances. The PSA at least threatens some versions of conjunctivism, those that affirm Therefore, it cannot be true that subjective indistinguishability implies sameness of shows that indistinguishability is things appear, we end up with a paradox; A=C, and yet ¬( A=C). The phenomenal sorites indistinguishability implies sameness of appearance, and we trust our abilities to judge how kinds

of states, there is no common factor shared by H and VP. And t ances are, one would have to prove that we make mistakes There is also another answer available to the conjunctivists: there is a relevant Now, the question is how strong the PSA

degree. adually; the change in blue color is too small to be detectable. But such change is a of appearances

On the other hand, if the disjunctivist is right, then Hs and VPs are different . In order to show such a strong point, namely, that we shouldn‘t rely on degree ver, it doesn‘t show that our judgments about how things appear are -

hallucinatory and veridical one. L , that doesn‘t show that we would miss the difference between not

I would have anyway; if he were not controlling my a transitive relation, alt

sameness of objects (Robinson) or contents 45 - based objection really is? The PSA shows

- VPs. Appearances in the PSA example hough identity is transitive. et me give an example to make systematically hat difference might .

CEU eTD Collection distinguishable states. Then, objection the is that H imagined appearance thoughtin would is (―what du content same the case, experienced‖) that In etc. colorfulness vividness, in presented, imagination. Different modes normally make a difference in the phenomenology of the object hallucination there are two appea certainly as rich real perceptual won‘tbe the scene. worryThe the in is that argument from scene imaginary the moment, very this at you have that scene perceptual the imagine and appearances merely at first conceiving our in that possible it Isn‘t powerful? so be imagination our Can VP? from mention two more worries that are going to be address indistinguishability and sameness of appearances. Before presenting the argument let me potentially meet the objection raised by the PSA and close the gap between subjective common factor view. Thus I will present a thought experiment Although such an answer is respectable, my sympathies are more inclined toward the (2008, pp.138) by tiger with one small part of the hologram, and then continueof thisreplacements series of of replacements parts of one onefor parts of the other. We couldthen replace there onecould small be apart gradual of the If each of those two things [real tiger and holographic tiger] is composed of great many parts illustrate the point. possible not to notice a difference between two kinds of things, and he gives an example to experience changes, without me noticing any change? Neta argues that it is conceiv happening. My experience flows ―smoothly‖. Wouldn‘t it be really surprising that the 5 secon have a VP for 5 seconds, and then I have a hallucinatory experience for 5 seconds, then again

- one, and thereby make a gradual transition from the tiger to a hologram of the tiger. The firstThe question is how can one imagine a ds of a VP followed by 5 seconds of a H. And, yet I don‘t notice any changes

e to different modes of presentation should yield subjectively subjectively yield should presentation of modes different to e seem transition from one thing to the other thing by a temporal series

to be the same? For exa rances in different modes of presentation 46

perfect ed by the TE argument. mple, if you try to close your eyes

hallucination indistinguishable (TE) argument that can –

perception and

able and

kind

- of

CEU eTD Collection aspect of the experience, and is identical with how the purported object is presented, the object (if any). The content of experience, in the pr experience is about in the TE must not rely on the correctness of any existence assumption of epoche external world. In Husserl‘s (1931) terminology, the skeptic demands the so call sitting in front of you in a classroom, whereas there are really no people and no chairs in the appearance showing how the skeptical ―matching‖ relation can be defended. be sufficiently narrowedcan to meet th appearances of sameness the and indistinguishability subjective between gap the PSA. I want to show through a thought experiment argument from hallucination that the subjective from indistinguishabilityinference the to samenessThus, of appearancesdetail. is therebyfine a renderedspot questionable. to able not may we although the that something have may conceiving our in possible that appearances in the TE are indistinguishable although a hallucinatory appearance 1000 sides) and circle are indistinguishable although they are different figures. Similarly, it is yet they might objects differ how in their really For are. chiliagona example (a r not be phenomenally exactly the same as perceived appearance. Consequently, we have good easons to be skeptical of how the conceivability argument is supposed to work at all.

In the thought experiment (TE) you are asked to conceive a (hallucinatory) In what follows I will attempt to addres Another related worry is that two appearances may seem to be indistinguishable, and or ―bracketing‖, according to which phenomenological specification of what the which is indistinguishable from your present veridical experience of people 2.2.3. AThought Experiment Argument e three objections. This argument will also be important for 47 s the two worries, and the objection based on

veridical appearance lacks (or (or lacks appearance veridical esent usage, captures the phenomenal

ed method of

vice versa vice

figure with

),

CEU eTD Collection (‗ between impact on the Cartesian argument, by directly addressing how the ―matching‖ relation imagine an appearance which is your mind. Nothing ch veridical scene. But, to imagine a veridical scene is to keep the same apparent features before appearance which is indistinguishable from the V one you actually imagine your present the same as the veridical scene before yo detail or make the appearance slightly blurry. So, the H appearance that you imagine remains ―bracketed‖ in the first place. It is not the case that you have to visually imagine an extra tiny in the phenomenological description of a V appearance the existence of a p doesn‘t add, nor in any way change imagining the scene you are presently aware of, because peo imagine an appearance of people sitting in front of you, and add to it ―there are no physical alone. So, what appearance do you imagine? The condition of the imagined scene is to from a V one is an appeara ―bracketing‖ the existence of its object (if any). An H appearance which is indistinguishable Ä ‘ stands for ‗subjectively indistinguishable‘, and ‗=‘ stands for ‗identical‘) ple in front of me, no physical walls, no chairs, etc. ‖ However, this extra condition 3. The ‖no real people in front of you, no real chairs, etc.‖ condition makes no difference 2. To imagine an H appearance ( 1. To imagine an H appearance ( Let me present the TE reconstructed in the following form of an argument: to the imagined scene. real people in front of you, no real chairs, etc.‖) it could be a V one, as far as you can tell by reflection alone. H and V appearance is conceived in the skeptical scenario. anges. Therefore, imagining an H indistinguishable from VP is to nce which could be a V, as far as you can tell purely by reflection

exactly like Ä Ä

V appearance) is to imagine (a V appearance +‖no V ur consciousness. In imagining a hallucinatory appearance) is to imagine a H appearance such that

a veridical appearance. Thus, the TE bears direct 48

hysical object is

CEU eTD Collection 25 experience in the skeptical scenario. present how the skeptic can formulate the ―matching‖ relation of veridical and non narrowe appearance. Consequently, the identity claim (‗=‘) in the fourth step of the TE amounts to the Therefore, a V appearance is qualitatively (or of the same narrowest type) identical with H If there are two mental episodes condition ‖no real people in front of me‖. At t two stages. First, at t According to option a. imagining (V appearance +‖no real peop possible to obtain two interpretations of the TE, and two corresponding conclusions: term ―the same‖ is ambiguous here. Depending on interpreting the second step of the TE, it is from a V you imagine This argument shows that when you conceive an H appearance which is indistinguishable

I took this term from M. G. F. Martin. a. 5. 4. T

he narrowest type identity accessible features. hallucinatory and veridical one, which are exactly alike with respect to all reflectively indistinguishability and the sameness of appearance. appearance) st (or qualitative) type identity of H and V appearance. This would be one way to

In the TE (or in imagining) there is no distin To imagine an H appearance ( 1

you have a V appearance before your mind, and then at t

an H appearance which is

in the TE, then there are two appearances, H and V one.

25

of H and V: in the TE there are two appearances,

Ä

V appearance) is to imagine an H appearance (=V 2

you have imagined the required hallucination. 49 the same

ction between subjective

as a V appearance. However, the

le in front of me 2

you add the ”

) happens in - veridical

CEU eTD Collection modes of presentation must yield a difference on the phenomenal level. The answer is that in in the first place. Let me address these issues now. strength, and have impact on the three objections that motivated introducing the The two different interpretations of the TE give two conclusions that differ in logical from hallucination: difference is mode reality, V and H appearance are co the last Frege‘s relation between morning star and evening star. The first star visible in the morning is The relation between H and VP with respect to their purported object is somewhat similar to which must be the same in both cases the act of imagining both temporally and with respect to the purported object. Such object, does not affect the scene that is before your mind. Thus, the act of perceiving overlaps with one mental act. You imagine something that you actually see, bu According to option b., imagining (V appearance +‖no people in front of me‖) happens in The thought experiment argument establishes the following two premises of the argument b. 2. Therefore, appearances of H and 1. It is conceivable (possible) that H appearance is subjective indistinguishable from the Co

The latter interpretation (b) of the TE directly addresses the first worry star visible in the evening, and both aspects refer to the same thing. In the imagined (1) and ((5) from the TE). V appearance. - referentiality - individuated and remains unreflected in imagination.

: H and V appearance refer to the same purported object.

- referential; they share a purported object, while their , is taken under two modes: perceiving and imagining.

VP are co 50

- referential/narrowest

t what you add in imagining - type identical. From

-

that two TE argument

CEU eTD Collection interpretation (a) is much weaker than (b), and it would not be sufficiently strong for the is (at least) sufficiently narrowed to meet the three objections. However, the first sameness of appearances in cases of H the co indistinguishable and their appearances differ, then despite conceding the PSA objection and undetected. impossible that ther are either co However, the TE presents a special case for hallucinations. H and V appearances in the TE subjective indistinguishability of appearanc chilliagon counterexample. Both objections undermine a more general thesis, namely, that phenomenally diffe objection that imagination and perception (as two modes of presentation) would yield phenomenal level to the purported object presented in the perceptual mode. Hence, the your consciousness. In thi the condition ―there are no physical objects out of the mind‖ to the veridical scene present to physical objects out of the mind‖. Here, you don‘t need to make a ―mental‖ copy but just add such a strong claim. Instead, he asks you to imagine ―a exactly like the V one, perfectly vivid in every detail. However, the skeptic need not require appearance. In this case it would be hard to see how can you imagine an appearance with is objects out of my mind‖. This would imply that we have to imagine a ―mental copy‖ o appearance by imagining ―something the TE you need not imagine an H appearance subjectively indistinguishable from V unterexample with the chiliagon, the thesis that subjective indistinguishability implies The gap between subjective indistinguishability and sameness of appearance in th The version (a) and (b) also offer a solution for the problem raised by PSA and the

If there is no chance, in principle, that appearances are subjectively - referential or narrowest type identical. From this it follows that rent appearances can be answered. e is a difference in detail between appearance of H and VP which is s case, the imagination like - VP does not seem to be directly undermined.

V appearance, whereas there are no physical es doesn‘t imply sameness of appearances. 51 - mode does not make a difference on the

V appearance, whereas there are no it is absolutely

f the V

e TE

CEU eTD Collection 27 26 version (b). From this it follows that only the weak version (a) of the TE is legitimat that lacks a real object, but rather something physi H presupposes that the external object is constitutive of V appearance, as chemical structure of is H water but something you imagine that water is something else than H that water is H me inference from the type identity to object identity. Before I proceed with that argument, let VP of an H, properties of appea the real tiger, and yet those objects are different. Similarly, it may be argued that in the case different kinds of objects. For example, a holographic image of a tiger might look the same as still be room for the possibility that qualitatively identical app conclusion that H and V appearance are narrowest conclusion concerning sameness of

This kind of ―mixture‖ of disjunctivism and conjunctivism is actually defended by W.P. Alston. 2 I am very thankful to Howard Robinson for raising this objecti O is essential for water. Then, it is metaphysically impossible that the V appearance lacks 26 address an objection 3 . Thus, the conjunctivist (sense O, but not water itself. Similar cal objects. Consequently, the H that you imagine in the TE cannot be a V appearance Let me start with an example. If water is H

3 O, and from this it follows that you ca like 27

water. You can merely conceive that something looking like water

2.2.3.1. The Objection From Conceivability that concerns the conceivability argument. rance may be instantiated in a sense datum, but not in the case of

ly, my opponent can argue the following. The disjunctivist objects - datum theorist) needs to offer an argument for the in H and VP case. The (a) strategy gives the like 52 2

a V appearance without its real objects. O, let‘s say H 2

- O then it is not metaphysically possible type identical. But in this case there will on. nnot conceive that water is H

earances are instantiated in 3 O, you are not imagining

e, but not the strong

3 O. When

CEU eTD Collection entertain the possibility that the V appearance can be ―stripped‖ from its physical objects (if seems to be doing his job by demanding open would we need to consider the thought experiment argument in the first p actually true. But if enter the debate by already deciding the nature of perception then why the po VP have physical objects by employing philosophical reflection (TE), the disjunctivist rejects resembles Moore‘s dialectical situation. In the context in which we try to determine whether is that there is something probl this is not conceivable because one‘s present VP is essentially world appearance which is ―stripped‖ from the reality of its objects, the disjuctivist responds that appropriate. The skeptical context however changes appropriateness of Moore‘s answer. discusses epistemology with his dogmatic friends philosophers, such statements would be question against the skeptic, although in normal conversational c hypotheses must be false. The problem is that Moore‘s response here simply begs the that I have hands‖, context in which the epistemic status of ordinary beliefs are at stake, Moore as debate is somewhat reminiscent of the one between Moore (1959) and the skeptic. In the which the inconceivable for the disjunctivist. Now, the essential question here is whether the context in impossible that V appearance lacks a real object. What the skeptic asks is actually disjunctivist rejects the metho demands to employ the skeptic and the disjunctivist. In the very early stage (first premise) of the TE the skeptic ssibility of even conceiving that his position is false because he believes that it is Similarly, in the context in which the skeptic raises the In responding to this difficulty I want to draw your atten

debate takes place makes the disjunctivist‘s answer dialectically appropriate. This ergo epoche

―I know that there is external world‖. Therefore, the skeptical

and ―bracket‖ the existence of perceptual object (if any). But the d because it does not reflect reality ematic about disjunctivist response here that very much - mindedness. All the skeptic asks us is to 53

possibility of conceiving a V tion to the dialectics between ontext where Moore -

it is metaphysically - involving. My opinion lace? The skeptic serts ―I know

CEU eTD Collection hallucination (based on the TE): purported object presents itself. Here is the final formulatio the same because ―what is experience about‖ cannot be individuated apart from how the referential/narrowest propose to move the argument one step forward. From ―appearances of H and V is possible that appearances of Hs and VPs co stand really is without deciding the matter at start. At the very least (or best), I think there is a is this: actually should not presuppose any claim about what is constitutive of perception. The upshot hallucination is all about inquiring the real nature and object of perception, then the TE guide to real nature of perception is possible. any). As far as phenomenology of the experience is concerned, the scenario we imagine is 4. 3. When hallucinating I‘m directly aware of a non 2. If H appearance is co 1. It is possible that H appearance exactly matches V appearance by being co - off between the disjunctivist and the skeptic‘s position here.

the disjunctivist should not raise an objection to the TE by appeal to what perception Let me now return to the main line of the TE argument. The sub Moreover, in the context where skepticism is at stake, the only non conclusion of the simple version of the argument from hallucinatio far as I can tell, in both cases I‘m directly aware of the same purported object. referential/narrowest When having a VP I‘m directly aware of sense

- type identical‖ I propose to argue that their purported objects must be - - referential/narrowest type identical with it.

its phenomenological analysis. Since the argument from - referrential/narrowest 54 -

type identical with V - physical object (sense datum),

datum. From (2) and (3). n of the argument from

- type identical. Now I - appearance, then as conclusion is that it - n question begging .

P are co -

-

CEU eTD Collection tell, in both cases I’m directly aware of the same purported object. appearance is co Then, the dot namely, disanalogy can potentially meet the objection. An H and VP are you imagine, whereas the extra dot in the above example ads something. And maybe this the imagined scene (―there a referential/narrowest H indistinguishable from a VP you imagine a H appearance which is co As I have already argued, a H whic principle hologram of a tiger and the real tiger. But no matter how hard you try there is no chance excellent discriminative abilities. Similarly, it is possible to sp dot is reflected in the appearance, although it is undetectable for people who don‘t have difference between the two pictures, at least in principle. This is possible because the extra really try harder you would be able to spot the extra dot. There is a possibility to spot the of dots are different although at first you are not able to detect their difference. If you would objects. counter although you actually see two different pictures. The disjunctivist could say that this is a pictures, one with 10 dots and the other one with 11 do possible objection which concerns the 2 Now, let me discuss how this part of the TE argument can be challenged. Consider the first Let me try to give an a -

example which shows that sameness of appearances doesn‘t imply sameness of direct our epistemic situation with respect to their discrimination cannot be improved.

-

to detect a difference between an appearance of a perfect H, and a veridical one. - example is a counterexample to a more generalized version of (2): - referential/narrowest - type identical to the veridical appearance. The additional condition of re no physical objects‖) makes no change to the appearance that nswer to the counterexample. One could say that appearances h you conceive in the TE is perfect because in imagining a nd - type identical with y appearance, then as far

premise. For example, you are presented with two 55

ts. They appear to be the same, ot the difference between a in principle

However, that does not -

indiscriminable, If x

as I can

-

in

CEU eTD Collection than exactly matches genuine perception. However, my motivation was intentionally helped subjective indistinguishability and the sameness of appearances through a TE. I thereby non our attention; I decided to focus on proposing a way how to narrow the gap between many respectable views and objection the context of contemporary discussion on philosophy of perception. However, there are discussion about the common factor and disjunctivism in order to place the TE argument in implies sameness of appearances in the argument considerations that rendered questionable the claim that subjective indistinguishability important questions. The though experiment argument was motivated mainly by hallucination, I agree with Robinson, is inconclusive. same kind of object. Namely, the disjunctivist‘s position is still viable. Such argument from follow that objects of the two a weaker interpretation of the TE, the narrowest yields the conclusion that objects of a H and VP must be the same. However, from the same? I believe that the premise (2) is plausible. judge there is no difference. Am I not justified in claiming that their direct objects are the the difference between an appearanc objects of H and VP must be the same. Suppose that I did everything possible in order to spot there is a relevant difference between the dot imply that an instantiation of it (referred by the premise (2)) is thereby undermined, because pro However, the thought experiment argume The strong interpretation of the TE, the co Finally, I would like to remark that we have good justification for the thesis that

skeptical. My goal throughout the discussion on hallucinations was to estimate how

the skeptic to defend the assumption that non ppearances (i.e. their properties) must be instantiated in the e of a perfect H and veridical appearance. And yet, I s to the argument from hallucinations that did not get - example and the hallucination case. - type identity thesis, it does not necessarily 56

nt makes a contribution in addressing

- from hallucination. I introduced the

refere

ntiality thesis, is quite strong, and it - veridical experience pro

common factor rather

-

CEU eTD Collection have a good explanation of the phenomenology of perception, but we have to deal with datum theorist‘s point of view seems to be the following: either (i) we endorse the PP and very plausible, but its consequenc and how they are governed with physical laws. On the one hand, the PP seems intuitively naturalism, then we need an explanation how these entities are brought by our experience, problematic the very nature of mind theory raises many problems that I cannot address here. In particular, philosophers find hallucination) defensible, there are worries that both arguments inevitably leave. Sense is far more compelling. However, although I find both arguments (from illus the same. The version of the argument that generalizes through continuity thesis (Robinson) a propon generalizes through indistinguishability thesis (Crane) is inconclusive, although I believe that disjunctivism is a viable option, I must concede that the argument from illusion that have a different nature, in objects are the same. As we have seen, two experiences might be indistinguishable and yet that if two experiences are indistinguishable, it doesn‘t necessarily follow that their direct their objects is fully enfolded, and placed in the debat 2.1. until now when the relation between subjective indistinguishability of H and VP and and hallucination. it is a plausible argument. Let me now conclude the section on the arguments from illusion compelling is the arguments that is traditionally labeled as ―skeptic friendly‖. I conclude that I postponed the final conclusion of the argument from illusion discussed in section ent of such argument has good ground to believe that objects of illusions and VP are Conclusion Of The Argument From Illusi

virtue of having different kinds of direct objects. Since es are difficult to accept. The dilemma, from the sense - dependent entities. If 57

e with disjunctivism. We have learned

such theory is to be consistent with on And Hallucination ion and

- datum

-

CEU eTD Collection 28 terms of the common factor does not mer ―matching‖ relation. Thus the skeptical assumption, the ―matching‖ relation spelled out in must be the same. Both common factors are thus related and can individuate the skeptic‘s and VP appearances are phenomenally exactly the same, to the the common object. In the argument from hallucination it was argued from the thesis that H kind in a broader sense (perceptual experience, perceptual appearance); or more narrowly (ii) the sense basis of what is different. Therefore, skeptical hypotheses are possible. Then, as far as what we know on the it is possible that things seem the same way perceptually, whereas reality may be quite possibilities. If we the ―veil of perception‖ and open perceptual knowledge to be subject to skeptical error following. The arguments from illusion and hallucination are plausible arguments that lead to suggest. the world. This certainly counts as an objection against the theory, as the ―traditionalists‖ enabled by sense there is the epistemological worry we began with, namely, its vulne experience. The remaining question is what the lesser sacrifice is. to force us to make a compromise with respect to o ―neat‖ . As Crane points out, the phenomena of illusion and hallucinations seem metaphysical problems; or (ii) we have a less satisfactory explanation of phenomenology, and

For more see The common factor that individuates the ―matching‖ relation within the framework of My final conclusion with respect Apart from metaphysical and explanatory problems for the sense -

datum theory can be cashed out in two ways, concerning (i) the common me

Huemer (2001). given - data (appearances) which interpose themselves between the perceiver and

are always aware of (mere) appearances, mind

to us in the experience, there is no way to rule them out.

to the sense ely follows as a conclusion of the arguments from 58

ur ordinary conception of perceptual - datum theory and skepticism is the

conclusion that their objects -

dependent sense data, then rability to skepticism - datum theory

ntal 28 -

,

CEU eTD Collection avoid the conclusion that posits obscure mind order to respond to the challenge raised by the argument from illusion and hallucination, and are left out with the threat of skepticism. far as the of perception does not involve a state of mind that is world problem. Crane (2005) concedes that McDowell‘s crit loosing genuine intentionality, intentionalism also gives rise to a ―veil of perception‖ According to Crane‘s interpretation (2005), McDowell‘s objection (1987, pp. 250) is that by way sense (at least) immediately arise. In this respect, intentionalism seems to resist skepticism in the the problem of Since intentionalists deny that the arguments from illusion and hallucination are sound, then object. Thus nothing suggests that our perceptual epistemic access to the world is mediated. sense going to assess whether intentionalism an have a ―common cause‖ puzzle, and the puzzle of perception raised by the phenomena of illusion and hallucination (sameness of appearances), which confirms McDowell‘s (1 illusion and hallucination (sameness of objects), but also presupposes it as a premise - datum theory. According to intentiona Let me first address the point that At first, intentionalism seems to be a theory that circumvents problems that affect - datum theory fails to. However, this is only a surface hiding a d 2.3. Intentionalism, The Common Factor, And The Possibility Of the ―veil of perception‖, and consequently skeptic‘s error –

the common factor view. In the rest of the present chapter I am

perception is not essentially world d disjunctivism are vulnerable to skepticism. lism in perception we are aware of the external - Skepticism dependent sense data as objects of perception, 59

icism can be roughly put as follows: as 982) point that the skeptical

-

possibilities do not ifferent problem.

involving - involving, we

. In

CEU eTD Collection real object, since a phenomenologically identical state ( a H) can occur in absence of its that the phenomenal character of perceptual experience is not explained by reference to its aboutness of a state in virtue of positing an intentional object. The thesis st ―brackets‖ existence of its real object, although the view preserves directedness and so but such a notion does not imply that whenever things seems in a certain way, there Perceptual content is in Crane‘s view identified with claims: captures the way in which a that being in a state with percep object doesn‘t imply that the state has a real object, like in cases of hallucinations, it follows in which intentional object is presented. Since being in a mental state with an intentional its nature is essentially bound to content, rather than object. The phenomenology of perceptual experience is best explained as a form of intentionality where object is merely intentional but not real. Thus, Crane (2001) argues the nature and figures an object to which your thought is directed. Similarly, in hallucinating a pink ra unicorn?‖, you would answer ―the unicorn‖. Clearly, ―the unicorn‖ is not real, but it still sometimes need not be perceptual experience. Although all intentional states have intentional objects, these objects intentionalist deny the PP mething seeming to be such a. c. Reality of a percept b. Perceptual experience is best understood as relation to content.

