The Nature and Uniqueness of Material Value-Ethics Clarified

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Nature and Uniqueness of Material Value-Ethics Clarified The Nature and Uniqueness of Material Value-Ethics Clarified Vlastimil Vohánka Palacký University Olomouc, Czech Republic ABSTRaCT. Although material value-ethics was introduced into philosophy at least a century ago, confusion still persists as to what it implies. This arti- cle offers some clarification. It states how material value-ethics stands opposed to formalistic ethics, commonly – though perhaps wrongly – attributed to Kant. The resulting analysis allows us to establish a combination of features that give material value-ethics an advantage over deontological, consequentialist and other perspectives, regardless of the hermeneutics issue. KEYWORDS. Material value-ethics, formalistic ethics, consequentialism, Kant, Dietrich von Hildebrand I. INTRODUCTiON ax Scheler published the first part of his Formalism in Ethics and MNon-Formal Ethics of Value in 1913. The second part followed in 1916. Though particularly seminal for the tradition of non-formal or material value-ethics (die materiale Wertethik), this work did not propose any clear or sufficiently broad clarification of material value-ethics as such. I contend here that the main representatives of material value-­ethics are the same in this regard. Hence one of the goals of the present con- tribution is to provide a broad clarification. My second aim is to deter- mine what is unique about the ethics thus conceived. Before I pursue this plan, however, a few words about the representatives in question and the genuine lack of proper clarification seem appropriate. Material value-ethics emerged as a substantial part of the German- Austrian school of ethical intuitionism, a school founded by Franz ­Brentano and Alexius Meinong. It was developed more fully by Edmund ETHICAL PERSPECTIVES 24, no. 2(2017): 225-258. © 2017 by Centre for Ethics, KU Leuven. All rights reserved. doi: 10.2143/EP.24.2.3218003 ETHICAL PERSPECTIVES – JUNE 2017 ­Husserl, Adolf Reinach, Max Scheler, Dietrich von Hildebrand, Nicolai Hartmann and Aurel Kolnai, and continued by Hans Reiner, Manfred Frings and Peter Spader. Josef Seifert, John Crosby, Fritz Wenisch, Eugene Kelly, Philip Blosser and Graham McAleer have continued to develop it. Yet neither the main authors themselves nor the obvious reference works settle on a common denominator, i.e. a tenet or meth- odology shared by all material value-ethicists and nobody else. I will devote the remainder of this introduction to a series of examples. First, distinguished sources such as The Phenomenological Movement (Spiegelberg 1994), Encyclopedia of Phenomenology (Embree 1997), Phenomenol- ogy of Values and Valuing (Hart and Embree 1997) and the Routledge Com- panion to Phenomenology (Luft and Overgaard 2012) never pause to sum- marize on the nature of material value-ethics. Secondly, the accounts provided by Scheler and Spader are too nar- row for material value-ethics in general. Scheler taught that material value- ethics is one in which the morally good is the will to realize what one recognizes as a value – or as a higher or the highest value –, where the value itself is ‘material’ or ‘non-formal’. The morally bad is the will to realize what one feels to be a disvalue – or a lower or the lowest value –, where again the value or disvalue are material (1913-16/1973, 25-26; 53-54). Here a material value is a value of something relatively specific or determinate as compared to something general or abstract, such as the value of saving a drowning child as opposed to the value of doing what- ever is obligatory. A higher value is one that is more noble: more noble in the intuitive sense in which, for example, many people regard intel- lectual brilliance as more noble than good health. But Scheler’s outline does not fit a significant number of other material value-ethicists who regularly deny that all will to realize what one recognizes as a higher value is good. Often one should distribute medication rather than books, they would say, even if the value of intellect is higher than the value of health (Hartmann 1926/2002b, 51-53; 155-156; Reiner 1951/1983, 255; Kolnai 1977, 179-184; Blosser 1995, 143; Kelly 2011, 77-78). — 226 — Ethical Perspectives 24 (2017) 2 VLASTIMIL VOHÁNKA – MATERIAL VALUE-ETHICS CLARIFIED Turning to Spader we read that Scheler’s ethics is “[...] an ethics of nonformal values, values ‘seen’ through special acts of ‘feeling,’ not rea- son [...] a fundamental rejection of formal, rational ethics” (2002, 23). Again, this is too narrow for material value-ethics as such. Authors like von Hildebrand (1953, 10-13; 191-196) regard values as seen by the intel- lect rather than feeling, and as responded to by feeling only afterwards.1 Hartmann, Frings and Kelly, to conclude, appear to move in the right direction but are in need of further clarification. To Hartmann, material value-ethics says that “moral laws” and even “everything which ought to be” is “conditioned by [...] and refers to” consciousness of “concrete” values in which “the values themselves originally do not have the charac- ter of laws and commandments” (1926/2002a, 166-167; 179-180). But in what sense should we understand ‘conditioned’ and ‘refers’ here? This, at least, is hard to determine. To Frings, material value-ethics “[...] reveals intuitive cognition of values” – values in a way “independent in their being and of their realiza- tion by man” – and maintains that “[...] if such values are realized by any one person, correct moral acting is the result.” On the other hand, in “[...] formalistic ethics (Kant) the source of morally correct acting is placed into reason, and ‘Sittlichkeit’ exists in a moral categorical principle” (1996, 75-76). Independence does not mean that values hang somewhere in the void, but rather that true value judgements like “pleasure is intrin- sically a value, or more valuable than pain” are true independently of the realization of the valued things or anyone’s pursuit thereof.2 However, widely diverse actions realize some value or other, but not all of them are correct. Frings also does not say what standard should be acceptable for all material value-ethicists. For Kelly, material value-ethics is “(1) non-formal [...] and involves a profound criticism of Kantian ethical formalism” and “(2) founded in a phenomenology of the values themselves, that is, the content, available in intuition, of such values as trust, utility, friendship, or even the Aristo- telian virtues” (2008, 1). This ethics claims that “[...] moral consciousness — 227 — Ethical Perspectives 24 (2017) 2 ETHICAL PERSPECTIVES – JUNE 2017 is directed upon an objective realm of ideal values in which norms and virtues are ‘founded’” (2011, 7). The supposed objective ideality is noth- ing other than the alleged independence to which Frings alludes. But as before, how are we to understand ‘founding’? The clearest hint Kelly provides is made in connection with Scheler and von Hildebrand. These two, he notes, “ [...] attempted to found obligation in the values them- selves and human moral goodness in the hearing and responding to the call of values” (2011, 116). Kelly illustrates this point: [W]hen I experience [...] the kindness of some action of a person towards some other person or other sentient creature, the [...] value of kindness is given to me, and I respond to it in a specific act of affirma- tion. Similarly, once I grasp the validity of a demonstration of a theo- rem in mathematics, I naturally respond not only with intellectual assent, but also with a determination to use the theorem with confi- dence as a premise in further demonstrations (2011, 116). The talk of response to values, I will argue, is fitting, but it still needs clarification. And in doing so, I will draw especially on remarks of von Hildebrand, since he is more explicit than others about responses to values. Thus I will elaborate on Kelly’s suggestion – certainly one worth exploring, given his credentials as a leading scholar in material value- ethics – about what exactly this ethics is. I opt here for Kelly’s proposal not only because it is accessible to explanation, in contrast with others, but also because I find it confirmed in other authors than just Scheler and von Hildebrand. I submit the result as a refined hypothesis about a com- mon denominator for all writers in material-value ethics. This result will enable me to say why this ethics is noteworthy. II. WHaT MakES aN ETHiCS MaTERiaL? Ethics is any attempt to clarify or typologize moral phenomena, to defend which things should be ascribed which moral labels, or to describe the noetic structure of our moral awareness and reasoning. What is ‘material’ — 228 — Ethical Perspectives 24 (2017) 2 VLASTIMIL VOHÁNKA – MATERIAL VALUE-ETHICS CLARIFIED about such an attempt? The short answer: opposition to formalistic eth- ics. Material value-ethicists (whatever their common denominator) define themselves against Kant, whom they regard, rightly or wrongly, as a for- malist. So let us return to Kant himself. In the first section of his Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (1785/2011, 15; 17), Kant says that morally good acts of will are good ‘without limitation’, ‘without any limiting condition’, ‘in themselves’, or ‘unconditionally’. This means they are good in every instance and in a way neither enhanced nor diminished by their combination with anything else. In contrast, desiderata such as knowledge, wit, confidence, persistency, health, riches, power, and honour are enhanced in their goodness if pursued with a good will, or diminished or even bad if pursued with a bad will. So what is it about any morally good act of will that suffices to make it morally good? Many will be familiar with Kant’s dismissal of actual effects. As he insists, some morally good acts of will have poor actual effects. A good will is good not because of what it effects, or accomplishes, not because of its fitness to attain some intended end, but good just by its willing, i.e.
