Figures of Mind: Thinking Matter in Literary Form, 1650 - 1770

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Figures of Mind: Thinking Matter in Literary Form, 1650 - 1770 FIGURES OF MIND: THINKING MATTER IN LITERARY FORM, 1650 - 1770 A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Jess Keiser January 2013 © 2013 Jess Keiser FIGURES OF MIND: THINKING MATTER IN LITERARY FORM, 1650 - 1770 Jess Keiser, Ph. D. Cornell University 2013 This dissertation examines the interrelation of literary criticism and science of mind in the long eighteenth century by focusing on theories of imagination, fancy, and wit. In grounding these creative faculties in the physiology of the human brain, eighteenth- century thinkers explained the fanciful juxtapositions of the imagination by drawing on experimental science, even as they stressed the confused and mutable nature of the corporeal mind. In so doing, writing on fancy, wit, and metaphor became a means of questioning the boundaries between the thinking subject and the seemingly thoughtless body, the conscious mind and the matter that subtends it. I track this history in the works of Thomas Hobbes, Thomas Willis, John Locke, Alexander Pope, Jonathan Swift, and Laurence Sterne. BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH Jess Keiser was born in Mountain Top, PA in 1984. He received a B.A. in English from Tufts University in 2006, and an M.A. from Cornell University in 2009. iv For my parents v ACKNOWLEDGMENTS My greatest thanks goes to my committee: Rick Bogel, Laura Brown, and my chair, Neil Saccamano. Rick is an ideal reader in multiple senses of the term. His careful and subtle reading of my own work proved to be one of the most important assets when writing this dissertation, just as his often inimitable readings of eighteenth-century poetry and prose continue to be the standard for which my own writing continually strives. Above all, he is generous, wise, and witty (in the most technical sense of the term); I’m proud to say he is my teacher and friend. Laura’s capaciousness is unmatched in contemporary academia. She helped me shape what would otherwise be an idiosyncratic curiosity into something resembling a scholarly monograph. Her sense of what would and would not work in this project borders on the uncanny, and it was always a pleasure to realize that, whenever I finally had figured out some seemingly intractable problem, Laura was the one who had pushed me in the right direction. It’s a cliché to describe a scholar in literary studies as “rigorous,” but I nevertheless think the term can be applied accurately to Neil. His insistence on slowly working through the difficulties of eighteenth-century texts and on rejecting the easy way out spurred me on throughout my years at Cornell. He has encouraged, challenged, and inspired me in so many ways big and small that it would take another dissertation to accurately convey his influence. Like the sublime or the sentimental, his impact goes beyond “mere” words. Without the unwavering support and unerring guidance of Rick, Laura, and Neil I would not have been able to complete this dissertation. I sincerely hope they find their best qualities as scholars and as teachers reflected in these pages. Many of the ideas in this dissertation took shape in classes and conversations with a number of Cornell faculty. I thank Kevin Attell, Cynthia Chase, Elisha Cohn, Peter Gilgen, Neil Hertz, Michael Jonik, Rayna Kalas, Phil Lorenz, and Jenny Mann for their intellectual generosity, unfailing advice, and ready friendship. Various pieces of this dissertation were vi presented at conferences, and I thank Rick Barney, Frank T. Boyle, Danielle Spratt, and especially Al Coppola for encouragement, conversation, and support. The best ideas in these pages are not my own; they resulted from (often late-night) conversations, debates, confessions, confusions, dialogues, speeches, digressions, rants, satires, sing-alongs, “symposia,” and the occasional reading group with my friends at Cornell. They are not only my ideal audience but my ideal friends. They are: Jacob Brogan, Seth Perlow, Paul Flaig, Cecily Swanson, Ryan Dirks, Aaron Hodges, Bradley Depew, Alan Young-Bryant, Alexis Briley, Ari Linden, Sarah Senk, Rob Lehman, Audrey Wasser, Martin Hägglund, Sarah Pickle, Ben Glaser, Stephanie DeGooyer, Sarah Eron, Carl Gelderloos, Douglas McQueen-Thomson, Dan Sinykin, and Tatiana Sverjensky. I fatefully wandered into Lee Edelman’s seminar on the literary criticism of Barbara Johnson and Paul de Man in my Junior year at Tufts. Since then Lee has had the most profound impact on my life as nearly anyone I can think of, and I hope that his influence is felt here. Finally, my greatest debt is to my family—my parents, James and Denise, and my sister, Lindsay—for help, support, and encouragement. vii TABLE OF CONTENTS BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS vi INTRODUCTION 1 1. VERY LIKE A WHALE 20 2. FIGURING