(Perceptual content

real. If you were asked ―What is the object of your thought about an - ual object is not essentially determining the nature of experience.

the view that something real is immediately given in the real - and tual content doesn‘t necessarily imply that the content

object is presented. Crane obtains the following set of

real perceptual object). - such. Intentionalist‘s conception of perceptual content 60

how the object seems

content amounts to the

(2001, pp. 147), ated by (c) means

is

t, such way

CEU eTD Collection content 30 29 hallucination to arise. From this it follows that the conclusion of the argument from illusion and Since both perceptions, and give rise to the problem of the ―veil of perception‖ possibilities because they posit a common factor present in hallucinations and veridical rendered poss the same perceptual content in the absence of physical objects. Again, skeptical scenarios are as the ―veil of appearances‖. For every genuine perception, it is possible to be in a state with figures as the common factor is sufficient to lift the veridical and non and ―bad‖ case is to skepticism. Perceptual content, the way in which the intentional obje the same, while reality might be radically different than your senses tell you. And that leads occur in t phenomenal character of a particular perceptual experience, e.g. seeing fire in a fireplace, can determined by its perceptual content. When we couple that thesis with (a), it follows that object. Moreover, according to strong inten

This view that denies existence of However, Crane says that a phenomenal character of perceptual experience and Both theories he absence of its real object. It is possible that how things seem to you now may be

mode. theories lift the ―veil of perception‖, they both enable skeptical error

Perceptual content Sense datum - ible.

―in perception we are directly aware of appearances‖ of the ―veil of appearances‖. problem of the ―veil of content‖.

ex hypothesi

- - veridical experience. Thus, it seems that perceptual content which

sense –

- common factor (sameness of objects) gives rise to the problem datum and intentionalism qualia

the same, and explains the phenomenal ―matching‖ between –

common factor (sameness of contents) gives rise to the , intrinsic, non tionalism

61 - relational, irreducible properties of experience. the ―veil of content‖, which is as problematic

29 , the phenomenal character is entirely -

enable skeptical scenarios as genuine is entirely explained in terms of its

in two ways: -

is not es ct seems in the ―good‖ sential for the - possibilities

30

CEU eTD Collection the object of a H and VP is not the same, then experiences are not the same. He affirms experience section I will discuss disjunctivism and its anti kind assumption, seems to have the best chance to neutra skepticism in its very start. Disjunctivism, a theory that fundamentally denies the common possibilities. Naturally then, the denial of a common factor emerges as a way to block intentionalism opens up perceptual knowledge to be undermined by sufficient to meet the skeptical challenge. precisely to deny the common kind assumption. In what follows I will d opens. According to Huemer (2001) and McDowell (1982) the best strategy to begin with is world, in the absence of external objects. metaphysically possible to have the same perceptual experience as the one in the ―good‖ (CF): If H and VP share a common factor (perceptual content or object) then it is that H and VP have a common factor. room for the possibility of skeptical scenarios. What is essential seems to be the assumption possibility of skepticism, because intentionalism denies that claim and yet it is leaves open If the skeptic is indeed committed to (CF), a way to evade the possibility of skepticism Both the sense I have already indicated how the common factor figuring in sense -- > same object‖. The disjunctivist seems to reas - datum theorist and the disjunctivist accept the conditional ―same 2.4. Disjunctivism And Skepticism

- 62 skeptical implications.

lize the skeptical threat. In this on in the following way: since skeptical error

iscuss whether this is - datum theory and

-

CEU eTD Collection skepticism: between the arguments from illusion presuppositions (that I understand to be) of the ―traditionalist‖ view concerning the relation and hallucinations, which were discussed in the previous sections, let me roughly map the in the ―good‖ world could occur in the ―bad‖ world. chance to start off, if it essentially relies on the claim that all perceptual experiences we have presupposition about the common factor is remov matches the one in the ―good‖ world. Once the ―veil of perception‖ is lifted, and the skeptical then, it is not possible to have a non perceptual experience, which in the case of VP has an object, and in case of because in that world there is no corresponding external object. possi If the external object is an essential, constitutive part of a VP, then it seems that it is not affairs directly available to her. (2008, pp. 378)perceptual experience can yield falls short of a subject‘s havingWhat shapesan environmental this scepticism stateis the thoughtof that even in the best possible case, the most t says that: disables the possibility of skeptical scenarios to even arise as genuine possibilities. McDowell stand modus tollens

ble that in the ―bad‖ world I could have the same experience that I have now, simply - off between two positions. However In order to clearly see how the disjunctivist deals with the 2. Key assumption about the nature of perception and hallucination 1. There are phenomena of illusion, and ―philosophers‘ hallucinations‖.

factor view.

, whereas his opponent affirms

- veridical experience with the content that exactly

and hallucination, the ―veil of perception‖ and , the disjunctivist brings a caveat that supposedly modus ponens 63

ed, skepticism does not seem to have a

. And here we have a typical

There is no such thing as

problems raised by illusions

H it doesn‘t. And –

the common

hat

CEU eTD Collection McDowell says, ―without the ‗ Now, we can clearly see that the disjunctivist denies (2), and consequently (3) and (4). As the sense “good” world, in the absence of external objects. content then it is metaphysically possible to have the perceptual content as the one in the perception enables skeptical hypothesis to arise in the framework of the intentionalist theory theses. In the previous sections we have seen how common factor is an assumption that the in The first three premises concern the sense tentionalist and the sense 9. =Skepticism. From (7) and (8). 8. The closure principle 7. Hence, S does not know that (¬SH), on the basis of experience. From (6) 6. Therefore, perceptual evidence in the ―good‖ and ―bad‖ case is the same. From (4) 5. Perceptual experience is S‘s evidence. 4. Therefore, 3. Argument - datum theory leads to the possibility of a skeptical scenario – ¬SH. If S doesn‘t know (¬SH), then S doesn‘t know that p. and (5) the sense From (2) or from (3). [This sub in the actual world and yet, reality is radically different (Deceiver Hypothesis). Perception‖). From (1), and (2). [This is the argument for the sense of VPs we are aware of appearances/mental representations/sense data (―Veil of

(4) follows from (2), which is encapsulated in CF:

-

from illusion and hallucination leads to the conclusion that in all cases dat it is metaphysically possible to have the same perceptual experience as um theory]. - highest common factor‘ conception of experience…the datum theorist. From (5) to (9) we have epistemological :

If S

knows - datum theory, whereas (2) and (4) are shared by

- conclusion concerns both the intentionalist and p , and knows that 64

And in th e first section we have seen how p If H and VP share perceptual entails -

(4) follows from (3). ¬SH , then - datum theory].

of S

knows

CEU eTD Collection front of one, for example.‖ (1999, pp. 154) experience. Both experiences can ‗tell one‘ (incorrectly, in the nonveridical ofcase) the thatcontent there of isa nonveridicalayellow door experience in can inde 31 ―bad‖ case (premise (6)). This claim is denied by the call it) deceived‖ inevitably leads from such a conception of evidence. The core claim then is (I shall skeptical hypotheses. The first premise of the skeptical argument, ―I don‘t know that I how it seems could count against th premise: ―perceptual experience is S‘s evidence‖. If our sole evidence or justification that particular internalist conception of evidence. The key point then is to understand the 5 to the sub of the skeptical problem is not entirely exhausted by the discussion on the common factor (up Therefore, I d ―bad‖ world, it follows that I cannot rule out SH on the basis of perceptual evidence. that all perceptual evidence that I have in the ―good‖ world is both worlds, then the conclusion ske things seem premises ((5) of skeptical scenarios version of the doctrine, and expand our understanding of the theses from (4) rendered impos illusion and hallucination don‘t give raise to the ―veil‖, and the skeptical scenarios are traditional problems [including skepticism] lapse‖ (1982, pp. 479). The arguments from

Putnam points out that ―…McDowell does indeed insist on the existence of this kind of common factor. Part - Now the notion of evidence comes in the focus of the debate, suggesting that the In (5) ―experience‖ refers to what is ―reflectively accessible about experience‖. If

the - conclusion (4)). According to McDowe

captures the ―matching‖ relation that constitutes evidence which is the same in

evidential common factor - on‘t know that (¬SH). –

which is shared in both situations

sible. I will discuss the disjunctivist strategy, but also the epistemological (8)).

e skeptic amounts to what is reflectively accessible to the subject -

to the skeptical conclusion that proceeds from episte

ptical conclusion will inevitably follow. From the thesis

-

which refers to evidence shared in the ―good‖ and ed be the same as part of the content of a veridical 65 31 , then it is impossible to rule out the

ll (1995) the skeptical problem arises for a

disjunctivist about evidence ( ex hypothesi

the same in the mological -

the possibility evidential

th

am not

-

locus the

how

CEU eTD Collection if not inexorably lead to epistemological disjunctivism. 32 the above sketch that depicts the ―traditional‖ understanding of the problem. skeptical argument need not necessarily be reconstructed as to carry requirements specified in both dis in terms of claims about the nature of perceptual experience and evidence, and undermine which needs additional epistemological premises. makes the for the thesis that in both cases evidence is the same. Although the common factor view view pla common factor seems to be conjunctivist about evidence, the skeptical argument will still carry. Thus, the evidential would not carry; (6) wou evidence in both cases is the same (disjunctivism about evidence), the skeptical argument factor. In case one would endorse the former view (common factor the common factor view leads to skepticism disjunctivism about perception st perceptual experience nor evidence in the actual world and in the deceiver world. This implies existence of its object. From this it follows that is not possible to have the same question‖ (1982/1998, manifest to him, the obtaining of the fact contributes to his perception. As McDowell stresses, in the ―good‖ case ―when someone has a fact made disjunctivism

rategy most likely demands two theories to converge Byrne and Logue (2009, pp. 68) argue that metaphysical disjunctivism (a theory of perception) naturally and However, I believe that the skeptic can weaken his position to make it less committing From this discussion we can learn something interesting about the skeptical argument; junctivism about perception and disjunctivism about evidence. I think that the ys a role as a presupposition in the skeptical argument insofar it offers an explanation skeptical hypothesis ), which is an epistem 390 ld be false. But if one is disjunctivist about perception and - 1). If perception is constituted by the physical object, then it sufficient

32 possible, this is not enough for the .

ological version of the doctrine concerning the nature of condition for skepticism, whereas the common factor insofar

66

it constitutes the evidential common –

disjunctivism about evidence and epistemic standing skeptic simpliciter al argument In particular, the ), but deny that on the

CEU eTD Collection skeptic need not be comm to subjective indistinguishability suffices for the skeptical argument, then it seems that the perception that posit common factor. If a logically weaker epistemological claim pertaining suggestion that the skeptical argument does not a what metaphysically constitutes the ―matching‖ relation, which brings to the fore a Such skeptic‘s claims do not bear any commitments about what is the nature of perception, or from the one Therefore, it is metaphysically possible to have Then, instead of (4), (4*) can be formulated as follows: in the ―good‖ world, in the abse simply weaken CF, and merely state a weaker version, (CF*): of what is reflectively a hallucination, the skeptical argument will still carry: S does not know that (¬SH) on the basis world. Nevertheless, if one cannot tell that one‘s present experience is not a perfect type of experience one has in the actual world is the one in the actual world. The skeptic may even concede to the disjunctivist that the same Instead, he can say that you might have a ―subjectively indistinguishable‖ experience from yet, reality is radically different say that skeptic c It is metaphysically possible to have a it is metaphysically possible to have the same experience as in the actual world and an say that he is not committed to something like (4). The skeptic doesn‘t have to

in the actual world, and yet, reality is radically different ccessible about the experience. In other words, the skeptic may itted to any particular version of the common factor view. From nce of external objects. , where the ―same‖ refers to the same typ subjectively indistinguishable 67 a subjectively indistinguishable experience

not metaphysically possible in the ―bad‖ rise only for a particular theories of

experience from the one (Deceiver Hypothesis). e of experience.

CEU eTD Collection both kinds of di subjectively indistinguishable experience from the one in the ―good‖ world. It seems that ―bad‖ world. All the skeptic needs is to argue that the skeptic is not committed to the the independent of any theory about perception that the skeptic should commit himself to. Then, argument is a weaker claim the non argument does not necessarily present a problem only for theories of perceptions that endorse we could be deceived. If this diagnosis of the skeptical challenge is correct, the skeptical possibility more general (non theory, intentionalism, experience, skepticism remains a threat. All three theories that I have discussed possibilities on the basis of what is reflectively or introspectively accessible about one‘s even disjunctivists do not deny that claim. criterion assumptions about the nature of perception. The argument merely requires an reconstruction of the skeptical position is stronger because it d position in a very theory rely on such a committing premise. Instead, (4*) suf skeptical hypothesis to arise if the skeptic is committed to (4), but I stress that he need not perception‖ is not necessary to generate the skeptical problem. The sense the case, then the role of the argument from illusion and hallucination in lifting the (4*) it directly follows (7) S does not know that (¬SH) on the basis of experience. If this is - Thus, the skeptic can object that the ―traditional‖ diagnosis of skepticism presents his epistemic common factor view, since the crucial assump

for the common factor: a perfect H is subjectively indistinguishable from VP. And : as far as we know on the basis of the reflectively accessible content of experience, sjunctivism cannot counter skepticism. Disjunctivism - metaphysical) claim (CF*), which presents an uneliminable and disjunctivism - committing way that he need not endorse. Note that the present -

subjective indistinguishability thesis. And this is the only claim, sis that the same perceptual experience can occur in the -

As far a

seem to be vulnerable to skepticism because of a 68 as far as I can tell s one cannot rule out skeptical error

fices.

oes not depend on any tion of the skeptical , I could have simpliciter - datum view enables epistemic epistemic -

denies (4) sense datum

―veil of

-

CEU eTD Collection hypothesis must be spelled out in terms of some kind of ―matching relation‖ between the accompanied with false perceptual beliefs. Hence, a presupposition was that one can have a non The ess intentionalism, and disjunctivism, lead to or (at least) are vulnerable to Cartesian skepticism. denials of sk indistinguishability thesis. Therefore, reflective knowledge or internalist knowledge of the experience is factive or not, which is the crucial point embedded in the subjective have an argument left; he can say closure argument is then rendered false. However, as Robinson suggests, the skeptic will still factive evidence, it follows that S knows that SHs are false. The first premise of the skeptical the subject evidential advantage, from the premise that S has know The disjunctivist about evidence says that if the fact about being in the ―good‖ world gives (2008) nothing distinguish the states is the core issue, not their ontological status and disjunctivismare doesreally perceiving, or are dreaming or are the victim of andoes evil notdemon. invoke Inability the internal to external object of which we are aware. When Descartes sets outa thecertain sceptical object is nochallenge help against he the sceptic unless we are in a position to tellwhether that it isa aperception real is of a real object or not. The fact thatIt anis thate the foundation for scepticism is not the ‗veil of perception‘, but our inability to tell confirmed by Robinson who summarizes the point in the following way: from which it directly follows that (7): S does not know that (¬SH). Such diag whereas evidential disjunctivism denies (6), but the skeptic needs only something like (4*)

In this chapter I have discussed whether and how the sense ential assumption enabling skeptical hypothesis to arise is taken to be the possibility

to enable use to distinguish when we are directly perceiving and when we are not. eptical hypotheses remains out of our reach. - veridical experience phenomenally exactly like veridical experience,

status of appearances, but only that Conclusion Of Chapter II that S cannot tell on the basis of reflection whether one‘s 69

xperience is in fact directly of we cannot tell - ledge in virtue of having datum theory, that the skeptical

nosis about is whether we

CEU eTD Collection this chapter. The theory analyses perception in disjunctive terms, thereby denying the problem of the ―veil of weaker claim about the nature of experience. However, intentionalism still leaves us with the theory. While the later postulates existence of mind be individuated in a less committing way than This view of perception gives the skeptic an explanation of how the skeptical hypothesis can veridical experience matches its veridical counterpart in virtue of sharing for the possibility of skeptical hypothesis to arise because it makes it poss still left as a viable position. from illusion and hallucination arguments that enable skeptical hypothesis to arise are plausible. However, the argument datum) present in VP, whereas reality may be radically different. I concluded that the possibility that one can have a non The conclusion of the arguments from illusion and hallucination then makes plausible the by the ―matching‖ relation that refers to sameness of objects (or appearances) in both cases. out of our direct scope of consciousness. The skeptical hypothesis is the same. Such a view lifts the problem of the ―veil of perception‖, leaving the external object illusi most important conclusions. this thesis in various ways, from more to less committing ones. Let me remind you of the common factor thesis. Throughout this chapter non - veridical (hallucinatory) and veridical case. I have identified such relation with the on and hallucination) suggested that objects (and appearances) in both states are the The relation between disjunctivism and skepticism was discussed in the third part of Intentionalism postulates perceptual content as the common factor, and opens room Arguments to the effect that we are aware of mere appearances (the arguments from

content‖.

are inconclusive because disjunctivism about perception is

- veridical ex a formulation provided by the sense 70 perience of the same kind of object (sense we have seen how the skeptic can formulate

- dependent objects, the former makes a n rendered possible ible that the non how things seem - datum

-

-

.

CEU eTD Collection skepticism remains a challenge. experiential evidence that we are not deceived, and requires eliminating epistemic luck, that give rise to the ―veil of perception‖. Insofar the skeptic requires reflectively available skepticism does not threat only theories of perception that posit a common factor, skeptical argument appears to be much stronger than the ―traditional‖ line suggests, since skeptical argument. the disjunctivist theory of perception (and the two other views) are vulnerable to this kind of indistinguishability thesis is sufficiently strong for the skeptical argument. Consequently, way, neutral to any particular theory of perceptio skeptical argument. I proposed a ―matching relation‖ that can be formulated in a very weak skepticism. I have inquired whether this theory is vulnerable to a weaker version of the common kind assumption which is ―traditionally‖ thought of be A fter the survey on skepticism and the nature of perception I conclude that the

71 n. My thesis is that the subjective

ing responsible for or theories

CEU eTD Collection ultimately have an impact on the force and plausibility of the skeptical argument. I will phenomenology and nature of dreams because the question ―what are dreams made of‖ will this is a question that will be argument. Namely, the latter will also depend on how we understand dream experiences. And are still some issues that make the deceiver argument slightly different than the dream perceptual knowledge sufficiently like hallucinations for the purposes of the skeptical argument targeted at different views of ―what are dreams made of‖ will enter the debate. Although dreams are dreams. Again, the issue of some sort of common factor emerges here non deceiver world. The dream argument, however, does not involve hallucinations, but rather the skeptic raises an error discjunctive terms, or by reference to a common factor. This question was important because hallucinations are, from what we ordinarily believe it to be. We have seen what different views say about what which our experience of the world is subjectively the same, whereas reality radically differs views of perception have an impact on understan issues in theories of perception. In particular I have focused on the question of how different - veridical experiences that are subjectively alike waking perceptual experiences, namely, In the previous chapter I have discussed the Cartesian skepticism and its relation with in contrast with genuine perception. The relation was spelled either in –

they are non - possibility which involves non addressed. In what follows I will also inquire into T HE DREAM ARGUMENT - veridical experie CHAPTER 72 ding the skeptical hypothetical scenarios in

nces subjectively like veridical, there III - veridical experiences in the

too, and this is how

CEU eTD Collection don‘t know that I am not dreaming‖, and again there is a premise that follows from the the from follows that premise a is there again and dreaming‖, not am I that know don‘t dream error brings fore the to the epistemic luck platitude; even ifyou perceptual have true beliefs, the although it might actually b don‘t you then now, dreaming not are you that tell theout possibility you that dreaming, solely basis onthe ofyour If experience? you cannot would have the same conviction that you are reading you now, dreaming were you If following. the say would Descartes experience? sensory waking our on doubt a cast dreams in deceived we are that fact the does how So, dreams. denies nobody Well, false. were beliefs our and dream a just was We believe that the plot of the experience is real, until we finally wake up and realize that it W the distinction between internalism and externalism. address non against dream skepticism that relies on his model of dream experiences. Finally, I will Sosa‘s view as a response to the problem of dream skepticism. I will propose an argument of the argument, and on issues concerning Augustine, and Sosa‘s imaginative model. introduce two i hile dreaming, we usually don‘t know that images in our mind do not correspond to reality. Descartes‘ starting point of the argument is based on experiences we all have had. had. have all we experiences on based is argument the of point starting Descartes‘ The chapter is divided in three parts: in the first part I focus on Descartes‘ exposition - - Cartesian pre possibility makes your belief reflectively lucky. The skeptic‘s first premise is nfluential views of dreams: the orthodox view defended by Descartes and St. 3.1. Cartesian Steps Of The Dream Argument mises of the argument that concern a deeper epistemological issue e thee case that you reading are thispaper. Again, the argument subjective indistinguishability, then I discuss

73

know this paper. So, how can you really rule

that you are reading this paper, paper, this reading are you that

that we are deceived in in deceived are we that

―I

-

CEU eTD Collection observes that he had dreams in which he was tricked, i.e. the dream experience was not In the first sentence Descartes makes a statement about his past dream experiences. He be asleep.‖ (AT VII 19: CSM 13) result is that I begin to feel dazed, and this very feeling onlyany reinfo sure signs by means of which being awake can be distinguishedth from being asleep. The As if I did not remember other occasions when I have been trickedwhat by I exactlyam doing. similar All this would not happen with such distinctnesshead toand someone it is not asleep. as Indeed! moment my eyes are certainly wide awake when I look at this piecedressing of paper; I shake my How often, asleep at night, am I co argument: From this Descartes concludes that there is no experiential criterion of wakefulness. whether he‘s now awake or asleep, merely on the bas and distinct dreams in which he was deceived, it seems that he cannot be entirely sure He observes that his present experience is vivid and distinct. But, given that he had such vivid indicates that we are awake, and not dreaming? This is the question that trou awake feels differently than being asleep? What exactly about our present experience intuitive and simple answer, but on more reflection, can we precisely point out certainly doesn‘t feel the same as having a dream that one is seeing the Pope. That is an the present section. we really howwaking a tell exper addressed what could be interpreted as the first step (or question raised) of the argument: can explicitly and concerned mainly was Descartes However, makes. skeptic contemporary by the fire‖. Therefore, ―I don‘t know that I‘m sitting by th closure principle ―If I don‘t know that I am not dreaming then I don‘t know that I‘m sitting

oughts while asleep! As I think about this more carefully, I see plainly that there are never Let us take a closer look on Descartes‘ passage where he introduces the dream Austin (1962, pp. 48) convincingly said that being present in front of the Pope - gown, sitting by the fire

leep; as I stretch out and feel my hand I do so deliberately, and I know

nvinced of just similar events ience differsience from dream experience? That is topic of the when in fact I am lying undressed in bed! Yet at this 74

is of the character of his experience. e fire‖. These are the steps that the –

rces the notion that I may that I am here in my bles Descartes. how

being

CEU eTD Collection relation between his will and action. Hence, properties of experience include: vividness, Descartes reflected upon the sensations he had, he reflected upon his self potentially bear the mark of wake doesn‘t question one‘s wakefulness, but one‘s knowledge of wakefulness. conclusion is then, even Suppose that it is true that he is awake being asleep. Then, the question doesn‘t seem to be whether he is actually awake or not. claim, ― although there may be one that I cannot detect at the moment. Descartes makes a stronger awake now. The claim does not seem to be only that ― reflectively accessible property of his present experience which c from being asleep‖. The conclusion is that there is no ―mark‖ of wakefulness; there is no saying ―there are never any sure signs by means of which being awake can be distinguished such vivid and distinct dreams. Finally, after a careful investigation Descartes conclude his present experience apparently cannot be certain indicators of wakefulness, because he had himself of being ―tric that only waking experiences (Ws) have, but dreams (D) lack. However, Descartes reminds words, the ―mark‖ that Descartes is trying to find is a property of the experience, a property and action. He is looking for the ―mark‖ introspe vividness of the feeling of hands and head, he observes the relation between his deliberation is looking for the ―mark‖ of wakefulness by reflecting upon his experience: distinctness and wakefulness, something that waking experiences have, but dream experiences la present experience is not one of those dream experiences. He is looking for a ―mark‖ of veridic al. So, how can he tell that he‘s not tricked Let me now make a few remarks about ―properties of experience‖ which could there are no sure signs” ked by exactly similar thoughts‖. Then, distinctness and vividness of

if he is awake, he cannot ! He claims tha fulness that Descartes is looking for. In his thinking -

how can he tell that he is awake t being awake can never be distinguished from 75 ctively, in the experience itself. In other know now

I can not find ? Descartes wants to be sure that his

that he is awake. The dream argument ould indicate that he is

a sign of wakefulness‖ ? The skeptical - awareness, the

ck. Descartes

s by

CEU eTD Collection reality. The next question is whether such argument is consistent at all. Descartes cannot be certain that his present experience and beliefs really correspond to experiences, they cannot be a m ―external‖ coherency. Since all such properties seem to be present both in dreams and waking on the experience itself. coherent. Hence, this kind of coherency depends on other beliefs that a subject has, no dream would be coherent. If I believe what all sane persons do, my dream would not be everything experience has with other beliefs rest of my belief itself, but I have to reflect upon ot whether my experience is coherent, I have to reflect not only upon my present experience he points out his room. Nothing in this scenario gives him any reason to doubt that he‘s awake. However, he takes into consideration. He says that he is now in his dressing sentence of the passage could be interpreted as if amounts to explanatory relations that hold experience is coherent in the following sense his conscious decision to stretch. The action is explained by his will to s also include distinctn Finally, ―properties of experience‖ include ―‗what it is like‖ properties, ―internal‖ and There is another kind of coherency important in this context. In order to find out ess, or ―what it is like‖ to be in a mental state. However, properties of experience is made of cheese, and I had a dream that I live in a house made of cheese, my coherency

that he had dreams with a coherent plot. - system. ―Being coherent‖ in this sense depends on the relation the dream . For example, Descartes observes how stretching of his body follows

ark that distinguishes them. From this it follows that - her beliefs, and observe how the plot ―matches‖ with the

let us call it ―external coherency‖. If I believed that within -

I shall call it ―internal coherency‖ 76

the plot of the experience itself. The first that is the first criterion of wakefulness that

- gown, sitting by the fire, in

tretch. The -

which

t only

CEU eTD Collection contradiction ((0)&(5)). Thus, asserting (1) assumes (0) I occurred [4].‖ (1959, pp. 259) say, that h For a philosopher who does use it as a premise [1] is, I think, in fact, implying, though he does not expressly the conclusion because: Moore accepts the first premise but he claims that if (1) is true then it is not compatible with the dream argument, which could be reconstructed in the following way: In Philosophical papers 5. Therefore, I 4. If I don‘t know that my memory is not a part of a dream, then I don‘t know that I 3. If I don‘t know that I 2. If a waking experience is qualitatively indistinguishable from a dream experience 1. My present experience of (p) sitting by the fire is subjective e himself knows it to be true. He is implying therefore that he himself knows that dreams have had dreams. having dreams is not just a part of the dream then I don't know that I‘m not dreaming (based on my sensory experience). from dream experiences of p I have had. 3. 1. 1. The Dream Argumen don’t know if I have ever dream

(1959) ‘m not dreaming now then I don‘t know that my memory of know that I have had dreams.