Recommended publications
  • Hegel and Aristotle
    HEGEL AND ARISTOTLE ALFREDO FERRARIN Boston University published by the press syndicate of the university of cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom cambridge university press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb2 2ru, uk 40 West 20th Street, New York, ny 10011-4211, usa 10 Stamford Road, Oakleigh, vic 3166, Australia Ruiz de Alarcón 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town 8001, South Africa http://www.cambridge.org © Alfredo Ferrarin 2001 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 2001 Printed in the United States of America Typeface Baskerville 10.25/13 pt. System QuarkXPress™ 4.04 [AG] A catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Ferrarin, Alfredo, 1960– Hegel and Aristotle / Alfredo Ferrarin. p. cm.–(Modern European philosophy) Includes bibliographical references and index. isbn 0-521-78314-3 1. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 1770–1831. 2. Aristotle – Influence. I. Title. II. Series. B2948 .F425 2000 193–dc21 00-029779 ISBN 0 521 78314 3 hardback CONTENTS Acknowledgments page xiii List of Abbreviations xv Introduction 1 § 1. Preliminary Notes 1 § 2. On the Object and Method of This Book 7 § 3. Can Energeia Be Understood as Subjectivity? 15 part i the history of philosophy and its place within the system 1. The Idea of a History of Philosophy 31 § 1. The Lectures on the History of Philosophy: Editions and Sources 31 § 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Hans Reichenbach
    Coming to America: Carnap, Reichenbach and the Great Intellectual Migration Part II: Hans Reichenbach Sander Verhaegh Tilburg University Ich habe das Gefühl, dass gerade Amerika mit seinem Sinn für das konkrete und technische mehr Verständnis haben müsste für meine naturwissenschaftliche Philosophie als Europa, wo noch immer die mystisch-metaphysischen Spekulationen als die wahre Philosophie angesehen werden. ⎯ Reichenbach to Sidney Hook, January 31, 1935 II.1. Introduction In the late-1930s, Rudolf Carnap and Hans Reichenbach, arguably the two most prominent scientific philosophers of their time, emigrated to the United States, escaping the increasingly perilous situation on the continent. Once in the U.S., the two significantly changed the American philosophical landscape. In this two-part paper, I reconstruct Carnap’s and Reichenbach’s surprisingly numerous interactions with American scholars throughout the 1920s and 1930s in order to better explain the transformation of analytic philosophy in the years before and after the Second World War. In the first part of this paper, I reconstructed Carnap’s contacts with American philosophers throughout the 1920s and 1930s. In this second part, I focus on Reichenbach’s interactions with the American philosophical community before he moved to the United States. I argue that some of Reichenbach’s work from the mid-1930s⎯ in particular Experience and Prediction (1938)⎯ can be better understood if we take into account the context in which it was written. This paper is structured as follows. After an overview of Reichenbach’s ignorance about Anglophone philosophy in the first stages of his academic career (§II.2), I reconstruct his ‘American turn’ in the early 1930s, focusing especially on the reception of his philosophy by a group of New York philosophers (§II.3).