ANIMAL SPIRITS 62 3. THE PRINTED MIND 116 4. THE MATTER OF THOUGHT 167 WORKS CITED 221 viii Introduction Around 1660—the exact date is uncertain—a team of Royal Society physicians led by Thomas Willis removed an intact brain from the skull for the first time. Prior anatomists, Willis noted, continually failed in this endeavor. According to Willis, these anatomists “imperfectly understood” the organ they had been dissecting for millennia.1 At best, they modestly exposed the brain tissue lurking just beneath the “forehead or forepart” of the skull after “some rude cutting”; at worst, they mangled the brain, carving its “Globe as it were into slices and parts” and thereby making it impossible to differentiate the various segments they had mashed together.2 In either case, they did more to obscure the brain than to enlighten it. Willis himself admitted that properly anatomizing the brain—which seemed baroquely ornamented with rococo “swellings and tuberous risings with several tails or little feet compacted together”—was difficult.3 “[Y]ea the parts of the Brain it self are so complicated and involved,” he lamented, “and their respects and habitudes to one another so hard to be extricated, that it may seem a more hard task to institute its perfect Anatomy, than to delineate on a plain, the flexions and Meanders of some Labyrinth.”4 In order to map this labyrinth, Willis assembled a team of virtuosi to aid in his dissections: Thomas Millington, who would help him “confer and reason about the uses of the [cerebral] Parts” the group uncovered; Christopher Wren, who would illustrate their findings in painstaking sketches; and most important of all, Richard Lower—the team’s very own Ariadne—who performed most of the dissections. Thanks to the edge of Lower’s “Knife and 1 Thomas Willis, Cerebral Anatomy in Five Treatises, trans. Samuel Pordage (London: Printed for T. Dring, C. Harper, J. Leigh, and S. Martin), 55. 2 Ibid., 55. 3 Ibid., 55. 4 Ibid., 55. 1 Wit,” Willis explained, “in a short space there was nothing of the Brain, and its Appendix within the Skull, that seemed not plainly detected, and intimately beheld by us.”5 At first glance, what Lower’s knife had revealed was simply a greyish mass netted with fine blood vessels: a “curious quilted ball,” as Willis later put it. But subsequent dissections made the organ less curious as Willis and his team began better to understand cerebral anatomy. Willis and his team eventually produced the most complete picture of the brain in the seventeenth century. They observed that the brain was divided into twin hemispheres, that it had a large central mass on the top (the cerebrum), a smaller ball on the bottom (the cerebellum), and a marrowy stem at its base (the medulla oblongata). They carefully tracked the nerves that originated at the root of the brain and plunged into the body, and they also mapped the network of arteries that fed blood to the brain from the heart . But these observations, despite their revolutionary significance, were only prelude to Willis’s real work: understanding how the brain produced the “faculties and affections of the Soul.”6 For Willis, this meant reasoning about the ways in which the matter of the mind—the structures of the brain, its nerves, and the fluids contained therein—created mental faculties like imagination, memory, and volition. In lectures delivered to an audience of Oxford students, Willis attempted to overturn millennia of conjectures concerning mind and body by explaining how it was that the brain created thought. Willis explained that sensation “depends on refined vital spirits, distilled in the brain, and thence communicated by the nerves to the whole body”; that imagination “is caused by an impression from some external object that moves the spirits inwards and excites other spirits in the medulla oblongata into an expansive movement”; and that volition occurs when the movement of these animal spirits “is extended to excite the appropriate nerves which in turn, provoke the external 5 Ibid., 55. 6 Ibid., 53. 2 parts to follow the same object.”7 In other words, for Willis, nearly all thinking could be reduced to flux of chemically charged particles (the animal spirits) pulsating in the skull. * Willis “discovery” of the brain is undoubtedly momentous, but it also leaves us with a problem, a problem that still troubles us today and a problem that this dissertation explores by attending to the literature and thought of the late seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries. The problem is this: how is it that the mere matter of the brain could produce thought? It is one thing, after all, to anatomize the brain, to detail its labyrinthine folds and to track its web of nerves. It is quite another, however, to explain how this “curious quilted ball” thinks—to explain how it was that the curious nerves and flesh Willis discerned in his dissections could also give rise to a mental quality like curiosity.