Moore raised an objection regarding the consistency of 77

t Is Self

ed. - Defeating (Moore)

Hence, we have a ly indistinguishable

CEU eTD Collection dream argument seems to question consistently our certainty in particular judgments based on am dreaming now, that my experience in not about the external world. for doubt. The point of the argument could also be stated by introducing a had. Descartes does not need to claim that premises are certain in order by the fire (p) is subjectively indistinguishable from dream experiences of p I Then, the 26) that one is inclined to believe or to affirm that one has in therespect past beento p ―taken(where one‘‖. ―evidence‖ is similar to what one hadThe in point,the past). intuitively, It is sufficient is that one does not ne something with certainty. She says: know I had dreams‖ since the point of the argument is to cast a doubt, not to establish is not contr contradicting ―I don‘t know if I have ever dreamed‖. Believing something that I don‘t know could be interpreted in a weaker sense as ―I believe that I dreamed‖, and hence it is not But, knowing something is far fr grounds for claiming that asserting p implies knowing p? Asserting p implies knows ever had dreams. conclusion that I don‘t know that I‘m not dreaming now, and hence I don‘t know if I have defeating. Asserting (1) implies that I know I have had dreams, but the argument yields the be just a dreamed memory. According to Moore‘s interpretation, the argument is not know that he is not dreaming. If one The diffic

that he had dreams. I think that the skeptic is entitled to ask Moore what are the Therefore, Moore‘s objection is not undermining the strength of However, it is not obvious that Descartes i

ulty Moore stresses is that one does not know that dreams have occurred if one does skeptic can just reformulate (1) as follows: (1*) adictory. As M. Wilson (1978) argues, Descartes doesn‘t even need the strong ―I

om believing something. The statement about having dreams

is

dreaming his memory about having dreams could ed to know one has ever been deceived with 78 s committed to the claim that he actually

my present experience of sitting

to establish a reason the argument. The possibility believing believe

self

(1978, pp.

- that I I have

p.

CEU eTD Collection whether I‘m looking at this piece of paper. Particular judgments based on sensory experience provided the basic ―dream material‖, even though I can not be certain at this very moment nature in general. Even if I a This passage suggests that the dream argument is not questioning the existence of corporeal time through which they may endure, and so on. (AT VII 20: CSMthings; 13, 14) the quantity, or size and num class appears to include corporeal nature in general, and it'sfrom extension; which wehe for shape all of theextended images of things, whether true or false,certain that even occur simpler in thought. and more This universal things are real. Theseof are things a the ever been seen before Or if perhaps they manage to think up something so new that nothingthem naturesremotely which similar are hasnew i painters try to create sirens and satyrs with the most extraordinarythe body bodies, as a wholethey cannot give things that are real, and hence that at least these gene which come in sleep are like paintings, which must have been fashionedhave such inhands the orlikeness such a bodyof at all. Nonetheless, it must surelymoving be admittedmy head andthat stretching the vision out my hands Suppose then that I am dreaming, and that these particulars questioning the belief about the existence of the external world: The following passage from possibility. But can such a ―local‖ doubt make me doubt that there is no external world at all? perc next question is about the scope of the dream argument. establishes a more radical doubt, namely, in th sensory experience. However, at this point it is still not clear whether the argument

colors used in composition must be real. By similar reasoning, although this general kinds eptual judgment that ―here is a piece of paper‖ is rendered questionable by the dream If I‘m dreaming now then I am not really seeing this piece of paper. My particular -

eyes, head, hands and so on 3. 1. 2. What Is The Scope Of The Cartesian Dream Argument? - are things which are not imaginary but real and exist. For even when - something which is therefore completely fictitious and unreal m dreaming now there has to be the external world which Meditations n all respects; they simply jumble up limbs of different animals. ber of these things, the place in which they may exist, - could be imaginary, it must at least be admitted that

suggests that Descartes‘ dream - e existence of a mind are not true. Perhaps, indeed, I 79

ral kinds of things

- that my eyes are open, that I am

s it were the real colors - independent world. The - eyes, head, hands and argument is

do not even

not -

at least

CEU eTD Collection is that there must be an external world that supplies us with the ―dream content‖. images is combine experiences is based on the causal relation with the external world. The content of dream answer. In the above passage Descartes indicates that the explanation of the content of dream can he be confident that there is an ext experiences them. If he doesn‘t know that he has hands, that there chairs, the sun, etc., how external world, and at the same time doubt whether particular objects are the way he This argument suggests that Descartes cannot consistently b of a mind doubting particular judgments about the external world, without doubting the very existence are in 5. Therefore, at any time t, I don't know that there is an external world. From (2), (3), (4) 4. The external world just is a ―bundle‖ of partic 3. For any time t, if I‘m dreaming, then I don't know that this particular object O is the 2. If I am dreaming now then I don't know that judgments about particular objects are 1. Even if I‘m dreaming now the existence of simple and universal things are beyond He 6. The conclusion in (5) contradicts (1). deed doubtful. re is a set of claims that generate tension in Descartes‘ argument: each other. way it seems. true. etc.). doubt (I know that there is an external world with most general properties: shape, size, - independent world. The question of consistency thus re

d, so to say, from the ―material‖ we get from senses. Then, his conclusion

However,

the question is whether Descartes can be consistently in ernal world at all? Here is what Descartes could

80

ular mind e confident that there is the - independent objects related to - emerges.

CEU eTD Collection external even though there is nothing real out there. is no external reality, whereas the demon hypothesis implies the Descartes‘ view that remains: the dream passage implies that we cannot have dreamsgeneral of(and external more committing) reality if claimthere point she makes is that what Descartes assumes is that theremental must content, be cana figure as a presupposition implicit in the passage on dreams33 (AT VII 20: CSM 13). The certain doubt, if I am dreaming then I don‘t know that particular everyday perceptual the external world doesn‘t seem to have a simple answer. Nevertheless, there is at least dreams has to be something ―o Descartes‘ passage about dreams implicitly affirms it; in order to have dream images there problematic. The evil demon argument assumes that content seems that Descartes implicitly denies world which causes such experiences, and thereby supplies the mind with its content. Thus, it experiences of sky, of different sounds, shapes and so on, even though there is no external The evil demon hypothesis introduces a possibility that sounds and all external things are merely the delusions..... ( ATenergies VII 23: CSMin order 15) to deceive me. I shall think that the sky,rather the air,some themalicious earth, demoncolors, of shapes,the outmost power and cunning hasI will e suppose therefore that not God, who is supremely good and the source of truth, but internalism about. To put it simply, if there were no water, I could not think about water. been directly or indirectly (through testimony) in a causal relation to the thing I am thinking right way (Joe, 2004). For example, I can form a thought with have a certain intentional mental state, it is necessary to be related to the environment in the Externalism

I am thankful to Katalin Farkas for observing that Descartes‘ causal principle, rather than externalism about However, this view brings Descartes in ten Such argument ultimately hinges on an 33 Finally, the question of whether the dream argument casts doubt on the existence of .

which is implicit in the evil demon hypothesis:

with regard to mental content can be (very roughly) put as follows: in order to ut there‖ that brought about the content which the mind combines in

about externalism. However, granting that point, there is still a tension in content

externalist assumption about the mental content. - sion with his commitment to externalism. But then, Descartes view is 81

opposite one cause

can - – externalism is false, whereas

certain content only if I have we can have experiences as of the of experience, rather than a more have thoughts and mployed all his content

one

CEU eTD Collection sleep, two and three added together are five, and a square has no more than fourthey sides.‖(AT really exist VII in20: the CSM natu14) other subjects of this kind, which deal only with the simplest and most generalother things, disciplines regardless which of dependwhether on the study of composite things, are doubtful;mathematical while truths:arithmetic, ―So ageometry reasonable and conclusion from this might be that , astronomy, medicine and 34 were dreaming then opinions of the scientists would be brain activity. However, this kind of external criterion is not what Descartes had in mind. If I example, I can ask scientists to tell me whether I‘m awake or not by determining what is my Now, the question is how or on what grounds can I judge that I am awake or not ‖Being able to tell this means that for every situation I am in, I have to to be able to t Let m Let me begin with two possible accounts of the criterion of wakefulness: cri judgments are true (SYM). The first criterion requires that I am in a position to tell which is which experience;

Although the dream argument targets at particular judgments based on the senses, it definitely doesn‘t question terion of wakefulness. (b) When awake I can tell that I‘m awake (a) When dreaming I can tell that I‘m dreaming e consider the first option, I shall call it the 34 whether . Now, let us dwell deeper in what could be Descartes‘ notion of the re or not, contain something certain and indubitable. For whether I am awake or 2. 1. Being able to tell

Being able to tell

I am awake or not‖ 3. 1. 3. The Criteria Of Wakefulness

that whether

implies: 82

I am awake (when I am awake). symmetrical

I am awake or not.

just dreamt opinions. So, the only

criterion of wakefulness ell in which one I am.

? For

all

CEU eTD Collection 35 Let us see how Descartes‘ argument might be reconstructed with the SYM criterion: property that D do not have, and/or W lack a ―dream property‖. (b‘): Ws have a distinct detectable indicates that I‘m dreaming, and/or dreams lack the ―waking property‖. (a‘): dreams have a certain ―dream property‖ which can be reflectively detected, which implies the following: my experience on the basis of which I can tell (SYM) indistiguishability‖ understood in the following way: interpretation of Descartes‘ criterion of ―waking property‖ which all waking (perceptual) experiences have and dreams lack. One have, and perceptual experiences lack; and by the same token, there must be a detectable then it must be that a dream experience has a detectable situation one is in from dream experiences (D) on the basis of some property of the experience, to being able to subjectively (introspectively) distinguish waking (perceptual employ reflection/introspection as a mean for discernment. Thus, the SYM criterion amounts non

Let me assume that present experience is waking experience. - 2. I remember having distinct, coherent and vivid dreams. 1. Distinctness, coherency, and vividness, are pr que I can distinguish W from D iff there is an introspectively detectable property of stion begging way of establishing a criterion in the debate with the skeptic is to . For example, if I can tell which is which experience by reflection alone,

―waking property‖ which indicates that I am awake, a

wakefulness can be explained in terms of ―subjective 83 whether

operties of my present

―dream property‖ that all dreams

I ’m awake or not.

35 ) experience (W) The criterion

in each experience.

CEU eTD Collection dreams lack. Since Descartes had examined all properties of experience, and all of them corresponding ―waking property‖ which only sometimes true; the ―dream property‖ can be detected. But the question is whether there is a people claim that not a dream. Another reason why (a) is sometimes true has to do wit absent in my present experience, I would be confident to say that my present experience is f not all dreams are incoherent. The difficulty is to distinguish waking perceptual experiences can know look back on our dream experience, and recognize a ―dream property‖. However, dreams incoherent thing Sometimes (a) is true. Some dreams have a ―dream property‖, which only dreams have. In rom such coherent and vivid dreams. Only if there is a property that 6. Therefore, I cannot distinguish W from D, not 5. There is no such detectable ―waking prope 4. [SYM] I can 3. Therefore, both Ds and my Ws have these properties. From (1) and (2) property that Ds do not have, (b): Ws have a detectable “waking property” which indicates that I am awake, a indicates (a): dreams have a certain ―dream property‖ which can be reflectively detected, which I can judge that I am awake, not experience on the basis of which I can tell

that I‘m dreaming, and/or dreams lack the ―waking property‖ while

distinguish W from D iff there is a introspectively detectable property of

dreaming they can actually tell that they are dreaming. Hence (a) is s usually happen, e.g. pigs can fly. So, it seems that sometimes we

and/or W lacks a “dream property”. - (b).

waking (perceptual) experiences have and 84 rty‖ of my experience on the basis of which whether

- [SYM].

I‘m awake or not, implies:

h lucid dreams. Some all

dreams have, that is

CEU eTD Collection skeptic to claim that even if there is a ―waking property‖, one is not able tosuch detect property it. doesn‘t exist. But, even if this claim were false, the argument wouldThis is still a way work; how Descartesit suffices could for thedefend the claim that undetectable property of the experience imp wakefulness. Here is the argument: follows that there is no ―waking property‖. Therefore, I am justified to believethat that absence there ofis evidence no sign forof there being a ―seen‖ by the light of introspection our argument box looking empty is good evidence that there is no chocolate in the box. Perhapssomething we can more apply to thisthis analogy to answer? Perhaps something like this: ―I have no evidence that there is a chocolatethat thein thebox is empty. Suppose now that someone tells you that there is a chocolatelooking in the in box.a box,Whatyour wouldyou eyes are working normally, and cond 36 follo asymmetrical criterion of wakefulness. After this point has been clarified, let me take one is a hidden ‗waking property‘‖ which is for some reason inaccessible to me at the moment. on the basis of which I can judge that I am awake hidden. The sub one all the skeptic rea can‘t detect the ―waking property‖ it doesn‘t follow that there is no such property. However, ―there are no signs by means of which he can distinguish W from D. in (5) follows. (distinctness, coherence, and vividness) that he can identify are present in D, the conclusion

Let me briefly discuss one possible line of argument in Descartes‘ favor. Consider one analogy. You are 36 4. 3.Absence ofevidence isevidence ofabsence of such property. 2.There is evidenceno of a ―wakingproperty‖. 1. Transparencythesis: there can be nothing i wing: being in a position to tell . At the end of the day it doesn‘t matter whether there is a ―waking property‖ which is

Let us now consider another candidate for the criterion of wakefulness However, Descartes ( I‘m justified in believing that there is . If we grant Descartes‘ principle that mind is transparent detectable

(ASY) criterion. Suppose that criterion of wakefulness amounts to the

- conclusion : lly needs is to establish that one can‘t detect such a property, even if there is -

the absence of evidence is the evidence for absence of the chocolate in the box. The signs‖, as it is stressed in (5). So, one may object that if Descartes

AT VII 19: CSM 13)

there is no such detectable “waking property” of m -

and I find no evidence that there is such a ―waking property‖; assuming

―waking property‖ is evidence that there is no such property, it that

no I am awake when I am awake. This criterion is less n mymind of which Iam not aware of.

―waking property‖.

seems to affirm that there are never any sure 85 itions for vision are optimal. You see perfectly well

is still consistent with the claim that ―there step deeper in enfolding the options for the

That is a little bit stronger claim than

-

everything that there is in mymind is

box‖. But there is

-

I shall call it y experience lies that

CEU eTD Collection indistinguishability. However, the former is a broader concept than the latter. There are further discuss only ASY which is because one is not able to tell one can‘t tell that we are dreaming while dreaming. There is no criterion of wakefulness of (b) awake or not, asymmetrical version of the criterion conclusion follows in both cases, whether he assumes the stronger symmetrical or the weaker it follows not only (¬SYM), but also (¬ASY): I cannot distinguish W from D. So, Descartes‘ in mind the argument reconstructed on the previous page, that f experience on the basis of which he can judge that he is awake. After carefully examining his experience Descartes claims that there is no such property of property‖. which indicates that I am awake, a property that D do not have, and/or W lacks a ―dream Here, I can distinguish W from D iff (b) Ws have a distinct detectable ―waking property‖ my waki (ASY) I can distinguish W from D iff there is an introspectively detectable property of criterion: dreaming when dreaming. Thus we obtain the following definition of the asymmetrical demanding than the symmetri Ws have a distinct detectable “waking propert So far I have talked about the criterion of wakefulness in terms of subjective My intention here is to point out that W are indistinguishable from D because the truth ng experience on the basis of which I can tell

or 2:

being able to tell that cal one (SYM) because I need not be able to tell that I‘m

one is awake, when being awake. From now on, I will in my opinion essential for the dream argument. that

of wakefulness (1: being able to tell

I am awake). 86

y” cannot be established, not because

that

I am awake.

Therefore, it follows, bearing rom (5) which asserts not whether

I am

-

(b),

CEU eTD Collection the Aristotel 37 matter how bot distinguishable from D iff for all I know, I could not be dreaming now. Here, it does not Let me now propose a formulation of ASY in terms of access discriminability: W is ruled out by whatever she knows. (2006, pp. 216) are true in a situation B, then, for all she knows, the subject could be in B. It isTake a all the propositions the subject knows in a certain situation A. If all these propositions subject. Farkas explains the relation as follows: one knows in case A and in case B, even if A and B are not in any w in Budapest is in this way discriminable from being in Stockholm. What matters here is what On the other hand, objects relative to some presentation, and thus requires that there have no presen I cannot actively discriminate, let‘s say being in Budapest and being in Stockholm, because I compare the of chocolate that I eat now, with the taste of it I experienced yesterday. But discrimination the present context has to be spelled out in terms of subjective indistinguishability relation. Descartes is left out only with reflection upon his experience. Th because relies on perceptual evidence which is (in this context) under question. Thus, evidence is mere dreamt in the context in which the skeptical scenario is at stake. If I am dreaming then scientif example, there is neuroscience, psychology, and so on. But these criteria are suspect to doubt different criteria of wakef ….a claim that a subject can actively discriminate between two objects makes sense only

For more on this see Farkas, K. (2006). ―Indiscriminability and the Sameness of Appearance―, However, there are several concepts of subjective indistinguishability. (2006, pp. 216). ian Society, 37 tation of the latter. K. Farkas says that: h experiences are presented. Once knowledge in both situations is fixed; either

is relative to a given mode o

―access‖ discrimination is not presentation Volume CVI -

evidence. To rely on such criteria would be question begging, ulness that do not rely on reflection, as I already mentioned. For

Part II, pp. 205 - 25 f presentation. For example, in this way I can

87

is such a presentation for - sensitive. For example, being e criterion of wakefulness in ay presented to the Active Proceedings of

situation not both

ic

CEU eTD Collection that you out that error possibility. If you don‘t know that you are know, you could be dreaming. From your reflective/subjective point of view, you cannot rule feature of your present experience grounded on a subjectively similar experience of sitting in a classroom, such that every belief while dreaming that you are sitting in the classroom. Your dream that you believe that you are sitting in a classroom. background to discuss Sosa‘s response to the dream argument. After clarifying several possible options for the criteria of wakefuln absence of a ―dream property‖, I could not be dreaming (b‘): when being awake, as far as I know in virtue of detecting a ―waking property‖ and/or my waking experience on the basis of which I can tel (ASY) I can following formulation obtains: only kind of non states are going to be relevant to fix epistemic conditions in both cases because that is the experiences are distinguishable or not. However, only facts about phenomenology of mental Let me begin with the Sosa‘s (2005) reconstruction of the dream argument. Suppose

are sitting in the classroom. access - question begging knowledge that can count against the skeptic. Thus the

distinguish W from D iff there is an introspectively detectable property of 3. 2. Sosa On The Dream Argument

could be a feature of a dream experience. As far as you

88

However, you could easily have such a l that not

I am awake. This implies: dreaming, then you don‘t know

ess we have a good - belief would be

CEU eTD Collection perception. 38 doesn‘t mean that it happens that y experiences (¬2), and we don‘t have beliefs not to hallucinate‖ (2005) dream argument relies However, Sosa denies the orthodox conception of dreams upon which he thinks that the D (dream)= H (hallucination)= perceptual experience VP (veridical perception)= corresponds to what we seem to see. have perceptual experiences, whereas there is nothing in the external world which In this view dream perceptual experience and belief. Or, if you like, they belong to the same Augustine), according to which Ds are mental states like perceptions These two claims amount to the so cal nature of dreams:

Similarly, we have seen t 2. In Ds we have perceptual experiences beliefs wehave (Ds) 1. Indreams ou are chased by a lion, but in actuality you are not. Whatever happens When something happens in a dream, reality doesn‘t tend to follow it. You may dream The dream argument, as Sosa presents it, hinges upon two assumptions about the

perceptual experience

s resemble hallucinations. Like in hallucinations (Hs), while having Ds, we 38 hat ―traditionalists‖ have seen the source of skepticism in a particular theory of . Dreams are not states like hallucinations. ―To dream is to imagi . From this it follows that in dreams we don‘t have perceptual perceptual experience while

you dream. Similarly, in a dream you may believe that a

led ―orthodox view of dreams‖ (Descartes, St.

while

89

+ object we dream (¬1).

-

they involve genuine kind in

of experiences. a dream,

ne,

CEU eTD Collection Press, pp. 264 Oxford Handbook of Epistemology 39 experience, then it follows that one can distinguish W from kind of imaginings (dreams). all fictions of a sort, or quazi fictions‖ (2005). If dreaming is not like perceptual kind of To dream is to imagine ii. Another strategy is available by denying (2): things about the world, despite of the dream ordinary perceptual beliefs same belief simply because in the dream class room. The dream world is not even in the realm of near relevant aspects, where S believes that she is sitting in a her ordinary beliefs are safe. In almost all nearby possible worlds which are just like ours in possible worlds where agent believes that p, p is true. Since in dreams S doesn‘t have beliefs, (unqualified) Sosa develops an anti i. One strategy is assured by denying (1): Consequently, Sosa‘s view of dreams gives him two possible anti From ―to dream is to imagine‖, it also follows that dreams are not perceptual experiences. inference fails: imagining: when we imagine, we don‘t really believe things we imag lion is chasing you, but actually you don‘t hold such a belief. Dreams are more like

See, for example: Sosa, E. (2002) ―Tracking, Competence, and Knowledge,‖ in to believe in a dream - 286. And Pritchard (2005). safety condition

- skeptical strategy which is linked with his discussion of safety. The . ―Dreams seem more like imaginings, or storie are rendered safe, and it follows that it is possible to know some

, ed. P. Moser, New York: Oxford University ã 39

to believe while you dream

requires that an agent S knows that p iff in (almost) all nearby

-

world S doesn‘t have beliefs at all. Therefore, - error possibility.

90

class room, she is actually sitting in a

- possible worlds where S has the

- skepti The ine. The following s, or even day dreams,

cal strategies:

CEU eTD Collection phenomenally differs from really being in such a position. The difference is in vividness and is different than ―what it is like‖ to perceive. Imagining that you are being chased by a lion propose a version of Sosa‘s dreaming, solely on the basis of reflection. After critically examining Sosa‘s theory, I shall anything. If this is so, then we are back to the beginning dreaming you would have the same conviction that you a dreaming to affirm. It seems that the point of the dream argument is that if you were to tell that one is awake, by being able to tell that one is actually affirming and not merely able to tell skeptic does not and need not argue that the criterion is symmetrical, namely that I have to be though I am skeptic, that the criterion of wakefulness is being able to tell Finally, I will discuss Sosa‘s criterion of wakefulness. Sosa claims, supposedly contra the a question concerning the criterion according forward a (2004 forward in I shall focus on Sosa‘s second strategy, on arguments against the skeptic which are put experience; to awake, and this criterion can be fulfilled because b) dreaming is not a kind of perceptual order to distinguish W from Ds, one has to be able to tell Sosa‘s main point is that waking expe - 5). Let me briefly sketch the structure of the f Let me first start with an obvious point about imagination. ―What it is like‖ to imagine I will raise a few questions for Sosa‘s thesis that dreaming is imagining. First, I put reductio ad absurdum Dreams and philosophy whether not able to tell that I am dreaming when dreaming. However, I think that the dream is to imagine.