    [Show full text]
  • Remembrances of Martin Heidegger in Marburg
    (Originally Published in Philosophy Today, Swnmer 1979, Pages 160-169) (© 1979 by the Messenger Press. Reprinted by Permission) REMEMBRANCES OF MARTIN HEIDEGGER IN MARBURG elisabeth hirsch According to Heidegger's own bered houses and the castle on a hill, words the years of his teaching career Marburg exuded a romantic· atmos­ he enjoyed most were those in Marburg phere. In addition, in a few minutes from 1923-1928. These were also the one was deep in nature and so Hei­ best years of the Weimar Republic. The degger could enjoy his customary af­ German mark was stabilized, the econ­ ternoon walks. If one was lucky to omy greatly improved and the cultural meet him, he would always stop for life reached a high point. Dance, music, a short talk. theater, the visual arts and poetry Today Marburg has 1;),000 students flourished as never before and created and half of them are Communists. But an atmosphere of excitement among when Heidegger was there, Marburg young people. And the immensely pro­ had only 3,000 students; their contact ductive intellectual and artistic actiY­ with thl' professors was close. Marburg ity did not fail to have an impact on was rather notorious for hE'r many the academic community. The French dueling fraternities; the students be­ writer Paul Duhamel was greatly im­ lansing to them were mostly conserva­ pressed by the German universities. In tiYes in politics. In opposition to them a lecture he delivered at Marburg Uni­ the liberal students founded the aca­ versity he remarked: "There are said demic association; if my memory is to be seven world wonders but the Ger­ correct, Heidegger attended some of man universities must be added as the its meetings.
    [Show full text]
  • Nicolai Hartmann and the Metaphysical Foundation of Phylogenetic Systematics
    Biol Theory (2013) 7:56–68 DOI 10.1007/s13752-012-0077-8 HISTORICAL ESSAY Nicolai Hartmann and the Metaphysical Foundation of Phylogenetic Systematics Frederic Tremblay Received: 22 May 2012 / Accepted: 16 November 2012 / Published online: 5 January 2013 Ó Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research 2013 Abstract When developing phylogenetic systematics, the be by traditional metaphysics. This view is characteristic entomologist Willi Hennig adopted elements from Nicolai of philosophers such as Bergson, Heidegger, Whitehead, Hartmann’s ontology. In this historical essay I take on the and Nicolai Hartmann. Hartmann harnessed and applied task of documenting this adoption. I argue that in order to this thesis to the analysis of the categories of reality, build a metaphysical foundation for phylogenetic system- including biological categories. The ensuing ontology atics, Hennig adopted from Hartmann four main meta- made possible the metaphysical foundation of temporally physical theses. These are (1) that what is real is what is andprocessuallyorientedscientific theories. Phylo- temporal; (2) that the criterion of individuality is to have genetic systematics is the method of classifying biological duration; (3) that species are supra-individuals; and (4) that categories according to genealogical relations on a tree-like there are levels of reality, each of which may be subject to diagram. This method was originally developed by different kinds of law. Reliance on Hartmann’s meta- the entomologist Willi Hennig to classify biological
    [Show full text]
  • Russian Contribution to the International Kant Studies from the Late 19Th Century Until the Present Day: an Analysis of Publications in “Kant-Studien”1
    CON-TEXTOS KANTIANOS. International Journal of Philosophy N.o 4, Noviembre 2016, pp. 35-55 ISSN: 2386-7655 Doi: 10.5281/zenodo.163988 Russian Contribution to the International Kant Studies from the Late 19th Century until the Present Day: An Analysis of Publications in “Kant-Studien”1 ALEXEY SALIKOV∗ Immanuel Kant Baltic Federal University of Kaliningrad, Russia; Free University of Berlin, Germany Abstract This article gives a general characteristic of the publications of the Russian philosophers in the oldest Kantian Journal “Kant-Studien”. The study embraces the entire period of the existence of this magazine, from the very beginning down to our days. In general, after compiling all materials related to Russia published in “Kant-Studien”, I became aware of get a picture of a significant presence of Russian philosophers in this periodical. This gives me a good reason to conclude that even if the impact of the Russian philosophical thought on the international Kant studies was not decisive, then, at least, it was tangible. This influence was due to the phenomenon which was later called the “Silver Age of Russian philosophy”, as well as the phenomenon of Russian emigration, arising as a result of wars and revolutions in Russia and the exodus of the Russian philosophers of the West, where one of their main initial shelters was Germany. Keywords Kant, Russian Kant Scholarship, Russian philosophical thought, Russian emigration, Kant-Studien. The history of the reception of Kant's philosophy in Russia is more than two centuries old and is well researched today. The role of the German university thought in the formation and development of the Russian understanding of Kant's philosophical system is also well 1 This article was written with support from the Russian Foundation for the Humanities (RGNF), Project No.