Recommended publications
  • Descartes' Bête Machine, the Leibnizian Correction and Religious Influence
    University of South Florida Digital Commons @ University of South Florida Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 4-7-2010 Descartes' Bête Machine, the Leibnizian Correction and Religious Influence John Voelpel University of South Florida Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the American Studies Commons, and the Philosophy Commons Scholar Commons Citation Voelpel, John, "Descartes' Bête Machine, the Leibnizian Correction and Religious Influence" (2010). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. https://digitalcommons.usf.edu/etd/3527 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Digital Commons @ University of South Florida. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ University of South Florida. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Descartes’ Bête Machine, the Leibnizian Correction and Religious Influence by John Voelpel A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: Martin Schönfeld, Ph.D. Roger Ariew, Ph.D. Stephen Turner, Ph.D. Date of Approval: April 7, 2010 Keywords: environmental ethics, nonhuman animals, Montaigne, skepticism, active force, categories © Copyright 2010, John W. Voelpel 040410 Note to Reader: Because the quotations from referenced sources in this paper include both parentheses and brackets, this paper uses braces “{}” in any location {inside or outside of quotations} for the writer’s parenthetical-like additions in both text and footnotes. 040410 Table of Contents Abstract iii I. Introduction 1 II. Chapter One: Montaigne: An Explanation for Descartes’ Bête Machine 4 Historical Environment 5 Background Concerning Nonhuman Nature 8 Position About Nature Generally 11 Position About Nonhuman Animals 12 Influence of Religious Institutions 17 Summary of Montaigne’s Perspective 20 III.
    [Show full text]
  • A Leibnizian Approach to Mathematical Relationships: a New Look at Synthetic Judgments in Mathematics
    A Thesis entitled A Leibnizian Approach to Mathematical Relationships: A New Look at Synthetic Judgments in Mathematics by David T. Purser Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy ____________________________________ Dr. Madeline M. Muntersbjorn, Committee Chair ____________________________________ Dr. John Sarnecki, Committee Member ____________________________________ Dr. Benjamin S. Pryor, Committee Member ____________________________________ Dr. Patricia Komuniecki, Dean College of Graduate Studies The University of Toledo December 2009 An Abstract of A Leibnizian Approach to Mathematical Relationships: A New Look at Synthetic Judgments in Mathematics by David T. Purser Submitted to the Graduate Faculty in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy The University of Toledo May 2010 I examine the methods of Georg Cantor and Kurt Gödel in order to understand how new symbolic innovations aided in mathematical discoveries during the early 20th Century by looking at the distinction between the lingua characterstica and the calculus ratiocinator in the work of Leibniz. I explore the dynamics of innovative symbolic systems and how arbitrary systems of signification reveal real relationships in possible worlds. Examining the historical articulation of the analytic/synthetic distinction, I argue that mathematics is synthetic in nature. I formulate a moderate version of mathematical realism called modal relationalism. iii Contents Abstract iii Contents iv Preface vi 1 Leibniz and Symbolic Language 1 1.1 Introduction……………………………………………………. 1 1.2 Universal Characteristic……………………………………….. 4 1.2.1 Simple Concepts……………………………………….. 5 1.2.2 Arbitrary Signs………………………………………… 8 1.3 Logical Calculus………………………………………………. 11 1.4 Leibniz’s Legacy……………………………………………… 16 1.5 Leibniz’s Continued Relevance……………………………….