I am awake or not. At the end, I raise a doubt whether one response, and argue that the skeptic faces a destructive dilemma.

of his main thesis that to dream is to imagine. Second, I raise (2005), and in the lecture 1 of

riences are distinguishable from dreams because: a) in

to which these mental states are type identical. 91

orthcoming discussion. – that ffirm, whereas you wouldn‘t affirm

we cannot tell that we are not that

one is awake, when being I am awake when I am, even ’s Lectures

is in position

CEU eTD Collection inference: from W? And yet, we are deceived in dreams. I find this puzzling. Consider the following and dreams are kind of imaginings, then shouldn‘t it follow that dreams are distinguishable consider dreams. Since imagining is d the basis of their phenomenal properties. So far so good. But, the trouble comes when we final upshot is the following: we are able to distinguish imagining from perceiving solely on phenomenology. ―What it is like‖ to imagine is different than presented in thought and imagination, and the way of presentedness explains their different and that I see the icon in a certain way precisely in virtue of its appearing to be ―t on the experience; I cannot see it as being round in case of genuine per an entirely different color or shape. However, this flexibility in presentedness is not the same constrained in any way by how the icon really is at this moment. I could imagine it as having between imagination and perception. For example, ima giveness to the senses seem, which belongs to our ordinary conception of perception, is presence to the mind or more importantly in the way the object is presented. One feature of - 3. 2. To dream is to imagine. [Sosa‘s assumption] 1. such. How the object is presented in perception differs from the way objects are Dreams are subjectively indistinguishable from waking experiences. [The skeptic and

(2) Sosa agree on this premise] Imagining is subjectively indistinguishable from waking experiences.

. This is a crucial feature that makes the phenomenal difference ception. How the icon is at the moment I see it puts certain constraints

istinguishable from waking (perceptual) experiences, 92 - shaped, if it is square shaped. It seems to me

gining an icon in front of me is not

―what it is like‖ to see. The how perceptual objects here‖ as such

From (1) and

-

CEU eTD Collection absurdum that we are deceived in dreams. deny either (1) or (2). But Sosa, and be legitimate. But in that case, there is an unacceptable consequence in (3). Thus, one has to ―dreams‖ in the premise (1). If dreams are kind of imaginings, then such a substitution should and perceiving. As we see, the trouble for Sosa arises when we substi But

4. Two mental states are type identical in virtue of sharing the same 3. Dreaming is 2. 1. Dreams are subjectively indistinguishable from perceptual experienc 11. 10. ((8)&)9)) is contradictory. 9. But, imagining is subjectively distinguishable from perce 8. Imagining is subjectively 7. 6. If A=B, and B=C, then A=C. 5. ―What it is like‖ to dream is the same as ―what it is like‖ to imagine. From (3) and (4) (3) is false; there is a phenomenological (discriminable) difference between imagining

Now let me put the simple argument in a more elaborated form of a properties (difference between mental state typ the best explanation of (1)). perceive). From (2) and (5), (6). thinking differs from seeing). their phenomenal properties, e.g. feeling depressed differs from perceiving something, ‖What it is like‖ to dream is the same as ―what it is like‖ to be awake (i ‖What it is like‖ to imagine is the same as ―what it is like‖ to be awake (to . ¬(3) ¬(3)

type

identical with imagining. [Assumption made by Sosa]. in

distinguishable from perceptual experiences. From (7)

Transitivity of identity relation. even the skeptic, or hardly anyone else, would deny (1)

93

es is determined by the difference in ptual experiences.

tute ―imaginings‖ for

general reductio ad es.

phenomenal nference to

-

CEU eTD Collection subjective indistinguishability relation. 40 waking experiences (I ~ W). The following transitivity fails: indistinguishable from W (D~W), it won‘t follow that imaginings ar imaginings (D~ I) because they belong to the same mental kind and dreams are ―indistinguishable‖, (I) for imagining): even if dreams may be indistinguishable from phenomenal sorites argument makes the following scenario plaus indistinguishability taken as active discriminability is not a transitive relation phenomenal qual raises a question of clarification: in what way are dreams kind of imagining? What are the simply be that (2) means ―dreams are a imaginings, but still have considerabl between dreams and imagining (or day differences between phenomenology of depression and joy. The same relation might hold emotion because they share certain general phen qualities, but not all of them. For example, joy is a kind of emotion just like depression is an same as imaginings. He can say that they are alike with respect to some phenomenal which is which. Similarly, Sosa need not argue that dreams are p doesn‘t mean that the cat looks exactly like the dog, otherwise we wouldn‘t be able to tell a subclass of imagining, then the objection can be (5) is too strong. If the second premise Let me now discuss possible replies on Sosa‘s behalf. First, Sosa could argue that the premise

In the previous chapter we discussed the phenomenal sorites argument that precisely questions transitivity of Second, Sosa could argue that the objection is not persuasive because subjective For example, a cat might look similar to a dog with respect to furriness, but that ities they share?

e phenomenal differences. Hence, Sosa‘s position might to dream is to imagine - subclass dreaming); they might both belong to a class of 94 of imaginings‖. In that case, the omenal qualities. However, there are vast

answered.

means merely that dreaming is

henomenally ible (―~‖ stands for e indistinguishable from 40 exactly . The

reductio

the

CEU eTD Collection effects. Functional than perceiving, etc.) from the point of view of the subject, feeling hunger differs from thirst, thinking is different Subjective/internal relevant criteria: phenomenal and functional difference between them. Let me elaborate options for the should have the same ―what it is like‖ as imaginings. But, I think that there is an important the view that general phenomenal character of a mental state determines its kind, then dreams dreams are not like hallucinations; dreams are kind of imaginings. Now, if we find plausible mind. In such a view dr the experiences are not veridical. Thus, what constitutes their difference is external to the dream is the same as ―what it is like‖ to be awake, with the caveat that in the case of dreams Augustine, dreams are the same kind of states as per imagining? what is the relevant criterion for establishing type (sub transitive. experiences‖ won‘t necessarily follow because subjective indistinguishability is not Therefore, ―(8) imagining is subjectively I ~ D~ WE

I~ WE WE I~ Which ever way Sosa would respond to the

: we fix the kind of a state by its

According to the orthodox conception of dreams held by Descartes and St.

: we fix the kind of a state by i

eams resemble hallucinations. On the contrary, Sosa holds that in functional roles distinguishable from (perceptual) waking 95 ts specific ―feel‖ or ―what is like‖. (E.g.

reductio ceptions because ―what it is like‖ to - type) identity of dreams and , i.e. by its typical ca , there i s one remaining question: uses and

CEU eTD Collection experiences are distinguishable from dreams fu criterion according to which dreams are a kind of imaginings. differences between dreaming and imagining, Sosa needs to answer the question what is the establish the type (or sub experienced determination, and (ii) how much of phenomenal likeness is sufficient to sub ques cannot be fulfilled, at least not fully. But then, the second question for Sosa branches into two alike. Consequently, the internal criterion for type (or sub experienced determination it is difficult phenomenal character of the experience. If dreams and imagining don‘t share the order of of presentedness reversed in dreams; the scene in my dream does not se e.g. I am the creator of the imagined scene. But, the order of experienced determination is three palms. In case of imagining, it is usually the case that I determine or ―tailor‖ the object, wind, are not details of the scene edited by me. It‘s not up to me whether there are to the scene: two palms, wind, etc. But, in dreaming, it appears that the number of palms, and When I imagine that different. First and foremost, the difference is in the order of appears in imagination. Consequently, the phenomenology of dreams and imagination is imaginings. I think that the way in whic the subjective criterion, I emphasize a possibly relevant difference between dreams and Now, let us see whether dreams and imaginings fulfill the criteria I have specified. Regarding rther develops the argument against the skeptic. In Sosa‘s view (one reason why) waking Now I shall pass to Sosa‘s account of the criterion of wakefulness, and see how he tions: (i)

of a situation or object is crucial for and partially determines the is type (or sub

I‘m drinking cocktails in Dubrovnik it appears that I am adding details - type) identity? Given that there are relevant subjectiv - type) identity compatible with mutually opposite orders of

h an object appears in dreams is different from how it to see how they could be sufficiently subjectively

is

because the criterion of wakefulness is to be 96

em to be determined by me. The - type) identity of mental states experienced

determination. e/internal

two or

way

CEU eTD Collection false, but because (b‘): “dream property” which can be reflectively detected, whi are indistinguishable from dreams is no criterion of wakefulness because one is never in position to tell and Williamson take to be legitimate. As I have previously argued, Descartes says tha follow that (b) is false, or that there is no criterion of wakefulness. while dreaming one can‘t tell that one is dreaming is to be able to tell whether one is dreaming or not. Then, Sosa argues that of course that wants to ascribe the from being dead by being able to tell that we are alive, when we are alive. It seems that Sosa dead people have no beliefs. However, that doesn‘t mean that we can‘t distinguish being alive distinguish being dead from being alive, by being ab Sosa argues that being asleep is in a relevant aspect similar to being dead. We cannot when one does not. Why not say the same of dreams?one (2005)could never tell Might the possibility that we dream not be like that of being dead, or unconscious? Even if introduces the following analogy: that we ca deceived about our situation, i.e. we can‘t tell that we are not awake. But that doesn‘t imply fulfilled, namely that one is able to tell not be fulfilled, we shouldn‘t worry about i dreaming, and (b) when awake I can tell that I‘m awake. Sosa argues that although SYM can one is awake. To remind you SYM in a position to tell

However, I think that Descartes had in mind the same asymmetrical criterion that Sosa nnot tell that we are awake when we are awake. To make his point stronger, Sosa that that following kind of reasoning to the skeptic. The criterion of wakefulness

Ws have a detectable “waking property” which indicates that I am one is awake, when

one suffers such a

not

implies that:

because I can‘t tell that (a‘) that

t as far as the asymmetrical (ASY) criterion can be one is awake. Certainly, when dreaming we are fate, one can still tell that one does awake, and not to b 97

(a) when dreaming I can tell that I‘m

le to tell to be dead when dead, because (a) is false. But, from this it do ch indicates that I’m dreaming

e in a position to tell : dreams have a certain

that one is awake. Ws not

suffer it esn‘t whether

t there

is

CEU eTD Collection conviction that you affirm, whereas you would not affirm anything. Can you be sure that you merely skeptic can say: ―You are now supposedly thinking, but, can you be sure that you a think the fol distinguishable in this way, it doesn‘t really help us against the skeptic, who might respond in we do. And this is what distinguishes their thoughts Here it is puzzling to see how, or on what basis can we distinguish waking from dreaming surroundings. This by our light sufficed to make the two statesworld, distinguishable.‖ nor that we are not dream state we do not affirm anything What enables us to distinguish the two content can tell that we affirm. Therefore, we can tell that we are a dream affirmatively believe. In his view, the property of affirming is sufficient for us to distinguish believing. When we dream we don‘t affirm anything, whereas, in our waking life are imaginings. Now, we are curious to know what Sosa takes to be other hand, we have Sosa who affirms that W can be distinguished from Ds because dreams have Descartes who after carefully searching for the ―waking properties‖ finds none. On the Rather, they disagree o essentially disagree with the skeptic about argued that ASY is sufficient awake, a property that Ds do not have

type in the way Sosa points out, without being able to distinguish their tokens. The - lowing way. You may know what distinguishes quasi dreaming Sosa says that the difference between dreaming and being awake is in affirmatively Now, if the skeptic actually takes the ASY criterion, it seems that Sosa doesn‘t tokens - thoughts from waking thoughts. So, when we are awake we do affirm, and we . Sosa says

that you think?‖ If you were dreaming now you would have the same n the question whether the criterion is satisfied. On the one hand, we - whereas in wak that in dreams we don‘t affirm anything, whereas in waking life

for skeptical purposes and logically weaker than SYM. ,

- and/or W lacks a “dream property” not that we are veridically perceiving an external what ing life we do knowingly perceive our types 98

- is the required criterion of wakefulness. . But, even if thought types are identical states is just the fact that in the

real thought type wake, whenever we are awake.

the ―waking property‖?

from

is false. I have dreaming to

(Sosa, 2005)

we do re not

CEU eTD Collection which is not distinctive for normal perceptual experiences. Once we find the property that all experiences, Sosa can argue that all dream experiences have ―imagination like‖ property asymmetrical criterion of wakefulness with denying the ―orthodox conception‖ of dream difficulty but I don‘t think that this objection is fatal for Sosa‘s view. By coupling the basis of the pheno skeptic may grant, the possibility that one merely seems to affirm cannot be ruled out on the affirm from really affirming. So even if there is such a ―waking property‖, as the friendly problem that boosts the dream argument aga because in dreams we don‘t affirm, whereas in waking life we do. As I already stressed, the the dream argument that relies on Sosa‘s account of dreams. hopeless. I will present a destructive dilemma against the skeptic, and sketch a response to but it is also about how do we know that our present experience has such propert point of the skeptical dream argument is not all about whether there is a ―waking property‖, a defeater that criterion of wakefulness is satisfied. Even if our experience has a ―waking property‖, we have skeptic‘s pit: if we cannot know that we are not dreaming now, we cannot know that the required in order to distinguish token how to discriminate affirming from dreaming skeptic may grant that affirming may be the ―waking property‖, but then raise a question of are not having a dream Sosa maintained that the asymmetrical criterion is legitimate, and can be fulfilled Nevertheless, I do not think that our epistemic situation and Sosa‘s solution is threatens menal properties of the (thinking) experience. I certainly acknowledge this - 3. 2. 1. A quasi knowledge - belief right now, which merely see

Response To The Dream Argument that our present experience has such a property. Thus, the thoughts. And this question brings us again into the in is our inability to distinguish seeming to - to 99 - affirm on the basis of reflection, which is

ms as if you affirm it? The

y.

CEU eTD Collection to formulate the strategy in a conditional way. knowledge that we are awake, then we can gain a significant dialectical advantage. I propose now, a cannot argue that consequently we are not competent when being awake. If we are awake because we are not competent to notice them. But, as we have learned so far, the skeptic dreams we don‘t us wakefulness is satisfied. satisfies the criterion. The dream defeater now threatens our if you don‘t know that you are not dreaming you cannot be confident experience lacks the ―imagination like‖ property? The skeptic can press the following point: now then our competence is reduced. Then, the question is how do we know that our because in dreams we are not capable of making rational judgments. So, if we are that the criterion is satisfied. “dream property” after all because there is a negative ―waking property‖ in the following sense ―waking property‖ as a positive property that Ws have and Ds lack. However, (b‘) is true have, detectable “waking property” which indicates that I am awake, a property that Ds do not ―dream property‖ that indicates that I am awake now. One disjunct of (b‘) property‖. Consequently, the ―waking property‖ is a Descartes‘: instead of looking for a ―waking property‖, we should look for a ―dream experience dreams have

and/ ssuming that the skeptic is willing to grant that, and rather focuses his attack on our I think that only one point has to be granted to the skeptic; we have to admit that in Howeve or lacks

W lacks a “dream property” -

the ―dream property‖ r, there is another skeptical objection lurking here

the ―imagination like‖ property. The strategy I propose is reversed from

.

ually notice any incoherencies in the plot of the experience, simply

The skeptic would certainly challenge our competence to judge -

it becomes possible t is

false, namely, the disjunct concerning the 100

n egative o identify that waking knowledge

one; it is the absence of the -

the

that your experience problem of knowing

that the criterion of Ws have a -

Ws lack the dreaming

CEU eTD Collection conditional part) in a form of a dilemma for the skeptic concerns competent ( skeptic can challenge this response by raising the question of whether one can tell that one is conditions, it does not follow that both epistemic situations are the same. However, the account not merely the reflectively access competence, are not the same in the dream case, although the ―imagination like property‖. Consequently, this fact about my experience, plus my symmetrical because I‘m incompetent in dreams. And also, makes a huge difference exhausting the description of my both epistemic situations. Remember that competence seems lucky.‖ To this objection I would respond that the reflectively accessible evidence, the it Now, the skeptic may say ―it seems to you that your experience has a ‗waking property‘, and formed in a reliable way. This suffices for me to know that this experience is not a dream. The belief that this experienc If

would seem the same if you were dreaming. Hence, your true belief is just reflectively I am awake then: (ii) (i) , might be the same in both cases. However, that kind of evidence

knowledge of competence despite being incompetent when dreaming. I am (after all) competent to tell that my experience has the ―waking property‖, My experience by reflection alone), and generate the skeptical problem on a higher level, which

it is not the case that my dream situation would be epistemically has the ―waking property‖, and yes, it also e has a ―waking property‖ is true if I am awake, and it is also . Let me briefly sum up the first stage of the response (the ible epistemic state, but also the external epistemic 101

-

and then address t in dreams my experience has the how it seems is seems

is not entirely

he latter problem that it does. . If we take into

how it

CEU eTD Collection situation) in a form of an argum Let me further clarify points made about the second horn of the dilemma (the waking 2. Suppose that I am awake now. In this case, my present experience is not ―imagination 1. Suppose that I am dreaming now. Then, the skeptical dream argument is just a part of criterion of wakefulness is satisfied. In addition, if I am competent then I am like‖, and I am competent to ju respond to it. unsound, and (b) it would be irrational from me to take the argument seriously and following: if I am dreaming now then (a) the skep am dreaming the argument just seems to be sound but is not. Thus, I conclude the is a dream it would be irrational to treat the dream argument seriously. In addition, if I alleged new computer, I would be considered completely ir importantly it would be the computer upon waking up. We normally don‘t take dreams seriously, and more seriously? For example, if I dreamt that I bought a new co my dream iterates then I am competent to judge that I am competent. Or, to put it simply, it‘s the same reasoning that just takes a diff faculty to judge my thinking about things. There is no higher am competent in making judgments about things, then I am also using the same make are objects of my higher order thought competent to judge that I am competent. My own reasoning and arguments that I .

it‘s a

dreamt argument ent: irrational

dge that. Hence, I can competently judge that the

to do so. If I would spend months in looking for my . In this case why should I take the argument 102

erent object. Hence, if I am competent

they are about my thinking. Now, if I tical argument is (very likely) mputer, I wouldn‘t look for rational. Similarly, if this - order faculty involved; competence

CEU eTD Collection rather present a ―dream defeater‖ to challenge it. 41 made of. As we see, even if dreams are ―made of imaginings‖, the question is how do we satisfied. But that question remains a thr brings to the fore concerns our competence to judge that the criterion of wakefulness is not arise only for the ―orthodox conception‖ of dreams. The essential problem the skeptic have learned something new about the dream argument: the s and hence I know that I know that I‘m not dreaming. competence iterates; I can mak dreaming. Knowledge that I know that I know p (KKp) is ensured by the thesis that belief that p, Knowledge of the external world (Kp) is ensur

I don‘t think that the skeptic would deny that experience gives 7. Therefore, from (1), (5) and (6) it follows that I know that I know that I am not 6. Since c 5. Therefore, if I am awake then I know that I am not dreaming. (K¬D) from (4) and (1 ) 4. Hence, if I am awake then the belief that this experience is not a dream is justified. 3. If I am awake then I am competent to judge th 2. The ―waking property‖ can be detected only while being awake and not dreaming. 1. If I am awake then my belief about the external world is true, and I am competent in Let me conclude this section. Through the discussion with Sosa and the skeptic, we dreaming. (K(K¬D)) wakefulness is satisfied. ―imagination like‖ property making judgments. prima facie ompetence iterates then I am also competent to

justification for the belief that p

e a competent higher order judgment about my competence,

eat independently of the issue of what are dreams 103 ed in the following way: if awake, I have a true

at my present experience lacks us prima facie 41 , and I know that I‘m not keptical dream argument does judge

justification. I think he would

that the criterion of

CEU eTD Collection basis of his experience). Namely, he doesn‘t have justification for the belief that he is not that he is Cartesian steps of the dream argument, premises that Descartes did not make explicit. concerned the criterion of wakefulness. In the rest of the chapter III I will off position with the skeptic. think that the proposed strate undermine the skeptic‘s assumption about the symmetry of the dream and waking situation. I competence iterates, and the external epistemic and non which threatens the ability to tell that the criterion is we can pretty safely say that when awake I know that I am competent. The ―dream defeater‖ reason for the skeptic to grant competence in one domain and then deny it in the other, I think coherency and competence in thinking and reasoning. Since I do not see any non all I know, I might be dreaming. In addition, competence extends to my ability to introspect I am awake I have a wakefulness by Sosa‘s view that to dream is to imagine, and competence, the asymmetrical criterion of that is not known in the dream case. Once we know. Finally, Ws are access discriminable from Ds either just a dreamt argument or we do know things about the world, and we know that we we are not dreaming? The answer I proposed was the follow know that we are making a competent judgment about our experience, if we don‘t know that The Cartesian conclusion is that W is indistinguishable from D So far I have discussed Cartesian steps of the dream argument, which mainly awake even if he is awake, because he doesn‘t know that he is not dreaming (on the -

when awake one is able to tell that one is awake 3. Non true and justified belief that I'm not dreaming. Hence, it is false that, for gy based on Sosa‘s theory at least gives a prospect for a stand

- Cartesian Steps Of The Dream Argument

have the ―waking property‖, which is ensured 104

- satisfied is contra

there is something in the waking case - epistemic circumstances that ing. The dream argument is

-

can be and is satisfied. When . - Descartes cannot tell posed to the claim that discuss the non - arb

itrary

-

-

CEU eTD Collection intelligence is not defective…‖ (1950, pp. 94) believing and not knowing it, and in view of the former fact, we know that in certaincan directly instances know that of we are knowing it, and when we believe something we know43 or can know that we are one‘s intellectual duties. For more see G. Pappas (2005). (experience or belief), and (iii) access to the knowledge basis, (ii) 42 argument can be interpreted within suc Kp alone. A version of the K such a justified belief, it follows that one can, in princip where justification is accessible to the subject on the basis of reflection knowledge basis is supposed to be. In Descartes‘ view knowledge is a justified true belief, Chisholm, Ginet, Fumerton, BonJour, Conee and Feldman, is the view about what the of internalist kind. Internalism about justification, defended in different versions by he is dreaming h the fire, but that is not enough, he has to be able to neutralize the ―dream defeater‖, because if dreaming. Descartes‘ experience might give him

However, there are three kinds of internalism about justification: (i) A famous proponent of this principle is H.A. Prichard, ã KKp, is often taken to be one way to define internalism about knowledge e doesn‘t know that he is sitting by the fire. The justification at issue here is 6. 5. If I don't know that I‘m not dreaming then I don't know that (p) I‘m 4. I don‘t know that I‘m not dreaming. 3. Internalist justification is a necessary condition for knowledge. 2. If my experience is indistinguishable from some dreams then I don‘t 1. My present experience of sitting by the fire (p) is indistinguishable

have internalist justific from some dream experiences. sitting by the fire. - I don't know that p. From (4) and (5) deontological concept K thesis; which says that knowledge (in principle) iterates, mentalism

focuses on the nature of the basis itself,

h an internalist framework in the following way:

of justification analyses justification in terms of fulfilling ation for believing that I am not dreaming. 105 who says: ―When we know something, we either do or

prima facie

le, know that he knows by reflection access

justification that he is sitting by

internalism emphasizes subject‘s which is mental 42 . In virtue of having 43 . Descartes‘ its use our

CEU eTD Collection So, even if I don‘t know that I am not dreaming, I might still know that there is a window in require that we know the skeptical hypothesis to be false in order to it is enough that the belief is appropriately formed. Consequently, the reliabilist doesn‘t about it. to establish the matter of reliability. But most certainly I don't have armchair knowledge beliefs formed on the basis of experience are true. I need to have third person access to reality perception is reliable unless I am able to principle accessible by reflection. For example, I cannot decide the matter whether my justification is a component which is external to the mind, and consequently, it can not be in Justification, according to Goldman, is the According to his view S knows that p iff: we knowledge is whether the experience is properly related to the external world, and not what subjects need not have reflectively accessible ground for a belief. What decides the matter of - say that is what externalists about justification like Goldman and Dretske would typically do. They deny the 3 Now we can more clearly see ways in which one can resist the conclusion. The first way is to

what justifies S’s belief need not be cognitively accessibl believe 3. Bp is justified iff Bp is formed by a reliable cognitive process 2. Bp true is p 1. S’ s justification for believing that p may be determined wholly by facts external to S The believer, says the externalist, doesn't need to know that she has a justified belief; rd

about that relation.

assumption:

Internalist justification is a necessary condition for knowledge

Let us take for example Goldman‘s (1979) .

know the statistics about how often my perceptual

fact

106 that a given p

e to S rocess is reliable. Thus, . Externalists think that have knowledge that p.