    [Show full text]
  • Nicolai Hartmann
    Nicolai Hartmann Roberto Poli Nicolai Hartmann (1882—1950) was one of the leading German philosophers of the first half of the twentieth century. While Hartmann was in many respects a classic philosopher and wrote book-length works scrutinizing and developing all the major fields of philosophy, including the philosophy of history, ethics and aesthetics, his leading interest was ontology. He systematically developed the most comprehensive and rich theory of categories ever presented, which set out his thought on ontological modalities, the difference between the spheres of real and ideal being, the fundamental categories of reality, the ontological levels in which reality is structured, and cosmological categories. 1. Introduction ............................................................................................................................................... 2 2. Preliminary sketches .................................................................................................................................. 4 2.1. Philosophical method ........................................................................................................................ 4 2.2. Knowledge from an ontological standpoint ...................................................................................... 5 2.3. Being qua being ................................................................................................................................. 5 3. Ontological categories ..............................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Hartmann's Realist Ontology
    Translator’sIntroduction: Hartmann’sRealistOntology 1Hartmann in Context Despite an international upsurge of interest in the philosophyofNicolai Hart- mann (1882–1950) in recent years, his work is still almost completelyunknown to the English-languagephilosophical audience.Widelyrespected duringhis life- time, he was roughlythe same ageaspositivists Moritz Schlick and Otto Neu- rath, the existentialist Karl Jaspers, Catholic philosopher Jacques Maritain, and the Spaniard Jose OrtegayGasset.Neo-Kantian Ernst Cassirer and phenomenol- ogistMax Scheler wereeight years older than Hartmann, while the philosophical rock stars of the twentieth century,Ludwig Wittgenstein and Martin Heidegger, wereseven years youngerthan him (Harich2004,6). In his own era, he was not unknown to those in the English-speaking philosophical landscape with some interest in Continental philosophy. In his 1930 survey of Germanphiloso- phy, the youngDeweyan-Marxist Sidney Hook claimed that Hartmann was “in- teresting without being oracular,instructive without pedantry,and profound without being obscure,” and predicted that he “will soon be greeted as Germa- ny’sleading philosopher” (Hook 1930,156–57). It is no doubt difficult for readers to imagine that someonesocompletelyunknown todaymight have been consid- ered by anyone to be a “leadingphilosopher” of the time. Hartmannwas of Baltic German descent and an independent thinker who decisively struck out on his own in his groundbreaking 1921 Grundzüge einer Met- aphysik der Erkenntnis (Basic Features of the Metaphysics of Cognition)wherehe repudiated the Neo-Kantianism of his former teachers Hermann Cohen and Paul Natorp in Marburg. The fact that he wroteenormous systematic works with an analytical style and with athorough familiarity with the history of philosophy made him not easilyclassifiable.