    [Show full text]
  • The Year of the Animal in France
    1668 The Year of the Animal in France Peter Sahlins ZONE BOOKS • NEW YORK 2017 © 2017 Peter Sahlins zone books 633 Vanderbilt Street Brooklyn, NY 11218 All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, including electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording, or otherwise (except for that copying permitted by Sections 107 and 108 of the U.S. Copyright Law and except by reviewers for the public press), without written permission from the Publisher. Printed in Canada. Distributed by The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, and London, England Permissions from the publishers to incorporate from the following previously published works is greatly appreciated: “The Royal Menageries of Louis XIV and the Civilizing Process Revisited,” was originally published in French Historical Studies 35.2, pp. 226–46. © 2012 Society of French Historical Studies. All rights reserved. Republished by permission of the copyright holder, and the present publisher, Duke University Press. www.dukeupress.edu; “A Tale of Three Chameleons: The Animal between Literature and Science in the Age of Louis XIV,” was originally published in French Thinking About Animals, eds. Louisa MacKenzie and Stephanie Posthumus, pp. 15–30. © 2014 Michigan State University Press; “Where the Sun Don’t Shine: The Royal Labyrinth at Versailles, 1668– 1674,” was originally published in Animals and Early Modern Identity, ed. Pia Cuneo, pp. 67–88. © 2014 Ashgate: Surrey, England and Burlington, VT, 2014. Reprinted by permission from Taylor & Francis; “The Beast Within: Animals and the First Xenotransfusion Experiments in France, 1667–68,” was originally published in Representations 129, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Levels of Discourse in Leibniz's Metaphysics the Ontological Status of Bodies
    Levels of Discourse in Leibniz's Metaphysics The Ontological Status of Bodies: A Study of the Levels of Discourse in Leibniz's Metaphysics By SCOTT STAPLEFORD, B.A. A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts McMaster University C> Copyright by Scott Stapleford, August 1998 MASTER OF ARTS (1998) McMaster University (Philosophy) Hamilton, Ontario TITLE: The Ontological Status of Bodies: A Study of the Levels of Discourse in Leibniz's Metaphysics AUTHOR: Scott Stapleford, B.A. (Brock University) SUPERVISOR: Professor Wilfrid Waluchow NUMBER OF PAGES: iv, 169 ii Table of Contents Introduction 1 The Problem 2 Collateral Issues 3 Procedure Part I 4 Some Working Deftnitions 5 Phenomenalism 5.1 Linguistic Phenomenalism 5.2 Berkeleian Phenomenalism 6 Leibniz and Phenomenalism 6.1 Macintosh's Interpretation 6.2 Jolley's Interpretation 6.3 Wilson's Interpretation 111 Part II 7 Recapitulation and Procedure 8 Athenian and Darwinian Approaches 8.1 Woolhouse's Interpretation 8.2 Adams' Interpretation 8.3 Hartz's Interpretation 8.4 Loeb's Interpretation 8.5 Rutherford's Interpretation 9 Psychology and Ontology 9.1 Mind and Matter in Descartes and Locke 9.2 Leibniz's Analysis of Mind and Matter 9.2.1 The Primary-Secondary Quality Distinction 9.2.2 Physical Considerations 9.2.3 Metaphysical Considerations 9.2.3.1 Substance as Unity 9.2.3.2 Substance as Activity 9.2.3.3 Substance as Subject 9.2.4 Psychological Considerations 10 Levels of Discourse 11 Leibniz's Epistemological Realism 11.1 Requirements of the System 11.2 The Contrary Proposition 11.
    [Show full text]
  • Perception and Representation in Leibniz
    PERCEPTION AND REPRESENTATION IN LEIBNIZ by Stephen Montague Puryear B.S., Mechanical Engineering, North Carolina State University, 1994 M.A., Philosophy, Texas A&M University, 2000 M.A., Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 2004 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Department of Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2006 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY This dissertation was presented by Stephen Montague Puryear It was defended on December 5, 2005 and approved by Nicholas Rescher University Professor of Philosophy Robert B. Brandom Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy Stephen Engstrom Associate Professor of Philosophy J. E. McGuire Professor of History and Philosophy of Science Dissertation Director: Nicholas Rescher University Professor of Philosophy ii Copyright °c by Stephen Montague Puryear 2006 iii PERCEPTION AND REPRESENTATION IN LEIBNIZ Stephen Montague Puryear, Ph.D. University of Pittsburgh, 2006 Though Leibniz’s views about perception and representation go to the heart of his philosophy, they have received surprisingly little attention over the years and in many ways continue to be poorly understood. I aim to redress these shortcomings. The body of the work begins with an exploration of Leibniz’s proposed analysis of representation (Chapter 2). Here I argue that on this analysis representation consists in a kind of structural correspondence— roughly an isomorphism—between representation and thing represented. Special attention is given to the application of this analysis to the challenging cases of linguistic and mental representation. The next two chapters concern what I take to be the central issue of the work: the nature of distinct perception.