. Thi

s

CEU eTD Collection well known cerebral lesion case. A subject has a brain damage due to a form of cancer or a example that might bring to the fore what is missing in the externalist‘s solution. Consider the Does this kind of externalism give a convincing solutio reasons: one‘s knowledge about the external world (fist order knowledge). Here is how the externalist of knowledge about which situation one is (second order knowledge), cannot jeopardize is appropriately related to the ex order knowledge is actually the case. But, according to externalism, that merely shows that one lacks However, the externalist might even concede to the skept window is formed via reliable c front of me because: (1) it is true that there is a window there, and (2) my belief about the

Suppose that I am awake. If I‘m awake then I do know things about the world. if Suppose that I am dreaming. In this case I lack first and second order knowledge. if

I am awake, my belief is true, and my sensory experience is veridical and I dreaming am I then don'tknowthat p. relevant for first on c don‘t know that p. My state of knowing depends only on the situation I am in, i.e. But, even if I don‘t know reliable, then I know that p. ircumstances external to the mind. What I think about my situation is not ; I don't know that I know that p since I don't know whether my experience - order knowledge. ognitive process (e.g. vision). Hence: ternal world. Nevertheless, the externalist would say that lack that

I know that I am awake, it doesn‘t follow that I 107

n to the skeptical problem? Here is an ic that one doesn‘t know which one

second

CEU eTD Collection wolf there‖. If someone asked me ―why do you think that it is a wolf that you see?‖, I would everyday ascription of knowledge claims. Let's take for example a claim ―I know there is a He further argues that the skeptic‘s deman 18) that must be known not to obtain if we are to know the such our knowing such around us... (1984, pp. 14). contemporary skeptic, says that: that p, and conversely, if I know that p t necessary conditions for knowing p. If I don't know that I‘m not dreaming then I don't know dreaming then I don't know that (p) I’m sitting by the fire. the question is whether it gives a satisfactory answer to the problem of reflective knowledge. externalist may secure so called ―brute‖ (Pritchard, 2005) knowledge of the external world, defeater‖ presents a problem for the justification of perceptual beliefs. Although the be dreaming. Given that the dreaming scenario is an open epistemic possibility, the ―dream has also justified beli Thus, it is questionable whether the person who is awake, who has reliably produced beliefs, forming process. beliefs. Namely, the subject doesn‘t have any knowledge about the subjective point of view, it seems that those true beliefs just pop up with other irrational subject doesn‘t seem to have justification to believe that he has cerebral damage. From the forming process reliably produces beliefs about having cerebral damage. However, the of false beliefs, a true belief that he has cerebral damage. Thus, the brain lesion belief lesion, but he i

… knowing that one is not dreaming is a condition of knowing something about the world

Now let us discuss the grounds for the 5 The example emphasizes the intuition that reliability and justification can come apart. s unaware of it. However, the damage leads him to have, along with a number

- and efs. As far as one can tell on the basis of one‘s the experience, one could - such, it is suggested, we immediately recognize that it is a possibility

As soon as we see that a certain possibility is in

hen I know that I‘m not dreaming. Barry Stroud, a d to rule out the dream possibility is rooted in our 108 th

premise:

This premise can be put in terms of If I don't - and - such in question. (1984, pp.

know that I’m not reliability of his belief compatible with

CEU eTD Collection have an instance of a closed under known entailment, it follows that I don‘t know that it is a wolf ( ¬ Kw). We However, since I don‘t know that the animal is not that it is a wolf, and if I know that (W So, when we replace (p) with (W) and (q) with (¬d), we get the following result: if I know then S knows that condition for Kw. Here we have to make explicit the closure principle, which is the thesis that is a wolf, I have to rule out the possibility that it is a dog. In other words, K¬d is a necessar being a dog, that is (being a wolf (W) me. So, we have the following animal is not a dog then I‘m not entitled to claim that I know that there is a wolf in front of from dogs. And this seems to be a reasonable requirement; if I‘m not able to tell that the why it couldn't be a dog. To be more precise, I should be able still compatible with seeing a dog. If I really know that is a wolf then I should be able to tell say ―i knowledge is closed under 3. Therefore, Kq. K(p 2. Kp 1. 3. Therefore,¬ Kp. Kp. 3. Therefore,¬ K(p 2. ¬K¬q 1. t looks like a wolf, it has four legs, fur, tail and so on‖. However, everything I said is ã ã

q) q) q)

q . Or, more formally: modus tollens

known thought: if I know that being a wolf is not compatible with

entailment: If S knows that :

ã ã

¬d), then I know that the animal is not a dog. not being a dog (¬ d)), then, in order to know that it

109

a dog ( ¬K¬d), given that knowledge is p to tell what distinguishes wolfs , and knows that p

entails

q

,

y

CEU eTD Collection skeptical argument involves the following premises: in order to know p I have to if Kp then ¬ D. If I know that knowing p and dreaming are incompatible (K(Kp dreams, even if we can have true beliefs. Therefore, that accidentally true belief is not knowledge. and the corresponding state of affairs is just a coincidence. And our anti between the belief and the fact that makes it true. The ―matching‖ of Descartes‘ dream could easily form a false belief because in dreams there is no systematic causal coincidence that Descartes is sitting by the fire belief that p does no incompatible with dreaming? Consider again Descartes‘ veridical dream example. Descartes‘ this respect the dreaming case is not parallel to the dog Therefore, the truth of p can be (after all) example, Descartes could be sitting by the fire and dreaming that he is sitting by the fire. we lack knowledge in dreams. Actually, it is possible to have true beliefs in dreams. For in fact lying in bed. But having false beliefs in dreams is not the only dream we form false beliefs. E.g. we may believe that we are running on a hill, while we are Now 4. 3. I don't know that I‘m not dreaming. compati not dreamingis 2. Iknowthat 1. Dreaming is not compatible with knowing (I do not know that , let us see how the closure principle figures in the dream argument. Usually when we

p ). ). I don't know that p. ¬ Kp ã ¬D

t satisfy the tripartite account of knowledge. Here is why. It is purely a

know that I‘m not dreaming. At this stage, it seems that the Kp

compatible with dreaming: p does not entail ¬D. In ¬K¬D ble with knowing.

That is why we don‘t have knowledge in 110 and

dreaming that he is sitting by the fire. He

knowing

- wolf case. So what exactly is

is incompatible with dreaming: K(Kp ã reason for saying that p ¬D)

- if I am dreaming that luck intuition tells us

connection ã ¬D), then

- belief

CEU eTD Collection for perceptual belief, reflective perceptual knowledge remains unreachable. some victory to the skeptic. If we can‘t tell on the basis of reflection that we hav preserves somewhat ―brute‖, non argument. block the dream argument by denying a premise of the non aware of having justification in order to have first order knowledge. Thus, the externalist can to the implication holds. But the externalist does not accept that. In order to Kp, we don‘t have ¬Kp. If second order knowledge is a necessary condition for knowledge about the world, then However, the externalist would challenge the third step of this argument, that ¬K(Kp) following formulation of the argument: p, then S knows that she knows that p to argue that it only follows that one does not know that he knows p (¬K(Kp)). However, the conclusion obviously doesn‘t follow without an additional principle. If ¬K¬D, know 6. ¬ Kp, from (4) and (5) MP 5. ¬KKp 4. ¬KKp, from (2) and (3) MP 3. ¬K¬ D D (premise) ¬K¬ 2. K(Kp 1. It seems tha

that Kp. Since justification is not itself acce

(¬K(Kp)) ã ã ã

¬ Kp (contrapositionof KK) the ¬ D) (p D) ¬ ¬KKp, from¬KKp, (2) (1)and t the externalist has a successful way to respond the skeptic, a strategy that ã remise) remise) ¬Kp. The dream argument needs

- reflective knowledge. But such a response still concedes

(Kp

ã

KKp). Then, the skeptic needs to obtain the 111

ssible by reflection, then one need not be

the KK principle: - Cartesian steps of the dream

But then, the skeptic needs If S knows that

e a ground implies

CEU eTD Collection dream argument can potentially account for both epistemological intuitions. ―imagination like‖ property ground on the basis of which one believes that one is not asleep reasoning). On the other hand, the view preserves internalism about justification because the de facto and internalist justification. The belief has externalist justification because when awake, one judge that one‘s experience has no ―imagination like‖ property, then one has both externalist which may preserve internalist knowledge that one is not dreaming. If one is competent t Cartesian steps, and presented a possible response that is based on Sosa‘s theory of dreams argument at a diff external criterion. Nevertheless, the view does not manage to secure reflective knowledge. successful to a certain ex estimate whether an anti justification and knowledge required, as you might expect, determines how is one going to important division between externalism and intern However, there is a hope to meet the challenge raised by the skeptical dream The discussion about the non

forms the belief on the basis of a reliable cogni erent stage. I proposed a dilemma against the skeptic that concerns the - tent, insofar it secures ―brute‖ knowledge which satisfies the skeptical strategy is successful. My conclusion is that externalism is -

is accessi Conclusion Of Chapter III - Cartesian steps of dream argument lead us into an ble by reflection alone. The proposed response to the 112 alism. The question about the kind of

tive process (introspection and -

that there is no

o

CEU eTD Collection 44 mind It unity is rather the incomprehensibility and idea of of the God that indicates that nofinite defense of the trademark argument that rests on a logically weaker claim than priority thesis. perfect mind must be prior to any hu a of idea the that effect the to doubt‖ from ―argument Descartes‘ present will I God? of whe incomprehensible.and In the second section I raise the questionall, of what is the originat of the idea possible is infinite the as God of idea idea of God, to the conclusion that God exists. by Descartes in the whether there is God. I will defend a version of the so called other knowledgewithout onthis I matter, seem donot beto be able to he ―…must enquire whether there is a God, and, if there is, whether he can be a deceiver: for per faculties such that we are systematically about deceived the existence of things weseem to ( scientia

The argument is also stated in the ceive, our perceptual beliefs can not be more than beliefs. That is why Descartes says that

could be the cause of the idea of God. (AT VII 36, CSM 25) 25) CSM 36, VII (AT The plan of the chapter is briefly as follows. In the first section I discuss whether an Descartes ), but merely convictions ( convictions merely but ), A DEFENSE OF THE TRADEMARK ARGUMENT believed that without knowing God man cannot have true knowledge knowledge true have cannot man God knowing without that believed Meditation Three .‖ In this chapter I will follow Descartes‘ inquiry on the question question the on inquiry Descartes‘ follow will I chapter In this .‖ Discourse

pervasio manly created idea of God. Then I will introduce a new 4

4 and in the , which inquires about the source (and content) of the CHAPTER IV

). If ). 113 Principles

deus deceptor deceptor deus .

ther it can be both clear and and clear both be can it ther trademark argument created us with cognitive cognitive with us created entirely certain about any ,

presented

CEU eTD Collection and the founder of Plotinus (c. 205 45 intentional object of thought. other On the hand, ofthe idea God can be understoodalso as for stand can God of idea The understanding…or objectively, as what is represented by this term this act. In (AT VI explicitly points out the following distinction: Let begin me by clarifications; terminological what else (if anything else there be) which exists. (AT VII 45: CSMsupremely 31) supremely intelligent, powerful, created which and both myself everything and By the term ‗God‘ I understand a substance that is i infinite and supremely perfect being: ―completeness‖. indefin an has God of idea conclude that clarity is reconcilable with incomprehensibility because to the human mind the I clarity. its to contributes which idea the of ―completeness‖ the stressing ―indefinite‖), Descartes‘ the as of God of coherency conception the defend will I (Williams). distinctness and clearness its impossible (Gassendi), and (2) that the incomprehensibility of the ideaidea isthe not compatiblethat (1) with Descartes: to objections two around centered be will paradoxically admitted its incomprehensibility. Discussion of incompatibility thisapparent somewhat and distinctly, and clearly most infinite the perceived who mind, Descartes‘

Historically, pioneers of the idea that infinity is an attribute of God are first In this section I‘m going to discuss how the idea of God as the infinite the as God of idea the how discuss to going I‘m section this In Descartes begins his inquiry by stating that he has an idea or concept of God as an as an God of or concept idea an has he that stating by inquiry his begins Descartes idea 4.1. The Cartesian Idea Of God As The Actual Infinite

there is equivocation: it may either be taken materially, as an act of my my of act an as materially, taken be either may it equivocation: is there actual

ite dimension, which is nevertheless consistent with its its with consistent nevertheless is which dimension, ite what

infinite in contra in infinite

is represented: (i) the content of a thought, or an (2) (2) an or thought, a of content the (i) represented: is – 270 c.e.).

114

nfinite, [eternal, immutable,]independent,

Descartes means by―idea‖? Descartes st with the potential infinite (or the the (or infinite potential the with st - century Jewish philosopher Philo

I 8, CSM 7)

of the infinite is is infinite the of

45

move d

CEU eTD Collection 46 visible in the morning, or as the first star visible in the evening. Although aspects (or material star last the as Venus about think can I example, For object. intentional an about thinking the involves idea material the sense this In understanding. of The concept of material idea can be (or is) used in a more abstract way, referring to the degree, highest anythe limitationin in thepositive thing.be to [my it emphasis] (AT VIIneverthelessunderstand 113,we CSMif our 81) even infinity, of case the In that offers a better understanding of the trademark argument. He says: uses the distinction between the material and objective idea in a more abstract an which can be described as being realized in a neural state, etc. However, I think that he also act independent reality of the infinite. will sometimes use the term infinite without assuming its existence. This is the way I‘m going to talk about the infin beautiful being and white being unicorn the about talk We can real. are etc., states, neural d be should real in the mind understoodshould be thein following way.For objective the example, idea of unicorn a is indexed, it is infinite, at least God of idea objective the The psychological episode of thinking takes certain time, it belongs to an individual, etc. But, God taken as an ―material idea‖ whereas the former is called an ―objective idea‖ of God. The material idea of that

This concept that I take from Thomas Vinci (19 of understanding by

which we ar Descartes explicitly ties the concept of a material idea to a psychological state, to an

istinguished from mind from istinguished

insofar it is the object of someone‘s thought. This sense of intentional reality way of understanding act of thinking e aware of the object God that can be placed in a specific time and attributed to a specific person, -

that which the act of thinking is about about is of thinking act the which that in

is not infinite, either temporally, in extension, or thought. Th

- - beinghood independent reality, the sense in which horses, chairs, chairs, horses, which in sense the reality, independent

it is negative, because it depends on our 98, pp. 94) does not imply extra e sense of ―real‖ attributed to the objective idea 115 – 46

a a psychological vehicle. The latter is called

in order to emphasize ―bracketing‖ mind

aspect aspect

- mental reality of the infinite. -

is not time nor subject subject nor time not is under w under

not noticing ity of God. I hich we are are we hich d subtle way perfection. way -

CEU eTD Collection these items are not limitless because in ‗infinite‘, everythan rather respect.‗indefinite‘ term the use I (AThere so VII limit; a 113,recognize not do CSM 81) number, or the divisibility of the parts of a quantity, there is merely some respect in which I this sense God alone is infinite. ‗infinite‘, in the strict sense, only to that in which no limits of any kind can be found; and in the between here distinction a make I Now ― held between Descartes and his objectors. by presenting detailed a discussion of (or concept the idea) of infinite, God as the which is ―infinite‖ and ―supreme‖? What is the content of such an ide construct. human a not is God of idea objective the that think to me lead ultimately will puzzle This intentionalThe object is not this in way termsin exhaustible of (mat itscontent the in not content of my I thought. argue will that this isthe not case with idea ofthe God. head,horn onits an one has it but horse, a like a looks it though: my in is object) (intentional unicorn the how content. that belong to the objective idea but not to the material idea. special attention to this distinction and argue that in case of the idea of God there are features idea‖ to pick out the intentional object. Througho conception of God, and a defense of the trademark argument. I shall use the term ―objective more abstract sense because it provides a framework for a fruitful interpretation of Descartes‘ id ―material term the use Ishall thought. a of content the with identified be also ideas) differ, their intentional object (objective idea) is the same. Thus, the material idea can

infinity‖. To Caterus he writes: Descartes distinguishes two concepts that may be labeled by a single concept concept single a by labeled be may that concepts two distinguishes Descartes Usually there is no real distinction bet What Let me now pass to the next question: what does Descartes exactly mean by by mean exactly Descartes does what question: next the to pass now me Let

am I thinking when I‘m thinking about a unicorn can be spelled out in terms d its shiny There white. is nothing the intentional that has object that is

But in cases like extension of imaginary space, or the set of

116 ween the intentional object and the intentional indefinite ut the proceeding discussion, I will dedicate

and the the and

a? I will answer these questions infinite

. I apply the term term the apply I . erial erial idea). ea‖ in this this in ea‖

CEU eTD Collection positive unde a us offer to able not indefinite the in limits of inconceivability the is why distinction; this indefinite he admits that he Descartes emphasizes that he CSM 202) merely but 15, VIIIa (AT us. by discovered be cannot unlimited, exist, they if limits, their that admit negatively respect every in be to them understand positively way same the quite certain that He can have none; second because, in regard to other thin of infinite, first because in Him alone we observe no limitation whatever, and becauseWe call we thes are particular interest here: perfections, Descartes obtains the concept of God as limitless in all perfections. cri first metaphysical the with Coupled respects. respects. For Descartes properly speaking only God is infinite in this sense all in limitless is infinity hand, other the On size. to respect with finite yet and divisible, i is apple an example, For them. of all not but thing, a of features some to only by reference to ―limitless in some respect‖ and ―limitless in all respects‖. ―Indefinite‖ applies limitless perfections.in one is this (1986), ( quantity, or mathematical concepts of infinity.spacio God is greater magnitude, tha of terms in out spelled be cannot God of infinity the But them. ―Indefinite‖ refersdistinguishes to divisibility ofDescartes matter, extensionwhich of by the world, and the seriescriteria of numbers. important three are there However, Both concepts share something in common

ratione extensione Another In In Principia

e things indefinite rather than infinite in order to reserve for God alone the name rstanding (at least) of is what impossible about the indefinite? Some critics of

meta

) but in perfection ( metaphysical criterion that shapes Cartesian understanding of God as as God of understanding Cartesian shapes that criterion metaphysical

Descartes further introduces an epistemological criterion epistemological an introduces further Descartes physical criterion that distinguishes ―indefinite‖ and ―infinite‖ is made

cannot conceive positively under ratione perfectionis

limits. The problem is how to clearly understand -

they are spelled out in terms of ―limitlessness‖. 117 stands

terion, which states that God is infinite in in is infinite God that states which terion,

that God has no limits, whereas in the ). According to Margaret Wilson n the world, not in extension gs, we do not in -

limitless in all

-

that is of of is that temporal temporal nfinitely nfinitely

CEU eTD Collection the actual actual infinity. But we have to bear in mind that the sense in 47 form of reasoning. than add them to the idea. Making God‘s perfection explicit takes an inductive, ste ―there‖ already; I can only discover perfections that were already in the idea of God, rather th I‘m that not cannot come up with a new perfection that was not already contained in the idea of God . It is I that sense the in conceivable, is perfection of addition further no that way a such in God infinity‖, which is the idea of God is it and reaches complete intellectual grasp. Essentially, potential infinity is Meditation, the in says Descartes As stopping. ever without continue can numbers adding of example, the ―infinite‖ and ―indefinite‖ in terms of ―potential infinity‖ and ―actual infinity‖. of an answer to Gass I think that at least part of an explanation of the epistemological criterion, and the beginning perceive the infinite by a negation of the finite perceive what is beyond reachof the thought always stops something at you finite, and callit ‗infinite‘ onlyyou because donot feature principal wereit true a wouldidea, it represent the infinite as it is, an You insist that your perception of the infinite is arrived at by means of ‗a true idea‘.†1 But if indefinite. For example, Gassendi presents an objection of this sort: infinit the reduced thereby and concept, indefinite negative, a merely Descartes denied the epistemological criterion altogether, arguing that the concept of God is

We can however conceive of an idea of an actually infinite number. That would be a mathematical idea of I think that ―indefinite‖ fairly accurately corresponds to ―potential infinity‖. For For infinity‖. ―potential to corresponds accurately fairly ―indefinite‖ that think I - potential infinity distinction. Infinity of God is actual infinity in all respects incomplete

when you try to imagine an infinite series of numbers, you imagine that the process

imagining that starts from finitea state is constantly increasing, so inking of God by adding perfections, one followed by another. They are all all are They by another. followed one perfections, adding by God of inking -

the one we are dealing with here here with dealing are we one the

(or open (or endi‘s objection may be found in making furthera distinction between -

ended) by definition. On the other hand, the idea of ―actual ―actual of idea the hand, other On the definition. by ended) 47 , is

your perception; hence it is quite right to say you that complete .

118 ( AT VII 296: CSM 206)

-

which God is infinite is not entirely individuated by

all perfections are contained in the idea of -

namely its infinity. But in fact your your fact in But infinity. its namely d you would hence perceive its

compound –

in all perfections. e to some kind of of kind some to e ; it has parts, that it never

p - by Third Third

- step

CEU eTD Collection affirms that he he that affirms Descartes concedes that human intellect cannot grasp infin the is enough that I understand the infinite…(AT VII 46, CSM 32) thought; for it is in the nature of the infinite not to be grasped byadditional a finite being perha and likecountless grasp, myself. way any in are It I cannot which there God of that attributes or infinite, the grasp not do I that matter not does It admits that he cannot grasp the infinite: to inability the by undermined dicto am aware of? The basic prerequisite of the trademark argument is a conscious, coherent, de re having a infinite the we conceive can how of explanation an is argument Descartes‘ are sees one, he has a sense in which one has a about infinite without being aware of it the conceive actually to suffice not does It completeness? its in infinite actual the grasp clearly articulate initial Gassendi more). add always can we that understand we indefinite the understanding in (Namely, of. short open the idea is clearly and distinctly perceived as complete, while the indefinite is by definition Descartes‘ epistemological criterion

- , how can it be a starting point of the argumen

ended, and may be understood in a mere negative se negative mere a in understood be may and ended, idea of God as the infinite. The possibility of having such an idea seems to be be to seems idea an such having of possibility The infinite. the as God of idea electronics can see an iPOD without being aware of it as being an iPOD. This is the the is This iPOD. an being as of it aware being without iPOD an see can electronics However, someone might object that the proposed distinction only helps us to more unders to us help might infinity actual and potential between distinction The

de dicto understands

(rather than de dicto de re

the idea of God. So how does all this make sense? Descartes Descartes sense? make this all does how So God. of idea the de re

awareness of the thing

grasp of it. When someone who is familiar with what iPODs grasp the idea of God. In the the In God. of idea the grasp ‘s initial question: how can our finite mind even conceive or as ) understanding of it? Even if I can be aware of the infinite

infinite. For example, someone who doesn‘t know much -

that the idea of God is positively understood

119

t if I don‘t even know whether and what I as

being an iPOD. What is nse, by reference to what it falls falls it what to reference by nse,

Third Meditation Third ite, butite, onthe other he hand ps cannot even reach in my my in reach even cannot ps as

needed for infinite, by by infinite,

Descartes Descartes - because tand tand de

CEU eTD Collection we fix our gaze on some part of the sea at close quarters, then our view can be be can view our then quarters, close at sea the of part some on gaze our fix we just as we have a confused picture of a chiliagon when we take in all its sides at once. But if that our vision a its enormous vastness; but still weare said ‗see‘to it. Infact if from welook a distance so When we look at the sea, our vision does not encompass its entirety, nor do we measure out clearly and distinctly. In the instead of embracing (grasping) the infinite, human mind can touch (understand) the infinite Similarly, tree. a touched have you cases, both In it. touch merely can you it, embracing your of putting instead illustrate, To grasping). (or conception full is impossible, Descartes admits. Nevertheless, understanding is less demanding that having a presumabl would conception full a Having it. of conception full a having without infinity understand can we that argues He conception‖. full a ―having by ―comprehending‖ or ―grasping‖ grasp the infinite? clearly distinctly and at perceived (2)all, and how(1) is compatible not with being able to God of idea the can how (1) questions; difficult two by pressed is Descartes be must this since infinity, God‘s of conceive inaccessiblereally to a mind whichcannot is, he as his the of argument that itselfexigencies insists,require the and faith argument religious his both hand, other the On great. indefinitely as God of conceive really not does actuallyhe infinite,that and so forth,objections the and to may merelyopen be have putwill togetherhe a hazythis, notionclaim o of God as an a On the one hand he has to claim (as he does) that he has a perfectly ‗clear and distinct‘ idea expression, presents the tension in Descartes view in the form of a dilemma: W Bernard 23). says that ―we cannot comprehend the greatness of God although we know it‖ (AT I 145: CSC argument for the existence ofIn God. letter a Mersenneto (1630)Descartes paradoxically ab being yet and thought, his of seems to be pulled in two incompatible directions: not being able to grasp God as the object

In the the In y require to know all about infinity: all attributes of God, their quality, etc. But that Fifth ctual infinite being combining infinite perfections in a real unity; if he does not lmost covers the entire sea at one time, we see it only in a confused manner, illiams, not very much impressed by Descartes‘ somewhat mystical mystical somewhat Descartes‘ by impressed much very not illiams,

Replies First Set Of

Descartes makes a distinction between ―understanding‖ and and ―understanding‖ between distinction a makes Descartes le to grasp enough, clearly and distinctly, to ground an an ground to distinctly, and clearly enough, grasp to le