    [Show full text]
  • Building a New Thursday Circle Carnap and Frank in Prague
    Building a New Thursday Circle Carnap and Frank in Prague Adam Tamas Tuboly Institute of Philosophy, Hungarian Academy of Sciences; University of Pécs, Pécs, Hungary [email protected] 1 Building a New Thursday Circle Carnap and Frank in Prague1 1. Introduction When Carnap wrote a short intellectual autobiography for Marcel Boll in March 1933, he mentioned two things about Prague: (1) that he became a professor at the German University in 1931, and (2) that he worked on his Logische Syntax der Sprache until 1933.2 These things are well known. Carnap spent, however, five long years in Prague, just like he did before in Vienna: so, one might ask, whether (1) and (2) indeed sufficiently characterize his Prague- period. Philipp Frank (1949, 45), who was there for almost twenty years when Carnap arrived, wrote that “[f]rom 1931 on we [i.e. Frank and Carnap] had in this way a new center of ‘scientific world conception’ at the University of Prague.” This seems to be much more than what Carnap claimed. Actually Carnap might have had great expectations regarding Prague: the First Conference on the Epistemology of the Exact Sciences, where the Vienna Circle made public its manifesto, was organized by Frank there in 1929; five years later in 1934 the Preliminary Conference of the International Congresses for the Unity of Science was hosted again in Prague. As Jan Sebestik (1994, 205) claimed, “Prague has always been one of the important European centres of learning and of science, and it has often been the forerunner of vast currents or movements, both intellectual and political.” The city also had a long tradition of scientifically oriented philosophical thinking: through Bernard Bolzano, members of the Brentano-School (such as Anton Marty, Tomáš G.
    [Show full text]
  • Title: Nicolai Hartmann and the Transcendental Method Author
    Title: Nicolai Hartmann and the Transcendental Method Author: Alicja Pietras Citation style: Pietras Alicja. (2021). Nicolai Hartmann and the Transcendental Method. "Logic and Logical Philosophy" 2021 (online first), doi 10.12775/LLP.2021.001 Logic and Logical Philosophy (2021) DOI: 10.12775/LLP.2021.001 Published online: January 12, 2021 Alicja Pietras Nicolai Hartmann and the Transcendental Method In memoriam Professor Andrzej J. Noras (1960–2020) Abstract. One of the most often explored, repeatedly interpreted, and rec- ognized again and again as a valuable achievement of Kant’s philosophy, is his transcendental philosophy, a new methodological approach that as Kant believed will allow philosophy (metaphysics) to enter upon a secure path of science. In this paper, I explore Nicolai Hartmann’s reinterpretation and development of this methodology in both the historical and systematic context of his thought. First, I will deal with the Neo-Kantian’s under- standing of the transcendental method as a starting point of Hartmann’s own understanding of it. Then I will analyze in detail his only paper devoted entirely to the problem of the method, (Hartmann, 1912), to present how he understands the necessary development of this methodology. I will claim that despite the fact that Hartmann following Kant never denied that the real essence of philosophy is the transcendental method, he tried to show that this methodus philosophandi cannot be reduced to the Neo-Kantian’s understanding of it. He argued that the core of all true philosophical and scientific research is the transcendental method, but only insofar as it is accompanied by two other methods that are needed to complete it: de- scriptive and dialectical method.
    [Show full text]
  • Hans Reichenbach
    [Forthcoming in the Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy] Coming to America: Carnap, Reichenbach and the Great Intellectual Migration Part II: Hans Reichenbach Sander Verhaegh Tilburg University Ich habe das Gefühl, dass gerade Amerika mit seinem Sinn für das konkrete und technische mehr Verständnis haben müsste für meine naturwissenschaftliche Philosophie als Europa, wo noch immer die mystisch-metaphysischen Spekulationen als die wahre Philosophie angesehen werden. ⎯ Reichenbach to Sidney Hook, January 31, 1935 II.1. Introduction In the late-1930s, Rudolf Carnap and Hans Reichenbach, arguably the two most prominent scientific philosophers of their time, emigrated to the United States, escaping the increasingly perilous situation on the continent. Once in the U.S., the two significantly changed the American philosophical landscape. In this two-part paper, I reconstruct Carnap’s and Reichenbach’s surprisingly numerous interactions with American scholars throughout the 1920s and 1930s in order to better explain the transformation of analytic philosophy in the years before and after the Second World War. In the first part of this paper, I reconstructed Carnap’s contacts with American philosophers throughout the 1920s and 1930s. In this second part, I focus on Reichenbach’s interactions with the American philosophical community before he moved to the United States. I argue that some of Reichenbach’s work from the mid-1930s⎯ in particular Experience and Prediction (1938)⎯ can be better understood if we take into account the context in which it was written. This paper is structured as follows. After an overview of Reichenbach’s ignorance about Anglophone philosophy in the first stages of his academic career (§II.2), I reconstruct his ‘American turn’ in the early 1930s, focusing especially on the reception of his philosophy by a group of New York philosophers (§II.3).