Replies 120

Descartes gives the following example:

finite. (2005, pp. 129)

arms around a tree and and tree a around arms

as f some being

infinite be be infinite

clear and and clear

CEU eTD Collection distinguish it among other electronic devices. However, someone who is having such basic th about enough know to sufficient is it iPOD, an of out the object, and differentiate it from others. For example, in order to have a complete idea here? A plausible answer is that one has a complete idea of a thing when one is able to pick ―completene does what So idea. the in contained is what of knowledge complete Here we meet the notion of ―complete‖ that applies to the idea, which does not imply full or a thing which is bounded by no limits. [my emphasis] (AT VIIpossession 368: CSM 253)of a true and the for suffices it so lines, three within contained figure a is it that understand to triangle ignorant. is novice the which knowing and recognizing in this idea many more properties belonging to the same triangle,understands that ithas is of figure a bounded by three lines, evengeometry though geometersat are capable of novice a that doubt not do …we responds with an illustration: he instead requirement, Alston‘s satisfy would that conditions necessary and sufficient conditions‖ for understanding the infinit Thus, we can again reformulate Gassendi‘s question in the following way: what are the ―right properly credited with seeing X (1993, pp. 60). whole of any physical objec that: and distinct idea requires full grasp of the thing, then what do we understand? Alston insists understanding infinite the itself. Butif thispoint is right, if under not is infinite the of part a Understanding Gassendi‖. of idea authentic an make to enough Is thi theologians. (AT VII 113, CSM 81) all with along this, I admit and mind, human the by in taken be cannot God way, same the distinct, just as our picture of a chiliagon can be, if it is confined to one or two of the sides. In

I don‘t have to perceive the whole X in order to perceive it. I rarely, rarely, I it. perceive to order X in whole the perceive to have I don‘t

s answer plausible at all? ―It is‖, Gassendi would say, ―as much as the tip of my hair is Descartes does not give an analytically rigorous answer consisting of a list of of list a of consisting answer rigorous analytically an give not does Descartes complete idea t It see; but if I see enough of X under the right conditions, I am

Just as it suffices for the possession of an idea of the whole whole the of idea an of possession the for suffices it as Just

e? of the infinite in its entirety if we understand that it

121

an idea of a whole triangle when he he when triangle whole a of idea an e thing, to be able to recognize it and and it recognize to able be to thing, e standing orhaving clear a if ever if

, perceive the the perceive , ss‖ mean mean ss‖

is

CEU eTD Collection can be added nor taken away from it to make it ―more‖ infinite. But our our But infinite. ―more‖ it understanding, how we are thinking of God is inde make to it from away taken nor added be can objective idea) is complete; the intentional object of the idea has all perfections, and nothing material between indefinitean dimension I believe that some truth has to be conceded to Gassendi of an idea has a coherent answer to Williams; (2) Descartes criterion of truth interpreting the concept of God as find I why is that completeness; its in mind the to present is God of idea the as insofar Descartes can meet Gassendi‘s challenge; (1) the idea of God as the actual infinite is possible sufficient is that the ideais isWhat complete,be. may clearthey and distinct.whatever perfections, all in limitless is who God of idea distinct th by grasped be cannot God that view the little amount of knowledge can still be clear and distinct. Descartes can coherently maintain formulateme Descartes‘ answer Williams to as follows: knowledge comes degrees, in and order to perceive something as it is, we need not have perfect nicely points out, knowledge of the (idea of infinite) need not itself be infinite knowledge. In und Our God. of perfections all encompass not does idea such although God, of idea complete distinct idea (or understanding) complete idea, Descartes‘ a a having of sense this In it. of knowledge engineer‘s have not need iPODs of knowledge erstanding of the infinite need not extend infinitely. As St. ( Let me conclude this section with a few remarks. So far, -

can be reconciled with the impossibility to grasp all God‘s perfections. Howeve - objective idea, I would say that the object we object the that say would I idea, objective vis - nswer Gassendi to can be stated as follows. Having clear a and à - vis that

the the human mind. Bearing in Descartes‘mind distinction the actual infinite illuminating. I also think that Descartes God is limitless in all perfections suffices for a true and e intellect, although we can have a clear and and clear a have can we although intellect, e 122

finite with respect to inconceivable and

-

the idea of the infinity of God has knowledge. Consequently, let

I have defended the view that -

clearness and distinctness

are thinking about (the (the about thinking are ST , I. 12. 7) way

of of r,

CEU eTD Collection construct. I shall discuss whether this explanation is satisfactory. i the that is mind one‘s to occurs that explanation simple most The philosophical issues concerning God will remain untouched. dept the project, my of goal the mind in Bearing them. of all address satisfactorily to able not am I work, my of stage this At threatening. Scotus, St. Anselm and others, faces a lot of questions, some of them quite obvious and quite S Descartes, by defended that aware am I unproblematic. is God coherent. But that is far from having an ambition to claim that the traditional conception of has sort of an indefinite dimension. sharp than it seems on the surface because there is a sense in which the idea of infinity itself material idea. Consequently, the epistemological criterion of the infinite andinde indefiniteto due is less incomprehensibility with compatible still is completeness, and incompleteness, helps to understand how clearness of the objective idea of God due to its the d Hence, there is an indefinite dimension of the idea of God as the infinite. My interpretation of degree, highest anythe limitationin in thepositive thing.be to [myit emphasis] (AT VIIunderstand neverthele 113,we CSMif 81) even infinity, of case the In acknowledges that: clearly Descartes imagination. our beyond reach that God of perfections innumerable

istinction between the material My conclusion is that the Cartesian idea of God thus presented is at least possible and Let me now proceed with the crucial question: what is the origin of the idea of God? ss our way of understanding

- objective idea, and the distinction between completeness

it is negative, because it depends on our not noticing 123

h and extent of some theological and and theological some of extent and h

dea of God is a human human a is God of dea finiteness of the the of finiteness t. Thomas, Duns Duns Thomas, t.

CEU eTD Collection concepts of infinity. understands about actual infinity such explanations are not sufficient, then Descartes needs to (2) offer an account of what he negativa finite perfections. ways, although there are similarities; both concepts of God ultimately depend on concepts of perfecti constructed God of idea the amplification, While in proposal this call shall I unlimited. itself in is them of each where them, understand to capacity our beyond reach that perfections) of set indefinite (or perfections of amount unlimited an of conceive can goodness, …, for every relevant idea; God is actual infinity by negating limits to imperfections, and by conjoining them into an indefinite t generate to possible seems It 206). CSM 296: VII (AT Gassendi by suggested self could mind human Another the how of suggestion finite. the upon depended and relative infinite the of idea the makes which extra an to reference making without God of idea the of origin the explain could then capacity mental human mere A abstract finite perfect Faced with the two non two the with Faced A suggestion attributed to Gassendi (AT VII 287: CSM 300) is that a human mind can ons, is thereby and negative a concept. This is main difference the between the two

via amplificatione or via amplificationevia not

limited in knowledge, God is

4.2. Is The Idea Of God AHuman Construct?

The question whether the human mind could construct the idea of God ions via n via in infinitum

the infinite is a positive concept constructed by abstraction and egativa egativa - mental cause. I shall call this hypothesis hypothesis this call I shall cause. mental

are sufficient not explain to the idea of God in our mind? If

- perfection p God is no

theistic alternatives, Descart alternatives, theistic that is more and above his objector‘s amplified or negated , by amplifying goodness holiness, power, to perfection. because it reduces the infinite to a negative concept negative a to infinite the reduces it because 124 via negativa via not - invent the idea of the infinite is indirectly indirectly is infinite the of idea the invent

limited power, in Godis t limited in having p, etc. Hence, we

contains negations of finite finite of negations contains es has to tell us (1) why why (1) us tell to has es via amplificatione via

not

limited in he idea of of idea he via via .

,

CEU eTD Collection around. This a 48 The argument can be stated in the following way: enabled me to recognize my own defects by compari which being perfect more a of idea some me in were there unless perfect, wholly not was For how could I understand that I doubted or desired hone from doubt‖ Descartes argues that the idea of a perfect mind is a necessary presupposition of the two proposed ways is possible due to having a But the answer also seems to be ―no‖ Descartes‘ answer to the question ―Is the idea of God a human construct?‖ seems to be ―yes‖. concession can be extended to God of concept the to arrive can we that concedes question (2). Then position. Descartes‘ defend further and present shall I follows amplificatione ―argument from doubt‖, as Kenny (1997) calls it, which proceeds to the conclusion that God of idea prior amplification or negation. However, the very act of amplification necessarily presupposes a happil is Descartes question, former the to respect With questions. above two the in branches

Also, the idea of the infinite explains human aspiration toward intellectual perfection, not the other way 4.2.1. The Argument From Doubt To The Priority Of The Idea Of God In Wilson‘s interpretation (1986) of Descartes‘ letter to Regius (24 May 1640), Descartes

st self y willing to concede to his objectors that we can arrive to the idea of God by by God of idea the to arrive can we that objectors his to concede to willing y - reflection. rgument proceeds from the fact that we desire intellectual perfection.

and and 48 negativa . The ―priority of the idea of God‖ is defended on the basis of basis the on defended is God‖ of idea the of ―priority The .

cannot explain the origin of the prior idea of God. In what what In God. of idea prior the of origin the explain cannot

via amplificatione . Descartes insists that constructing the idea of God in 125

prior

as well, without detriment of his position. son?‖ (AT VII 46: CSM 31) –

via nega via idea of the infinite. In the ―argument that is, lacked something tiva, tiva,

but I think that such such that think I but

I will address the the address will I

and that I

the the via

CEU eTD Collection 49 replace ―perfect mind‖ in the 3 myself with God? I think that Descartes could respond in the following way. Suppose that I mind‖. teacher‘s ―my by replaceable 3 the in mind‖ ―perfect the Thus, imperfection. own my measure I can which Perhaps comparing my knowledge with my teacher‘s knowledge is sufficienta standard by a than rather mind perfect of a concept argument? Let me consider a few objections and discuss solutions. No oneself. of idea the to prior thus is God ofidea perfect mind ( can have an idea of finite or imperfect mind only by (at least an implicit) comparison with the our intellectual imperfection. The twist in the dialectics that Descartes Consequently, the standard by which we judge ourselves has to be prior than the concept of (at it The point of the argument is that we judge the degree of our own imperfection by measuring

This is also Plot 5. There 5. 4. Therefore, the idea of God as 3. In order to have a concept of an imperfect mind, I need to have a concept of a perfect 2. In order to be aware of myself 1. Obviously, I am an imperfect thinking thing. I doubt. least implicitly) against someone having all intellectual perfections by his essence his by perfections intellectual all having someone against implicitly) least imperfections that I find in myself (e.g. power, knowledge, goodness, etc.) mind ( of an imperfect mind. First, it is not clear why fore, the idea of God cannot be constructed by amplifying or negating finite finite negating or amplifying by constructed be cannot God of idea the fore, Nous inus‘ and Augustine‘s crucial presupposition in the argument for the existence of God. ).

Nous ) -

not the the not other way as Gassendi around proposes. idea The of rd -

premise by ―my teacher‘s mind‖. This would mean that the in order to be aware of myself as imperfect Nous as

The final upshot here is why do I have to compare compare to have I do why is here upshot final The an imperfect thinking thing,

more p more is prior to the idea of myself understood in (1). w, the question is how plausible is Descartes‘ Descartes‘ is plausible how is question the w, 126 erfect

(yet imperfect) mind than my own? own? my than mind imperfect) (yet

I have to have a concept introduces is that we -

would I need a rd

premise is is premise

49

.

CEU eTD Collection imperfection. concept of ultimately perfect mind it wouldn‘t be possible to have intermediatemind concepts is a concept nor the of conceptintellectual of my perfection that presupposes a concept ofSimilarly, a greater Descartes mind, then could without say thethat there can‘t be infinite regress in the objective cause of ideas. If my te necessary to admit a first efficient cause, to which everyone gives the name thereof God.‖ be an(ST. ultimate I. 2.3.) effect, nor any intermediate efficient causes; all ―But if in efficient causes it is possible to go on to infinity, there will be no first efficient cause, neither will infinite regress of efficient causes: intellectual perfection. The strategy could significantly resemble St. Thomas‘ sufficient?argum Descartes would probably say that such indefinite concept would presupposeneeds in orderthe concept to be aware of ultimate of oneself as imperfec infinite amount of imperfect minds 50 relevant only for abilithe idea of imperfection because ―the ability to use a predicate is not prior to, but identical with, argument from doubt at best shows that the idea of perfection must be without grasping all of them. idea an be would this But explanation. the in point stopping concept of imperfect mind is made by reference to an idea of the perfect mind that provides a plausibly eliminates the infinite regress in Descartes‘ advantage. The best explanation of the how can I even have infinite amount of concepts in my mind? members) of finite minds. imperfect thinking thing, I would have to be at least implicitly aware of an infinite amount (or infinite regress of more perfe more and more something against (implicitly) it measure I if and finite, still angelic is mind say angel‘s the again, then let‘s But perfection. intellectual perfection, of degree greater some of short falls that mind a mind, Descartes would raise here is that the concept of my teacher‘s mind c is a point the But mind. imperfect my of idea the to prior is mind teachers my of concept

There is a worry, However, there is another potentia ty use itsnegation‖ to (1997,pp.136). This is point legitimate, I concede, but is it

pointed out byKatalin Farkas, that such a concept of infinity which contains a potentially via negativa - and That would require -

– more perfect minds. Then, in order to be aware of myself . At best, Kenny‘s objection makes plausible the view that the

the indefinite concept, could actually be the prior concept of God that one t. In order words, why the indefinite concept would not be l difficulty with the argument. Kenny says that the 127 grasping

ct, I will eventually end up with an an with up end eventually will I ct,

the infinite. Since I‘m a finite mind, of which is plainly false. Therefore it is 50

that that I believe that Ockham‘s razor God has all perfections, perfections, all has God ent that there can‘t be simultaneous oncept of finite a

with the acher‘s

as

an

CEU eTD Collection modes (attributes). hierarchy, which ranges from the highest t 52 any other idea‖ (AT VII 41: CSM 28). It h more or less objective reality While formal reality of the material idea is not scalar, that which the idea is about can have But the unicorn is objectively (orintentionally) in virtue real of being a formally real as a mode of thought objecti reality (or reality formal The term ―objective reality‖ applies to intentional objects of ideas (objective ideas), whereas perception of the finite, and …I clearly understand that there is more reality in an infinite substance than in a finite one, infinite, or the about being of virtue in reality objective most the contains it because imperfection of argument from doubt. The idea of a be to seems There priority. discussing imperfection and perfection seems to be less plausible relation in case of of concept no had he if minds, ―intermediate‖ with perfections? And finally, how could Gassendi judge himself to be imperfect by comparison ultimate intellectual perfection, then how can there be ―intermediate‖ concepts of intellectual perfections amplificatione i

dea of the infinite and finite in that case might be simultaneous. However, in in However, simultaneous. be might case that in finite and infinite the of dea

The degree of objective reality is not vague but precisely ordered according to Descartes‘ metaphysical hence ve reality, contrasted with formal reality admits degrees. The idea of unicorn is is unicorn of idea The degrees. admits reality formal with contrasted reality, ve Nevertheless, there is an important point that has to be made in the context of of context the in made be to has that point important an is there Nevertheless, having infinite

in infinitum that my perception of the infinite, that is God, is in some way prior to my my to prior way some in is God, is that infinite, the of perception my that

, there is no such obvious simultaneity. When Gassendi amplifies finite finite amplifies Gassendi When simultaneity. obvious such no is there , , he raises them up to the infinite, step

that is myself. [my emphasis] (AT VII 46: CSM 31) - beinghood simpliciter 52

. The idea of God ―…has certainly more objective reality than Nous o the lowest degree; from infinite substance, to finite substances and - 51

in virtue of being a mental, thought episode in the mind. ) applies to ideas as mental acts (material ideas). The The ideas). (material acts mental as ideas to applies ) . Descartes says:

is the standard, and in this sense it is prior to the idea different argument for the same conclusion of the of the conclusion same the for argument different as more objective reality that the idea of an unicorn 128

Nous - by ? Simultaneity of the idea of of idea the of Simultaneity ? - step. If he had via amplificatione n object of thought.

no concept of

via via .

CEU eTD Collection here is not a real relation, but is intentionally or objectively real one. example, we can think that a unicorn that has 25 kilos is Richness of objective reality doesn‘t have directly anything to do with reality53 of the thing thought of. For 128) found in myself some idea, whether or not it was a perfection to posses it. (AT VI far35: asCSM my II For, according to the arguments I have just advanced, in order to know the nature of God, as God by similitude, by reference to perfections that both God and we have. admits that in our u ideasthe of the infinite and finite is something that Descartes explicitly acknowledges. He our understanding of does depend it on reflection of finite perfections. Inter standard itself is not dependent of us means that if perfection of idea the with simultaneous not is of imperfection idea the thesis: following the propose res plausible a is this If perfections. finite on depends itself!) standard Our construct. our is itself standard the that mean Similarly, cabbages are, have, or use concepts or judgments. (1993, pp. 41) From the fact that we use a concept to pick out cabbages as vegetables it doesn‘t follow that reminds us of an important point: of the infinite intellectual perfection by referen think that something has to be conceded to Gassendi; we necessarily think that the discussion of the argument from doubt brings to the fore an important point. I not because it follows from the argument from doubt. objectively real idea. Therefore, the idea of God is prior to any idea of finite perfection, but infinite independence of levels different exhibit about are ideas which that because

This is of cours

However, independently of the ways in which Descartes can argue for t - beinghood, the idea of a perfect mind mind perfect a of idea the beinghood, own nature is capable of knowing, I had only to consider, for each thing of which I

if we need to understand the standard by reference to finite perfections, it doesn‘t e not a real mind nderstanding of God symmetrically dependent symmetrically - independent notion of independence, but rather a mind

-

this is the -

to a certain extent 129

heavier that a unicorn having 50 kilos. ―Being heavy‖ ce to our finite perfections. However, Alston

maximum objective reality thesis. However, -

the source of source the . Such relation cannot hold because the the because hold cannot relation Such . understanding

-

we have to make reference to

all perfection perfection all

of the standard (not the the (not standard of the understand ponse, then let me me let then ponse, - dependent one.

- 53 dependence of . In virtue of of Invirtue . -

he priority, I the standard is the most most the is

CEU eTD Collection God by negating the concept of the finite, he says that it still must be true that one has a a has one that true be must still it that says he finite, the of concept the negating by God conclusions of the present section.the for But ideas. the of interdependence the about in the context of Descartes‘ whole project of the usage of predicates, as Kenny seems to suggest, but it has a richer meaning that can be found This suggests that the argument from doubt is not merely based on considerations perceives (the idea of) God by the same faculty he perceives himself (AT VII 51: CSM 35). cogitans mutual yet asymmetrical dependence between the idea of God and the idea of imperfect a is There himself. understanding of presupposition a is standard the as God of idea the connected with Descartes‘ und positive knowledge of of the idea God. Thus, understanding the idea of God is necessarily for necessary certainly are sort of this concepts Some mind. imperfect an is he that affirm Meditator and God would not be possible, and cons the between comparison the Descartes, and God between factor no common were If there "what has no part," or "the beginning of a line (ST I. 11.4.). attributes found in us is undeniable and indispensable. As St. Thomas says: our in God of unders idea the explicit making of sense the in to, arrive we which by means extent some To Descartes‘. of interpretation (1992) by reference to perfe Descartes indirectly grants that we understand the idea of God by comparison (or similitude),

For we apprehend simple things by things simple we apprehend For tanding, which is already implicitly held as a standard. Moreover, I think that our understanding of the idea of God by similitude of his his of similitude by God of idea the of understanding our that think I Moreover, When Descartes agues against Gassendi‘s hypothesis that one can generate the idea of

th at deepens throughout the ctions that we find in ourselves. This supports the following Beyssade‘s erstanding of himself, and as the argument from doubt states,

Meditations compound things; and hence we define a point to be, be, to point a define we hence and things; compound 1 30 Meditations . At some point Descartes even says that he

equently Descartes would not be able to via amplificatione via time being, I have to summarize summarize to have I being, time

. There is much more to be said

and and

negativa negativa

about the are are res

CEU eTD Collection 54 the in made conclusion theistic diff a propose will I principle, controversial and committing a such on relying of Instead idea. the in reality objective is there as idea an of cause total reality‖ whether the idea of God is prior or not. He needs the so called ―causal principle of objective bridges gap the between the idea in the mind theand world,independently questionthe of its doubt from argument the of priority best) (at idea of God perhaps must be prior, but Descartes needs more than that. Priority thesis gives a the for indispensable even not is it argument, objectors. idea of God should not)(and deny seems what obviously be to true because it is an idea of a self id an Descartes, being perfect and supreme depends on the concept of finite perfection, while the standard itself b objector(s), Descartes‘ meet to us helps negation process, then such idea can not be human invention. answer to the two non The priority thesis defended on the basis of the argument from doubt gives a straightforward ―prior perception of the infinite than of the finite, i.e. of God himself‖ (AT VII 45: CSM 31).

AT VII 42: CSM 29 Nevertheless, I that the think priority thesis plays secondary a the in trademark role 54 I believe that the distinction between the ―standard‖ and ―understanding the standard‖

which states that there must be at least as much formal reality in the efficient and

via negativa ea of an infinite substance is an idea of an ultimately independent being being independent ultimately an of idea an is substance infinite an of ea

- theistic altern

and idea elf does not suffice. Descartes still needs a causal premise that that premise causal a needs still Descartes suffice. not does elf – - amplificatione sufficient

of God in the mind, not the priority of God in reality. The The reality. in God of priority the not mind, the in God of is independent in the highest possible degree. According to to According degree. possible highest the in independent is Third Meditation Third atives: if the idea of God is prior to the amplification or source . At the end, Descartes‘ final answer is fair to his y stressing that that stressing y 131

of perfections. However, Descartes does not rgument for the existence of God. Yes, the the Yes, God. of existence for the rgument

. I am going to proceed with a logically logically a with proceed to going am I . -

we arrive (or to make explici understanding

erent defense of the Cartesian Cartesian of the defense erent –

the idea of an infinitely

of the standard standard the of t) thet)

CEU eTD Collection the objective idea of God. And when he admits that we arrive to the idea of God by means of believe that when Descartes‘ says that the idea of God exhibits infinity and ―intentionalidea‖ object‖ on the other,―objective understanding and Descartes‘hand, positionone becomesthe on more coherent. I ―content‖ and idea‖ ―material introducing way section I would like drawto ourattention to distinctionthe between the idea of God as the it sometimes out, points pp.182) (1992, Beyssade As perfection. intellectual toward aspiration human our of goal the with it conflates he sometimes and perfection, of standard the for stands argument for the existence of God. the for ground the set will it and God?‖, of concept negated or amplified the above and me to answer the question (2) ―what Descartes positively understands about God features that are not shared by both ideas sections few priority, in the distinction between the standard and understanding the standard. In the next objective idea, rather than the material idea. t question The amplification. or negation argument proceeds from the objective, rather than material idea which can be constructed by material and objective idea that is overlooked by Descartes‘ objectors. Descartes‘ trademark weaker claim than priority thesis, namely I will argue that there is a 4. 2. 2. The Argument For Distinctness Of The Material and Objective Idea Of

in which we understand God, and and God, understand we which in Descartes uses the term ― I shall strengthen the material the strengthen Ishall stands for the very faculty for producing the idea of God. However, in this this in However, God. of idea the producing for faculty very the for stands idea‖ very ambiguously. In the argument from doubt, ―idea‖

– what

the unity and incomprehensibility. This will help Such distinction is implicit in the argument from - hat needs to be answered is the origin of the the of origin the is answered be to needs hat God objective idea distinction by articulating some some articulating by distinction idea objective 132

we understand, the intentional object. By By object. intentional the understand, we

distinction between the

and unity he refers to , that is over

CEU eTD Collection simplicity God is identical with his divine to According existence. and nature of composed not is he nature; his from distinct scholastic In without detriment to his simpleness‖ ( Perfections therefore which are diverse and opposed in themselves, pre argument, assuming that such a doct Cartesian the of defense and interpretation one advance will I and Descartes, by adopted be to understand I that doctrine the of bones bare the present will I project, present the proper discussion and defense of the controversial theologic Plantinga in ―Does God Have Nature?‖, a and defended byF.W. Vallicela Alvin (1992). Since a by criticized thoroughly was view the Recently, Anselm. St. and Scotus, Duns . The most important figures associated with its formulation are states the simplicity of God is a very much discussed controversial doctrine in philosophical be remini incomprehensibility. and material idea. through idea invented humanly a having by is God understanding of way our that means he negation, or amplification In order to take a further step in understanding Descartes‘ conception of God, we have to material idea of God is preserved in virtue of their distinctive features features distinctive their of virtue in preserved is God of idea material In what follows I will explain in more detail how the distinction between the objective In St. Thomas‘ view simplicity implies lack of a real composition:

the material idea about the objective idea, his objectors focus their attention on the scent of his religious background. The so called (thomistic) terminology, God is not composed of matter and form, he is not not is he form, and matter of composed not is God terminology, (thomistic)

4. 2. 2. 1. The Unity Of The Idea Of God a material idea. W idea. material a esse rine is defensible. ST. , and his essence (

Ia. 4. 2.). 133 hile Descartes is able to transparently think think transparently to able is Descartes hile

id quod est doctrine of al doctrine is not in the ambit of ). God is his exi - St Thomas Aquinas, exist as one in God,

unity and and unity stence,

which

CEU eTD Collection 11. 1. 55 goodness, God would not have goodness. Then, it would not be within God‘s control to have If God had properties he would be dependent on them in the following way; if there were no prior condition of x's being F. (Vallicella F of instantiation x's of virtue F in x is if them: on depend will x that case the still is it instantiation, of relation asymmetrical the by properties its to them in the same way that any whole composed of parts depends on its parts. If the properties of x are constituents or ontological (proper) parts of x, then x will depend on Or, consider a more formal statement: essence these to that then it, with identical to opposed subsequent as be nature), (or essence an had would he if and he properties; then wisdom, or blessedness, knowledge, goodness, …if God were good or b way dependent some on in them. be In ―Doeswould God he have aand nature?‖ Plantinganatures, states:those in participate would God case, the were cannot be just one connected with the independence of the idea of God, and hence to its objective reality. God talk about different attributes of unicorns. attributes in a neutral way with respect to their mind there is no real composition or parts in (the nature of) God. I will talk about God‘s unity and Descartes adopts at least a ―simplicity‖ with ―unity‖ the equates Descartes see, we As 34) of the most important of the perfections which I understand him to have. (AT VII 50: CSM On the contrary, the unity, simplicity, or the inseparabi quod est and who God is, is the same as what God is. Consequently, God‘s

Actuall

The unity of perfections in God‘s infinite y, St. Thomas has an argument for the claim that simplicity implies absolute unity.For more see would be his cause. (1980, pp. 31) . Descartes says that simplicity (or unity) is a special perfection of God. of beings that fit in the genus ―perfect‖, nor in the genus ―infinite‖. If that lessed, or knowledgeable or wise by participation in the properties of weak version of the doctrine of divine simplicity which states that

, 2006)

134

- beinghood is in Descartes‘ view essentially

- independent existence, in the way lity of all the attributes of God is one - ness, then F then ness, 55 . Thus, I will assume that that assume will I Thus, . esse

is identical with his - ness is a logically logically a is ness But if x is tied

ST I can . I. id

CEU eTD Collection 57 56 can be added nor taken away from it understood as actual infinity, which essentially has no parts. It is complete. Namely, nothing pro have I As point. main the toward proceed me manifestationsone of the it. to (In ways various divine attributes is that they all identical are referencein but different sense, in referring in What the doctrine of simplicity requires one to understand about all the designations for the illuminating, orrecognized by under them different kinds variously find they descriptions under considered entity eternal single the is omniscience According to the doctrine of simplicity, what human beings call God's omnipotence or God's attributes substantively. Eleonore Stump nicely clarifi Ia.13.2.). Analogical predication doesn‘t perfectly represent God, although it predicates Him ( mode‖ higher a in and God in preexists creatures in goodness call we ―what means p good‖ is ―God However, etc. perfections‖ all has ―God is omniscient‖, called so the proposed famously 13.) I. (ST. Thomas St. God. about talk to language different Because of incommensurability the of God‘s perfections, weconsequently different need such absolute and simple attributes, ourmind can not comprehend perfections. of The source uncreated the as of thought is God because way, different a in nature God‘s different than attributes that belong to the finite. Attributes that we find in the finite belong to that God argumentation, the maximal perfection or the infinity simplicity; of God implies requires it (or not to have) certain properties. A

Cross, R. (1999). . Oxford: , 1999. But something can be added or taken away from our way of understanding God (the material idea). analogical predication However, the attributes of God are n are God of attributes the However, Bearing in mind the theological background of Descartes‘ idea of the unity of God, let

be

rather than

teaching of St. Thomas is that although reason can know God’s Simplicity, have

actual entity which is God himself or designating various various designating or himself God is which entity actual

or participate in his attributes. . The way we talk about God is to say that ‖God is good‖, ―God

ccording to my interpretation which aligns with Scotus‘ 57

(in order to make it ―greater‖) without turning actual manuscript) ot merely quantitatively but also qualitatively qualitatively also but quantitatively merely ot 135

es the view: posed, the infinity of God should be be should God of infinity the posed,

of effects ormanifestations of it.

what that

his attributes are. roperly speaking speaking roperly

God must have

ST ST 56 a

CEU eTD Collection in the proposed way that relates the idea of God to the ideas of finite perfections, th invent it by relying on our own mental faculties. Alternatively, if one cannot construct unity to have, everything that De wisdom, etc. In this case the objector‘s idea of God would seem to have everything it needs his from distinct not is goodness God‘s God: in composition real negating by God of idea This argument could be questioned by Descartes‘ o argument: following the stating by begin Let me idea. amplified objector‘s his than reality objective which the idea of God has the most objective reality. unity, or simplicity, implies lack of composition, and that is a principal perfection in virtue of ―infinite sea‖, which I understand indivisibleas an infinity composition. a into In 5. The idea of God held by Descartes‘ objectors is an id an is objectors Descartes‘ by held God of idea The 5. idea the than reality objective more has and perfect, more is unity has that idea An 4. 3. The independence of God‘s attributes contributes to objective realityof of the idea. relation real any out rules it because perfection a is composition of Lack 2. 1. Unity implies lack of composition. 6. Then, in virtue of exhibiting unity, Descartes‘ idea of God differs from his objector‘s that lacks unity. dependence. of idea Descartes‘ that argue and further, step one take I want Now idea, and has more objective reality. ―containing‖) perfections. Hence, it lacks unity.

scartes‘ idea has. Then, there is no reason to think that we couldn‘t De Fide OrthodoxaDe Fide

136

bjectors, who may simply add unity to the

St. Damascene compares God an with continu

um

of God‘s perfections. Such ea composed of (or (or of composed ea

God has has God en what is

more more

CEU eTD Collection essentially elusive; whenever we try to grasp the unity, we find ourselves with a complex idea interpretation my in o resolution its find can situation difficult indeed This only. Descartes to evident self is which statement dogmatic like more becomes reality objective most the contains constructed idea? If such feature c the idea can I defend the claim that Descartes‘ idea of God has more objective reality than the invent the idea of God. Now it begins to be really difficult to see in virtue of what feature of goodness, goodness of God is identical to wisdom of God, etc. terms of negative statements or even in positive identity statements Descartes that ―water does not freeze when it reaches temperature higher that 0 Celsius‖. Nevertheless, statements. The statement that ―water is H identity statements are about the nat negation of composition. mere a than rather attribute, positive a is unity that said be can it infinite, the conceive understand unity without grasping orcomprehending As it. far finite as the mind allowsto distinctly and clearly to enough is it solution: Cartesian the of direction the indicating dilemma will be subtly p destructive This all? at defensible be position Descartes‘ can how So comprehended. be otherwise the argument won‘t work. But Descartes insists that infinity is such that it cannot compreh be to God of nature the demands precisely opponent Descartes‘ it. of out sense make we can‘t or invention, our be might it unity? Is the doctrine intelligible at all? In short, either the idea of God is intelligible and then The objective idea of God conceived along the doctrine of divine simplicity is is simplicity divine of doctrine the along conceived God of idea objective The First of all, the doctrine of divine simplicity is stated in terms of identity relations, and still runs into the unfortunate dilemma again. If unity the stated be of God can in f the distinction between the objective and material idea of God. resent throughout the rest of the chapter. For now, let me begin with

annot be named, Descartes‘ assertion that the idea of God ure of a thing 2 O‖ tells us more about water than the statement ended by raising the question what unity is, is, unity what question the raising by ended 137

-

they are informative more than negative -

then i -

God is identical with his t seems that we could

-

CEU eTD Collection u 58 think. The distinction between the material and objective idea itself. object intentional short off such because only idea falls idea material the that something is there that aware become can Descartes object. the object of thought that is by reflection known to be more perfect than one‘s understanding of understanding is defective has an and indefinite dimension, bu all and unity, Infinity, unity. the how imperfect and composite idea of God way as a understand to infinitely God. supreme an has mind human that say to is This parts. no has understanding of object the whereas objective id ofidea God is infinite (intentional object) has no parts. While the material idea of God is not infinite, the objective no is there God of idea) (objective etc.), negation of finitude, their or and/or ideas of identity whereas relations, in Descartes‘ omnipotence, omniscience, (e.g. perfections of conjunction is a there objector, Descartes‘ (ma constructed the In 81). CSM 113, VII (AT negative..‖ we if even understand it to beinfinity, positive of in the highest degree,case neverthelessthe our way―In of understanding it issays: Descartes what emphasize to have I again, things‖. Our understanding of God, or the way in which we think of unity is c compound by things simple apprehend ―we out, points Thomas St. As say. to so fingers, of nicorn

However, ―is‖ should be taken in an (intentional) objective sense, not literally. Similarly, we can say that a simplicity consisting of negations or ideas of identity relations. It sleeps through our our through sleeps It relations. identity of ideas or negations of consisting simplicity

we are thinking of God is white. y focus on the material idea and rightly conclude that it can easily be our construct. ea, not of the material idea, because our understanding of God is compositional,

58 . The feature of unity God ofin perfections is feature thus a of the

I believe that believe I -

the material idea - itself become can transparent or perfections do not apply to our material idea; our way of of way our idea; material our to apply not do perfections

composition whatsoever since actual infinity as as infinity actual since whatsoever composition

Descartes‘ objector(s) don‘t fully appreciate the the appreciate fully don‘t objector(s) Descartes‘ 138 -

is somewhat an imperfect wayof reaching

-

the way in which we think and what we terial) idea of God held by by held God of idea terial) t t it applies to the intentional diaphonus , revealing the omplex. Once That

CEU eTD Collection and unified perfections creates the ―cloud of unknowing‖ in the depths of the ―queen among incomprehensibility? is what of question the answer to try me let Now incomprehensible. is it because minds human by invented be not could God of idea objective the objectors; Descartes to answer God of and (ii) Consequently, not. is latter the and incomprehensible material the to idea objective the of irreducibility and God is incomprehensible. would amount to unintelligibility. In the next section I will discuss in which way the idea of incomprehensibility coherency such no were there If 194). pp. (1992, way coherent a in idea, but it is more like a ―filtering principle‖ that retains some attributes and excludes ot idea of God objective idea of God is enoug about God from a distance without embracing him, but rather by catching a glimpse. G that understanding by it reach origin of the simple objective idea. Although we cannot grasp what the unity is, we can still potentialmind‘s compose to complex ideas. The interesting question is how to explain the objective idea that needs to explained, be not the materi the of infinity the is It God. of idea material the than rather objective the from proceeds Incomprehensibility Incomprehensibility is of key importance because: (i) it helps us to see the distinction the of understand can we little the incomprehensible, and elusive being Despite God of existence the for argument trademark the that believe I Consequently, –

because of its incomprehensibility 4. 2. 2. 2. The Incomprehensibility

of the idea of God pertaining to his innumerable, inconceivable, h to ground a coherent position. In Beyssade‘s view Descartes‘ od must be thus simple. The mind is capable of thinking thinking of capable is mind The simple. thus be must od 139 –

is not a generative rule for constructing an al al idea; weknow enough the about

Of The Idea Of God incomprehensibility grounds an an grounds incomprehensibility -

the former is is former the

hers

CEU eTD Collection perfections. perfections. undermine to Cartesian view that such (indefinite) imperfect knowledge of God‘s attributes is not sufficient is God that which concerns their amount and qualit suggested was it 1) vis perfections God‘s of indefiniteness (section the of because incomprehensible discussions previous In compatible? perfections, whatever they are. How are thes claims that he has a clear and distinct understanding of the idea of God who is limitless in all such is" it "whether know can it but is"; it "what know to as so form, unity is, remains incomprehensible. St. Thomas says that ―reason cannot r was argued that one can have a clear idea negative counterparts. its from it distinguish to criteria proposing by incomprehensibility of account epistemic Jean defend will I follows, what In territory‖. ―dark criteri any have don‘t we and incoherency, any hide potentially can that concept a as negatively, understood is incomprehensibility because precisely is connotation negative a has often ―mystical‖ why reason the part) capture the meaning in which (the idea of) God is incomprehe not do meanings suggested these all that argue will I etc. ―contradictory‖, ―incoherent‖, Mo God‖. of ―non e.g. connotation, epistemic negative ―hiddenness a have can with or ―incomprehensibility‖ ―indefiniteness‖ with equated incomprehensibility thus presented has a negative function of mind as clearness, incomprehensibility seems to veil mind‘s access to the idea. The notion of in itself impresses completeness, its in mind, the to idea the of presence While ideas‖. Let me begin with what was told about the incomprehensibility (of the idea) of God. It However, indefiniteness does not bear impact on the sense in which God is is God which in sense the on impact bear not does indefiniteness However, completeness

of the idea of God as the actual infinite infinite actual the as God of idea the of y that outstrips our imagination. I have defended the that on of truth that can enlighten the way into that that into way the enlighten can that truth of on e e negative and positive epistemological claims 140

God‘s perfections are in unity. But

- Marie Beyssade‘s (1993) positive positive (1993) Beyssade‘s Marie limiting nsible. I think that (at least in

knowledge. It can be - and - each up to simple

- - limitless in all all in limitless such. Descartes Descartes such. à re generally, generally, re - vis our mind, mind, our vis - sensical‖, sensical‖, what

the the the

CEU eTD Collection 59 negative incompr incomprehensibility there is something coherent to understand, which is quite different from conceive something. Such a distinction reflects in our present debate. In the case of positive i.e. indefinite, and infinite distinguishing account of negative incomprehensibility brings us back to the issue of epistemic criterion of The sections. previous the in explain to tried I have as reality, objective most the contains all that can be said. However, the idea of God is not only coherent, but about it. What the mind clearly perceives is that such idea in sensical, counterparts: ―non made by reference to attributes of the intentional object itself. by which we can distinguish positive and negative incomprehensibility (indefinitness) can be incomprehensible, not solely because of our epistemic constraints. The metaphysical criterion perfections are shortsightedness to parallel naturethe of thing the itself. sense in The God which is positively incomprehensible is not I‘m shortsighted, it is because of me that the ob us which limits knowledge. Let me positively

However, I don‘t deny that they are related. ; because; of ourcognitive limitations. For whenI example, see don‘t something because There is also a difference between positive incomprehensibility and its negative negative its and incomprehensibility positive between difference a also is There In case of indefiniteness

incomprehensible; it rather presents an instance of a coherent, or contradictory there is not much that we can positively understand understand positively can we that much not is there contradictory or coherent, incommensurab ehensibility in which there is nothing that can be positively understood. - sensical‖, ―incoherent‖

59

le . The idea of God is incomprehensible because God‘s God‘s because incomprehensible is God of idea The . (the idea of) explain the difference.

with ours. It is because of God‘s attributes that the idea is

,

―contradictory‖, and so on. When an idea is non

God is negatively incomprehensible because of positive understanding and not being able to to able being not and understanding positive 141 ject is out of my visual reach, not because of

cannot be true

negative the mo incomprehensibility . That‘s pretty much st true idea

-

it -

CEU eTD Collection 61 60 incomprehensible because of (1) our own cognitive defect (it is not indefinite), or because of believe, is the right way of under I way‖, ―middle The between. in somewhere is incomprehensibility and presence, marks hiding like someone who is playing hide and seek. While ―hiddeness‖ marks absence, clarity ―Hiddenness‖ here stands in contrast with ―presencerange. t perceptual seeker‘s his from hides seek and hide plays who someone example, And that is why the idea of God is as it is which God is positively incomprehensible. If the idea were hidden it would not display itself incompre incomprehensibility can be distinguished from contradiction. to comprehend something does not imply that its nature contradicts reason. Hence, positive have a complete grasp, full conception or account of the thing (its nature). But not being ab to means Descartes, and Thomas St. Leibniz, for I comprehend, as far as comprehend, To do not comprehend it. (Cave, 1995, pp. 464) Something is above reason if we have some partial or analogical und Positive incomprehensibility concerns that which is above reason: an obscure Mystery, it would be a manifest absurdity. (1985, pp.If 115)it happened that the Mystery was evidently co conception of mystery in the something being ―contrary to reason‖ and something being ―beyond reason‖, and to Leibniz‘s

Beyssade (1 This was explained is section 1 60 Let me sum up what it was concluded so far. The idea of God is not positively positively not is God of idea The far. so concluded was it what up sum me Let Now, there is also another possible way in which God can be thought of as negatively presentThe issue can be

. The idea of God hensible, that can be called ―hiddenness of God‖. But again, this is not the sense in 993, pp. 87)

is –

Theodicy it suffices to have an idea in its completeness

standing it.

addressed by St. to reference Thomas‘ distinction between not

where he says: incomprehensible in the sense of being ―hidden‖. For

142 ntrary to an evident principle, it would not be 61 that

present to the mind

God has all perfections. o the mind‖. But the idea of God is not

erstanding of it, but we

of Descartes clearly.

le

CEU eTD Collection distinctness corresponds to negative knowledge, it way; is aboutsimple whatquite a isin it puts Curley E. distinctness? is what of question the with begin reveals (rather than compatible but also positively (explanatory) The related. claim is that incomprehensibility of the incomprehensibility, clarity and distinctness, and bring clarity, suffices to sustain the distinction. Let me now extend on the relation between positive and incomprehensibility positive between bond the emphasizes which criterion epistemic comprehensibility, reference makes which to the attribute of the intentional object that cannot be positively present to the mind. meansout, opposite from presence to the m be present to the mind in its completeness as the actual infinite. Hiddeness, as I have pointed incoherency) is opposed to clarity. The indefinite, which is by definition incomplete, cannot(indefinit incomprehensibility negative whereas mind, the to idea context. Namely,incomprehensibility positive comes clarity, with presence the with of the this in neglected be can‘t that aspect the is God of idea the of Clarity feature. epistemic important thing that marks positive incomprehensibility is its relation with another positiv God‘s perfections,positively is and theirGod unity. of idea The incoherent). incomprehensiblenot because ofis the nature of the(it intent idea the about understood be to positive nothing is there (3) because or hidden), not is (it mind the to absence (2) its Meditations Beyssade (1993) claims that clarity and incomprehensibility are not merely merely not are incomprehensibility and clarity that claims (1993) Beyssade negative and positive distinguishes that criterion metaphysical the Thus, One too. criterion epistemic an is there criterion, metaphysical such from Apart .

hides) the idea of God

its very

ind. Andind. finally, is not incoherence something 143

distinctness ional object

the topic back to its original context (or differentiation). –

not the incommensurability

in the idea. eness, hiddeness or or hiddeness eness,

So let me , theand

of e

CEU eTD Collection incomprehensible. As Beyssade (1993) concludes, the truth rule of ideas, name In understood be to order in itsinfinite many more which I cannot grasp. (AT V 357: CSM IIIprovided 379) the fact that God is not grasped by me ‗It is eno beinghood. Descartes says that: can be coherent only if it is incomprehensible, only then the idea can truly be of the infinite Perhaps this distance is only real in the mind, and not in reality. Nevertheless, the idea of God incomprehensibility is a true apprehension of the incommensurable distance of th 88). pp. (1993, king‖ the to relation unequal his of knowledge true the subject Beyssa says majesty‖, of mark a is ―Distance king. the of distance (infinite) incommensurable illustration that Beyssade mentions, incomprehensibility is actually a true representation of an transcendence us gives distinctness hand, other the On composed. not is God that incomprehensible because of inco and degree highest the to distinct both is God of idea the Thus, attributes. has than rather According the to doctrine of divine simplicity something God has pre like quantity its of because only not goodness, God‘s with explained by reference to God‘s incommensurable attributes. I cannot compare my goodness matter and form, not created, etc. The reason why the idea is distinct to its highest degree is For example, distinctness of the idea of God enables us to infer that God is not involved in being that thing not oris what aand is thingwhat seeing of of matter that a thing…is a kind. of idea distinct (1986: and clear a 169Having

On the one hand, distinctness gives us negative knowledge of the finite, for example, de, ―and to decrease familiarity is not to disclose knowledge but to disclose to a a to disclose to but knowledge disclose to not is familiarity decrease to ―and de,

ugh that I understand the infinite‘. I mean, that it is sufficient for me to understand

I judge also that there are in him all perfections that I clear

-

that God is God that

(if he exists) beyond of what we can comprehend. To use an an use To comprehend. we can what of beyond exists) he (if

mmensurable attributes contained in the idea of God.

in order to understand God in very truth and as he is, - beinghood, the idea of God mustbe 144

but also because of its its of because also but - 70)

ly understand, and also knowledge of God’s God’s of knowledge - properties; he is both ly their clarity composed of

e infinite clear andclear Positive quality

- . .

CEU eTD Collection God that lacks composition and cannot be mastered by the mind? objective idea. We are left with an open question: what is the origin of the objective idea of the of explanation an not is idea material the up made have could we how idea is not reducible to or exhaustible by the material idea. Therefore, objector‘s explanation and positive incomprehensibility is not lack of any understanding, it follows that the objective two featuresthese notare merely n object is having something that my material idea lacks understanding to the object of my understanding, then merely by reflection I can tell that the m shift I when However, up. it made have I because about amplificatione constructed be may which latter, The God. of idea material a having that idea objective the to belongs that feature a is incomprehensibility Positive distinct thiscontext. in are ofGod idea objective andmaterial idea meaningful for the Cartesian epistemic project, I have the background to articulate how the argument for the existence of God. the ground to use further Iwill which system, Cartesian the in incomprehensibility of role explanatorily and gives related, it us a essentially but compatible, merely not are incomprehensibility and clarity how explains and distinctness is fulfilled not After clarifying the concept of positive incomprehensibility as cohere as incomprehensibility positive of concept the clarifying After , as Gassendi suggest, is comprehensible; I certainly know what is the idea idea the is what know I certainly comprehensible; is suggest, Gassendi , as in spite

egations, unity merelynot is negationof a composition,

of

framework for understanding positive the epistemic

but precisely 145

because of –

incomprehensibility and unity. Since y attention from my way of of way my from attention y

incomprehensibility. This via negativa via

one attends to by by to attends one origin and nt

or of the the of via via

CEU eTD Collection As Beyssade (1992) points out, making the objective idea of God God of idea objective the making out, points (1992) Beyssade As of God is ultimately When elusive. that we wethink grasp all wefind it, is a complex idea. get closer to God in our thought, there is always more that escapes reas (material idea) cannot exhaust everything there is in the objective idea itself altho perfections, God‘s of aware be to able are we enumeration; by is God of idea objective the of unity the in perfections understand we intellectually which by method The another. What is available in maki as a defect or limitation in that perfection. (1992, pp. 190) ( it is a kind of sieve o each starting from a given perfection which is augmented or raised up to the infinite. Instead important points andmost thethe main argument.between connection the deepen me Let incomprehensibility. from argument originate in a human mind. Only the infinite being could have placed su doesn‘t it that is explanation plausible a then reality, objective most the has and coherent, is God of idea the that Given nonsensical. or incoherent is it unless comprehensible, of all. This demands an explanation. If the human mind invented it, it would be in principle amplification, but the former cannot even be comprehended, although it is the most true idea rather than the material idea. preserved in virtue of unity and positive incomprehensibility, which pertain to the objective

intelligere …is not a matrix which generates an infinite set of possible definitions of the divine nature, ugh wecan never master his nature our in thought. way The weunderstandobject the Beyssade‘s interpretatio the of presuppositions establish to served sections previous in discussion The is idea objective and material the between distinction the of interpretation The ) of supreme perfection, and eliminates anything which is conceived ( f filter which lets through anything which belong to our understanding 4.3. The Argument For The Existence Of God ng the unity

The latter can be constructed by the human mind by negation or n is that the objective idea of God: explicit

146

is induction

-

passing from one perfection to

ch idea in our minds. explicit on. The objective idea –

as much as we by inductive inductive by concipere )

CEU eTD Collection summarized in the following way: also coherent, and the most perfect ideas of all, the argument from incomprehensibility can be positive incomprehensibility would collapse into negativeOtherwise, incomprehensibility.content. positive has and coherent, is God of idea Descartes‘ that show first thus balanced with a be supported by some clear and distinct knowledge. It is necessary that incomprehensibility is balanced with elements of positive epistemology. Knowledge of God‘s transcendence must episte negative somewhat of element The distinct understanding of God, which aligns with Descartes‘ strategy discussed in section 1. way‖―middle the between two horns of dilemma the ismaintain to sufficientlya and clear (2005, Williams as notion, hazy a be to seems then God of idea The about? I talking am what then predicates, negative) (or relative of terms in exhausted not is God of idea the of content the if dilemma: the of horn second the by presented o beware to I have However, God. of unity the of incomprehensibility positive from is proceed to needs proof the which by way right the Thus, dilemma. destructive my would God of idea objective the decompose or construct to and God comprehend to able being that concede I 46). II CSM 66: VII (AT things‖ on necessity any impose not does though by thought, our distance, but it cannot be embraced by the mind. If we could ―master‖ the nature of God in sea, the unity of God is seen through the window of our mind somewhere ―out there‖ in the method (enumeration, negation, etc.), is n

certainly that we indicate havecould made it is up,which pointthe made explicit in After (hopefully) showing that the idea of God as the infinite is not only possible but

fully understanding it, God‘s existence could not be proven because ―my ―my because proven be not could existence God‘s it, understanding fully

coherent intelligible idea of God. That is why I have invested effort to

ot the same as mology (positive incomprehensibility) has to be be to has incomprehensibility) (positive mology 147

constructing

pp. 129) pp.