    [Show full text]
  • Nicolai Hartmann's Philosophy of Nature
    NICOLAI HARTMANN’S PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE: REALIST ONTOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHICAL ANTHROPOLOGY Keith R. PETERSON Colby College –––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– Abstract: One significant thinker who developed a philosophy of nature that is both realist and inherently pluralistic is the long-neglected 20th century German philosopher Nicolai Hartmann. His nature philosophy is grounded in his “critical ontology” and theory of the “stratified” structure of the real world. This structure reveals the particular place of the human being in the world, from which humans engage in the natural and historical process of learning about the world, socially and scientifically. This view challenges many currently held relativist and post-Kantian epistemologies of the sciences. The point of departure for Hartmann’s philosophy of nature in his ontology and philosophical anthropology is discussed, and the issues of realism and the growth of knowledge in history are brought into relation with some reflections of Miguel Espinoza on these themes. Keywords: Nicolai Hartmann, Ontology, Philosophical Anthropology, Philosophy of Nature, Cognition, Strata, Stratification, Categories, Realism, Miguel Espinoza. –––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– Scripta Philosophiæ Naturalis 2 : 143 - 179 (2012) ISSN 2258 - 3335 Keith Peterson, Nicolai Hartmann’s Philosophy of Nature 144 § 1.— Who is Nicolai Hartmann? In his 1930 survey of German philosophy, the young Deweyan-Marxist Sidney Hook claimed that Hartmann was “interesting without being oracular, instructive without pedantry, and profound without being obscure,” and “a thinker who will soon be greeted as Germany’s leading philosopher.”1 While it is true that Hartmann was highly regarded during his lifetime, Hook’s prediction was never realized, as Hartmann’s impressive work was soon eclipsed by that of his younger contemporary, Martin Heidegger.
    [Show full text]
  • The Analysis of Wonder: an Introduction to the Philosophy Of
    The Analysis of Wonder The Analysis of Wonder An Introduction to the Philosophy of Nicolai Hartmann Predrag Cicovacki NEW YORK • LONDON • NEW DELHI • SYDNEY Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Inc 1385 Broadway 50 Bedford Square New York London NY 10018 WC1B 3DP USA UK www.bloomsbury.com Bloomsbury is a registered trade mark of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc First published 2014 © Predrag Cicovacki, 2014 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. No responsibility for loss caused to any individual or organization acting on or refraining from action as a result of the material in this publication can be accepted by Bloomsbury or the author. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Cicovacki, Predrag. The analysis of wonder : an introduction to the philosophy of Nicolai Hartmann / Predrag Cicovacki. pages cm Summary: “A concise introduction into the philosophy of Nicolai Hartmann (1882–1950), written in a way to stimulate further study and development of his thought”– Provided by publisher. ISBN 978-1-6235-6790-3 (hardback) 1. Hartmann, Nicolai, 1882–1950. I. Title. B3279.H24C53 2014 193–dc23 2013045333 eISBN: 978-1-6235-6100-0 Typeset by Newgen Knowledge Works (P) Ltd., Chennai, India For Heidi: Keep Shining “A man does not learn to understand anything unless he loves it.” Goethe Contents
    [Show full text]