it. Like vastness of the

points out. The The out. points

f the threat threat f the

CEU eTD Collection whatever is constructed by the mind can be molded by the mind, e.g. by synthesis, analysis, 51: CSM 35). But the simple a for I am plainly unable either to take away anything from it or to add anything to it‖ (AT VII of God‖ is quite simple, Descartes says that the idea of God‖ was not invented by me either; the trademark argument is crucial. The ―argument from compl importance on incomprehensibility as much as he emphasizes unity, its role in this version of can be the origin of the objective idea of God. Although Descartes actually doesn‘t put much According to the present argument, from the unity it follows that no finite mind whatsoe without at the same time making me recognize what they were. (ATcould VII 50: CSM 34) any cause which did not also provide me with the ideas of the other perfections; for no cause And surely of idea the the unity his perfections of all not could have been placed me in by Descartes argues the following: is also a plausible argument to rule out the possibility that the id finally, we would be able to comprehend the infinite and it, from away something take or add to able be would we authors its were we If mind. conclusionThe (3) in is that the idea of God as the infinite cannot inventedbe by human a 4. 3. 2. 1.

have made me understand the interconnection and inseparability of the perfections perfections the of inseparability and interconnection the understand me made have craftsmen mark stamped ―the on is his work‖.God of (AT VIIidea 51:CSM II 35)objective the that is explanation best The actual infinite. the of idea objective of the source the be cannot intellect human the Therefore, incomprehensibility thesis [ incomprehensible. positively and elusive is unity Such perfections. [ a the as God of idea objective The Unity thesis

rgument implies a problematic and ambiguous assumption that

]

]

148

ctual infinite ctual - beinghood (at least in principle). There eteness of the unity of the idea ea of God has many causes. - beinghood is a unity of of unity a is beinghood

Positive Positive of the the of

ver

CEU eTD Collection The only n assumptions of the arguments are problematic. How do we justify the ―bridging‖ principle? dependent on the premise about a certain existence of God outside of the mind. Also, Descartes‘ causal argument proceeding from the idea of God to the thing the on necessity its imposes which mind, the in perfection a as found is Existence con example, For mind. the outside God of existence the just presented is quitehave I different from argument The around. way other the not thought, on itself imposes object existenc God‘s proving of way right the that requirement Descartes‘ satisfies Cartesian position, and grounds the version of the trademarkenha argument. incomprehensibility positive and clarity between harmony univocitystrict of by attributes the turning man a God writ into large‖ content to transfer them [our attributes], in amplified for God, would which into the ensure would ―we God of attributes the of distinctness no were there If out. pointed already us to argue for the existence of God. both unity incomprehensible idea we could infer extra any of existence the from things, hazy many too of existence prove could argument the distinction between positive negative and incomprehensibility is indispe the why is this And incomprehensible. negatively is it because but time), the at perfect may actually (it perfect it‘s because not away, taken or added be can nothing which or addition, etc. However, it is conceivable that a drug experience might produce an idea to The argument from positive incomprehensibility of God has a specific virtue; it it virtue; specific a has God of incomprehensibility positive from argument The was it as together, come must incomprehensibility positive and clarity both Also, and on - arbitrary ways will be ultimately circular. However, my approach circumvents

positive incomprehensibility of actua via

causal principle t a priori

hat bridges the mind similitude

proofs that look for clues in the mind that point to - mental existence of its object. Thus, I think that 149

of what is in the mind and in reality. Both l infinity are special features that enable - reality gap is made by inference sider St. Anselm‘s argument. argument. Anselm‘s St. sider nces coherency of the the of coherency nces

(1993, pp. 90).The nsable. Otherwise, e is when the the when is e seem be be

CEU eTD Collection of an idea raised by Gassendi. I defended Descartes‘ argument from doubt to the effect that construction constructed by human mind, either fulfilling Descartes‘ criterion of truth. This, I believe, answered Williams‘related objectionexplanatory also but as well. incomprehensibility, with consistent merely idea the of distinctness and clearness that Beyssade with together concluded have I understood. positively is God of infinity that criterion epistemological Descartes‘ for criterion additional an as disting infinite potential and actual between distinction the negative, or indefinite. I presented a coherent answer that Descartes makes, and I emphasized obje Gassendi‘s addressed I all. proceeds from the idea of God as infinite. I have discussed whether such idea is coherent at challenge and the force of impossibility of grasping the idea of God implies that Godthe exists. I believe that hereseem, lies the may it as Paradoxically idea. the of explanation best the God existence the existence, it is rather something that we don‘t com his infer us helps that thought) in necessity or perfection, (his God about comprehend we it represents. The gap is rather circumvented by way of actually don‘t argue to bridge the mind I incomprehensibility, from argument the In premise. ―bridging‖ the about difficulties uishing indefinite and infinite because completeness of the actual infinity explains explains infinity actual the of completeness because infinite and indefinite uishing In this chapter I have defended a version of the Cartesian trademark argument that that argument trademark Cartesian the of version a defended I have chapter In this Furthermore, I have discussed the question whet question the discussed have I Furthermore, via negativa

or the argument. via amplif Conclusion Of Chapter IV ction that a clear and distinct idea of the infinite is at best best at is infinite the of idea distinct and clear a that ction via negativa icatione - world gap by way of similitude of the

150 presupposes a prior idea of a perfect being

or

prehend about the idea of God that makes amplificatione di ssimilitude; it is not something that her the idea of God could be be could God of idea the her

, which were alternatives – idea and what

of God is not not is God of it is actually actually is it -

a

CEU eTD Collection ultimately the most legitimate reason to think is thatGod of we couldidea the not inventcomprehend to it. inability Our incomprehensibility. positive and unity objective idea of God cannot be reduced to or ex reference human to perfections, and constructing the My idea. argument main was that the constructed). I have emphasized Beyssade‘s distinction between making the idea explicit by thought of by way of having a material, imperfect and finite idea of Descartes‘ objective idea of God which is infinite and exhibits unity of perfections, which is t a logically weaker claim to ground the trademark argument, namely, the distinction between standard that one needs to have in order to state ―I am imperfect mind‖. However, I proposed he material and objective idea. I have argued that the trademark argument proceeds from from proceeds argument trademark the that argued I have idea. objective and material he 151 hausted by the material idea because of its

God (possibly humanly

CEU eTD Collection a serious challenge for internalist conception of perceptual knowledge. These were my principle that finds its plausibility in the anti of the reflectively accessible aspect of the perceptual experience, through t vulnerable to skepticism. Insofar we are required to rule out skeptical hypotheses on the basis skepticism premises leads to skepticism, I stress that the view does not entirely acknowledge the force of perception is correct because the common factor view with additional epistemological skepticism. Although the traditiona subjective indistinguishability thesis. In this way all theories of perception are vulnerable to logically weaker version of the skeptical argument, which relies on a mere epistemological common factor view or any theory of perception. This con common factor, suggests that the skeptical argument is not necessarily committed to the metaphysical possibility. However, the discussion on disjunctivism, the theory that denies the sense everything seems the same perceptually, while reality is radically different. In this way, both shar plausible arguments that lead to the ―veil of perception‖ problem. If there is a common factor traditionally viewed as culpable for raising the skeptical threat. I concluded that they are quite response to the dream argument based on Sosa‘s theory of dreams. perceptual knowledge. I proposed a Cartesian response to the deceiver argument, and a ed by genuine perception and hallucination then it is metaphysically possible that - datum theory and intentionalism, enable the skeptical hypothesis as In chapter two I considered the a In this dissertation

because it is not the case that I discussed the plausibility of the skeptical challenge regarding list diagnosis of the skeptical argument and the nature of C rguments from illusion and hallucination which were only ONCLUSION -

luck requirement, skepticism follows. It remains theories which posit a common factor are 152

clusion was supported by a

a genuine he closure

CEU eTD Collection because we argument from comprehensibility seems more appropriate: we can know that God exists impose necessity on things, as Descartes says, the somewhat paradoxical dialectics of the kind of res must be perfect. However, I tried to take a different path. I didn‘t base the argument on some weaker logical basis than Descartes himself did. He argued that the cause of a perfect idea four primarily aimed at responding the skeptical deceiver argument. response to the dream argument plausible, the argument for the existence of God in chapter promises a compromise b combines both internalist and externalist elements is worth of further exploration because it wakefulness, outweighs the epistemic situation in the bad case. I believe that this view which the epistemic situation in the waking case is not symmetrical with the dreaming case; although everything I just said, it would seem the same, and I would be wrong. However, the overall tell that my presence experience lacks the ―dream property‖. Of cours dreaming then why bother with it? If I‘m awake then I can make competent judgments; I can propositions, but the dream argument is also rendered a mere dreamt argument. So, if I‘m externalists would typically do. If I‘m dreaming then I don‘t have knowledge of ordina of wakefulness, I tried to use the asymmetry between the dreaming and waking case as knowledge that th that is faithful to Sosa‘s view. Since the dream argument, in my understanding, targets our perception. findings concerning the relation of the Cartesi seeming In the third chapter I discussed the dream skeptical argument and proposed an answer In the fourth chapter I de emblance of what is in the mind and what is in reality. Since the mind cannot

cannot

is the same, my competence and the e criterion is satisfied, rather than undermining the possibility of a criterion comprehend God. This approach is reminiscent of a notoriously etween the two epistemological intuitions. Since I found such a fended the Cartesian trademark argument on somewhat an skeptical challenge and the nature of 153 fact that experience has the ―mark‖ of

e, if I were dreaming

ry

CEU eTD Collection religiously motivated. In th to the original context in which the Cartesian skepticism arose in the first place. the sole criterion of truth is subjective, in t know. The skeptical argument indeed poses a serious problem for perceptual knowledge if the basis of perceptual experience alone, I can rule it out on the basis of something else that I my epistemic situation. Although I am not able to rule out the skeptical erro for all I know, I might be a victim of the argument is false However, if I know that God exists, then I know that the first premise of the skeptical of the know on the basis of my present expe lucky. For example, it may seem to me that I‘m writing a conclusion now, but as far as I knowledge that the skeptical hypothesis is false renders every perceptual belief reflectively claim that ―I don‘t know that I‘m not deceived with perceptual knowledge. The first premise of the closure based skeptical argument was the one is that the infinite mind is puzzling and unique features that demand an explanation. I believe that the most plausible argue that positive incomprehensibility and elusiveness of the idea grounds the view that we have an idea (comprehending) and positive understanding by having a clear and distinct idea of God, and apparently negative epistemological element. Descartes‘ distinction between grasping how can we know that He exists? I believe that the right answer has to b controversial question both in philosophy and theology: if God is wholly transcendent then deus deceptor Finally, the trademark argument directly addresses the skeptical challenge concerning The skeptical deceiver argument that undermines perceptual knowledge is essentially . If I know that God exists, and that He is not a deceiver, then it is false that, . If I cannot rule this out then I don‘t have perceptual knowledge. e very beginning of the the source of such idea. rience, I might be deceived about it, I might be a victim that deus deceptor he perceptual experience itself. This brings us back God is infin 154 Meditations

respect to my senses‖. Lack of . Knowledge that God exists changes ite without knowing

Descartes asked himself that

God is infinite are alance the positive what r - possibility on

He is. I

CEU eTD Collection have any guarantee for their reliability, there would be no benevolent God who created us with our perceptual cognitive facul that our perceptual cognitive faculties lead to truth as their ultimate goal. If there were no than God Himself, anything less than an intelligent benevolent mind creator who guarantees deceiver challenge that aims at perceptual knowledge, this criterion cannot be anything less dependence about skepticism, namely, the extent that it confirms that the truth must be ―out there‖. This is an optimistic way to think our minds. Thus, radical skepticism concerning senses is actually fruitful for epistemology to then we would be able to know things about the world solely truth cannot be in our minds. If it were solely in our minds, that would be cause for worry; for accessible to the subject. The skeptical paradox just confirms that the perceptual criterion of outside of our minds if we rely solely on our perceptual experience, on what is reflectively Rotterdam, have made. Skepticism about the senses teaches us that we cannot know things same line of conclu finds the criterion of truth external to the subjective experiential certainty of the believer. only convincing argument that could end the the original historical and theological context in which Cartesian skepticism emerged, the argument requires a religiously motivated response genuine epistemic possibility, what can cast him out? Such a religiously is rendered conceivable only if God is a deceiver. But when the beli most obvious and convincing things. And what can be more convincing than one‘s perceptual whether it could be that God created him in such a way that he goes wrong even about the ef ―I have two hands‖, or ―I‘m sitting by the fire‖? Radical skepticism concerning senses In this dissertation I have revived the classical solution, and I am ready to confirm the

on an extra sion that some of my predecessors, religious thinkers like Erasmus of - experiential criterion of truth. But given the nature of the skeptical

as a mean which ultimately leads to truth Phyrrhonian crisis could be an argument that 155

God exists and He is not a deceiver. In telos on the basis of the content of . Without God creating us, we deus deceptor ties, then we wouldn‘t –

to recognizing our

inspired destructive enters as a

CEU eTD Collection dep then, the Cartesian skeptical challenge leads to recognition of a truth suggests that without God perceptual knowledge seems unattainable. In a surprising way attain knowledge, argument lies. If we agree with the skeptic that knowledge cannot be lucky, then in order to skeptical argument brings to the fore. And this is where the intuitive force of the skeptical accidentally so. But knowledge doesn‘t al might have true reliably produced perceptual beliefs, but without a guarantee, only endence on God. .

we need a guarantee, and an anti

low room for luck. This is the point that the 156

- luck condition. Skepticism ultimately –

our epistemic

CEU eTD Collection Crumplin, M. Cross, R. (1999). Crane, T.: Cottingham, J. (1993). (< Religious Studies Cave, E. (1995). ―A Leibnizian account of why belief in the Christian mysteries is justified‖. or.pdf Action, Knowledge - 13/12/2009) available at < - Byrne A., and Logue H.: Descartes Blumenfeld, D. and J. B. (1978). ―Can I know that I am not dreaming?‖. In M. Hooker (Ed.), Cambridge Companion to Descartes - Press, 85 Descartes Rene of Science and Philosophy the on Essays - Beyssade, J. Descartes’ Meditations Baier, A. (1986).―T Austin, J. L. (1962). Aquinas, T., London: Cornell University Press. Alston, W. P. (1993).

(2008) ―Either/Or‖. In F.Macpherson & A. Haddock (Eds.), (2009) (1993) ―On The Idea of God: Incomprehensibilities or Incompatibilitie (1992) ―The Idea of God andProofs of His Existence‖. In Cottingham J. (ed.), http://www.js - - -

(2005) ―The Problem of perception‖. In (2001) (2004) > accessed: 06 /11/2009) Knight, website: < http://www.newadvent.org/summa/index.html> Fathers of the English Dominican Province, Online Edition Copyright 2008 by Kevin Systematic Theology Disjunctivism: contemporary - 94 . Baltimore&London: The John Hopkins University Press.

-

Elements of Mind

―How to think and talk about M.: http://web.mit.edu/logue/www/disjunctivismintroduction.pdf Summa Theologica - A. (2008). ―Descartes: God as the idea of infinity‖. tor.org/stable/20019774

, Vol. 31, No. 4, 463 Duns Scotus . Ox Sense and sensibilia he he idea of true the God Descartes‖. in In A. O. Rorty (ed.), Perceiving God: The Epistemology of Religious Experience. A Descartes Dictionary ford: Oxford University Press. (< . Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 359

, Vol. 10, No. 1 . Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.

. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

, Second and Revised Edition, 1920 Literally transla

. New York: Camb BIBLIOGRAPHY -

473 readings > accessed: 29/10/2009 ) . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

the non

157 . Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy . Cambridge: MIT Press. (Introduction

Oxford: Blackwell publishers.

- existent‖. A manuscript. ridge University Press, 174 http://mit.edu/abyrne/www/either

. New York: Oxford University University Oxford York: New . Disjunctivism: Perception,

In ternational Journal of

s?‖. In S. Voss (ed.), > accessed

-

Ithaca and 200

Essays on .

- ted by

389

-

The The

CEU eTD Collection Francis. Eternal Truths and the Cartesian Circle: a Collection of StudiesKennington, R. (1987). "Descartes' evil genius". In W. Doney (Ed.), _PS04.pdf < Printed in the Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers. (WebsiteJohnston, M. Janowski, Z. (2000). James, W. (1905). Boyce Gibson. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd. Husserl, E. (1931). Hume, D. (1968). Huemer, M.: Meets the Cognitive and Social Knowledge Goldman, A. I. (1979). ―What is justified belief?‖. In G. Pappas (E identity‖. by knowledge knowledge: ―Mystical (1993). C. K. R. Forman, Aristotelian Society, Farkas, K. (2006). "Indiscriminability and the sameness of appearance". University Press. (1985). R. Descartes, University Press. DeRose K. and Warfield T. (1999). the in infinity of concept the and Cathars, the Catholics, ―The (1997). A. A. Davenport, Damascus, J., Meditations Curley, E. (1986). ―Analysis in the ‗Meditations‘‖. In A. O. Rorty (ed.),

http://homepages.wmich.edu/~dilworth/The_Obscure_Object_of_Hallucination_JohnstonM - -

(2001) ―Sense Data‖. In (2001) Publishers. American Academy of Religion thirteenth century‖, Green and Co.

> accessed 13/12/2009 . Dordrecht: Reidel. Reprinted in Goldman, A. (1992). . Berkeley: University of California Press. Skepticism and the Veil of Perception

(2004). ―The Obscure Object of Hallucination‖. De Fide Orthodoxa

Treatise of Human Nature The Varieties of Religious Experience. Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology

CVI Part II, 205 Cartesian Theodicy

The philosophical writings of Descartes of writings philosophical The Isis Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy , Vol. 88, No. 2, 263 ) , h

Skepticism: A Contemporary Reader ttp://www.newadvent.org/fathers/3304.htm - 25. , Vol. 61, No. 4, 705 . Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. . Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 158

- . Lanham: Rowm 295

London and New York: Longmans, -

738 Philosophical Studies . New York: Taylor &

Liaisons: Philosophy . Cambridge: Cambridge Cambridge Cambridge: . d.),

.

an & Littlefield

Justification and

Essays on Descartes’ . Translated by W. . N Proceedings of the ew York: Oxford Journal of the the of Journal

120.

R.

CEU eTD Collection No.3 Okasha, S. (2003). ―Skepticism and its Sources‖. Philosophy and Phenological Research 67, neta/In%20Defense%20of%20Disjunctivism.pdf (< Knowledge Neta, R. Moore, G.E. (1959). Menn, S. (1998). 93. - Knowledge Argument‖. In A. Haddock and F. Macpherson (Eds.), - Reality Subject, Thought, and Context - 455 - McDowell, J.: < Martin, M.G.F. (2004b). ―Uncovering Appearances‖, unpublished manuscript. Website: Journal of P Macarthur, D. (2003). ―McDowell, Skepticism, and the Veil of Perception‖. Malcom, N. (1959), 0Independence,%20and%20Epistemic%20Priority.htm < Ludwig, K. ―Skepticism, Logical Independence, and Epistemic Priority‖, Philosophical Quarterly Le Morvan, P. ( Leibniz, G. W. (1985) Encyclopedia of Philosophy Kenny, A.: Lau, J. (2004). "Externalism about mental content". In E. N. Zalta (Ed.),

(1995) ―Kn (2008) ―The Disjunctive Conception of Experience as Material for a Transcendental (1987) ―Singular Thought and the Extent of Inner Space‖. In McDowell and Pettit (Eds.), (1982) ―Criteria, Defeasibility, andKno http://www.homepages.ucl.ac.uk/%7Euctymfm/chapters.htm http://www.clas.ufl.edu/users/ludwig/web/users/kludwig/Papers/Skept http://philosophy.unc.edu/people/faculty/ram

- - - 79

(1997). (1968).

Cambridge. MA:

(2008). ―In Defense of Disjunctivism‖. In . Oxford: Oxford University Press. , F. Macpherson & A.Haddock (Eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.

hilosophy owledge and the Internal‖. Descarte Descartes

2004). ―Arguments Against Realism and How to Counter Them‖. Descartes and Augustine Dreaming Philosophical Papers

Theodicy 81, No.2, 175 s: A study of His Philosophy . New York: Random House.

41, no. 3, 221 Harvard University Press. .

. Reprinted in McDowell (1998). . London: Routledge&Kegan Paul Ltd. . La Salle: Open Court Press. - 190 - 234 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research wledge‖.

. London: George Allen& Unwin Ltd. . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

159 -

> access Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Proceedings of the British Academy

, Bristol: Thoemmes Press. Disjunctivism: Perception, Action,

> accessed 05/11/ 2009 ed 13/12/2009)

> accessed 13/12/2009) Meaning, Knowledge and

icism,%20Logical%2

The Stanford

Australian

American

55, 877

68,

-

CEU eTD Collection SOPHY.pdf (< - Press. Oxford Handbook of Epistemology - Philo - Sosa, E.: Smith, A.D.: Rorty, R. (1980). Rogers, G. A. J. ( Reynolds, S. L. (2000). ―The Argument from Illusion‖. NOUS 34:4, 604 Robinson, H.: Putnam, H. (1999). Pritchard, D. (2005). Prichard, H.A. (1950). Price, H.H.(1932). Popkin, R. H. (2003). Plantinga, A.: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Pappas, G. (2005). ―Internalist vs. Externalist Conceptions of Epistemic Justification‖. In Otto, R. (1923).

(2004 (2002) ―Tracking, Competence, Knowledge‖.and In P. Moser (Ed.) (2005) ―Dreams and Philosophy‖, http:// ------

(2008) ―Disjunctiv (2008) (2002) (2000) sophical Association (1994) (1980) (1980) (2008) ―The Failure of Disjunctivism to Deal with ‗Philosophers‘ Hallucinations‘‖.

- A manuscript. University Press. University Press. th to Relation Its and Divine the Press, 181 (Eds.), 5) ―Dreams and the Cogito‖. In www.philosophy.ox.ac.uk/__data/assets/pdf_file/0017/908/DREAMS_AND_PHILO

> accessed 13/12/2009) The Problem of Perception Warranted Christian Belief Perception

Does God Have a Nature? a Have God Does

Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, and Knowledge. The Idea of the Holy: An Inquiry Into the Non 1975). ―The Veil of Perception‖. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature - Perception 204 The Threefold Cord Epistemic Luck The History of Scepticism Knowledge and Perception

. London: Routledge.

ism and Discriminability‖. In A. Haddock and F. Macpherson

79 , issue 2, pp. 7 . Londo . New York: Oxford University Proceedings and Addresses of the American

. New York: Oxford University Press. . n: Methuen & Co. Ltd.

. New York: Columbia University Press. . Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. John Locke Lectures . New York: Oxford University Press. e Rational. e

- The Aquinas Lecture, Milwaukee: Marquette Marquette Milwaukee: Lecture, Aquinas The 18 160

. New York: Oxford University Press. . Oxford: Clarendon Press. Mind

J. Harvey (trans.), New York: Oxford Oxford York: New (trans.), Harvey J. . Oxford: Blackwell.

84, No. 334, 210

,

- rational Factor in the Idea of Oxford: Oxford University

The - - 224 621

CEU eTD Collection (ed.), Ithaca (NY)/ London: Cornell University Press,Wolter 148 A. B.(1990). Wilson, M. D.: Williamson, T. (2000). Williams, B. ( Wainwright, W. (1995). Vinci, T. (1998). Vallicella, W. F.: ( Thompson, B. J. ―Representationalism and the Argument from Hallucination‖, draft Stump, E. ―God‘s simplicity‖. A manus Press. Stroud, B. (1984).

http://faculty.smu.edu/bthompso/hallucination.html - - - -

(1992)"Divine Simplicity: A New Defense". (2006) (1986 ) ―Can I be t (1978).

Los Angeles: University of California Press, 339 indefinite)‖. In A. O. Rorty (ed.), Divine Simplicity Descartes 2005).

Cartesian truth

The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism The Philosophical Theology of Descartes: The project of Pure Inquiry Knowledge and its Limits . London: Routledge & Kean Paul. Reason and the Heart he cause of my idea of the world? (Descartes on the infinite and . Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. . New York: Oxford University Press. cript. Essays on Descartes’ Meditations

. Ithica, NY: Cornell University Press. 161 . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Faith and Philosophy > accessed 13/12/2009) John Duns Scotus - 359 - 162 . London, New York: Routledge.

. Oxford: Oxford University . In M. McCord Adams

9, 4: 508 . Berkeley and

– 525