    [Show full text]
  • The Thorax in History 3. Beginning of the Middle Ages
    Thorax: first published as 10.1136/thx.33.3.295 on 1 June 1978. Downloaded from Thorax, 1978, 33, 295-306 The thorax in history 3. Beginning of the Middle Ages R. K. FRENCH From the Wellcome Unit for the History of Medicine, University of Cambridge The end of Hellenistic experiment and observation physicians and surgeons did not give the Alexandrians the importance that historical hind- When Galen died at the end of the second century, sight attributes to them, nor did they recognise anatomical and physiological research died with Galen as authoritative as Galen's and later ages him. We are effectively in the dark ages at once, believed him to be. To a certain extent this is for the continued, if precarious, political stability true of the East as of the West: Aretaeus of of the Roman Empire was no substitute for the Cappadocia in Asia Minor was contemporary with, loss of vigour of the Greek intellectual tradition. or slightly later than Galen, but does not mention Galen's works survived, were commented upon him. Fragments of anatomy and physiology that and summarised, but no new inquiry was under- can be gleaned from his surviving works on the taken. When Galen visited Rome, it was as far signs and causes of acute and chronic diseases3 west as anatomy and physiology came: Pergamon, come from a variety of sources, some of them Alexandria, and Ephesus were the inheritors of purely traditional. Indeed, in Aretaeus we see an intellectual climate that sustained anatomy in more clearly than in Galen's synthetic physiology any form other than that employed by the sur- a distinction between traditional, literary anatomy, http://thorax.bmj.com/ geons of the legions.
    [Show full text]
  • Anatomy, Technology, and the Inhuman in Descartes
    UCLA Paroles gelées Title Virtual Bodies: Anatomy, Technology, and the Inhuman in Descartes Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/5ww094n7 Journal Paroles gelées, 16(1) ISSN 1094-7264 Author Judovitz, Dalia Publication Date 1998 DOI 10.5070/PG7161003078 Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California Virtual Bodies: Anatomy, Technology, and the Inhuman in Descartes Dalia Judo vitz Rene Descartes's Discourse on the Method (1637) marks a major turning point in the representation of the body in the Western tradition. Rather than valorizing the lived body and no- tions of experience, as his predecessor Michel de Montaigne had done in The Essays (1588), Descartes focuses on the body no longer as subject, but as object of knowledge, by redefining it anatomically, technologically, and philosophically. ^ He proceeds from the anatomical redefinition of the body in terms of the cir- culation of blood, to its technological resynthesis as a machine, only to ascertain its philosophical reduction to a material thing. Descartes's elaboration of the mind-body duahty will reinforce the autonomy of the body as a material thing, whose purely ob- jective and mechanical character will mark a fundamental depar- ture from previous humanist traditions. Decontextualized from its wordly fabric, the Cartesian body wUl cease to function by reference to the human, since its lived, experiential reality will be supplanted through mechanical analogues.^ Descartes's anatomical interpretation of the body in terms of the circulation of blood breaks away from earUer humoral con- ceptions of the body predominant into the early part of the sev- enteenth century.
    [Show full text]
  • Zwe Meditazzons of Rene Descartes and the Legi'rmatiqn of the Project of Mechanism
    ZWE MEDITAZZONS OF RENE DESCARTES AND THE LEGI'RMATIQN OF THE PROJECT OF MECHANISM: DAVID ANDREW CRAGG A Thesis submitted to the facuity of Emrmnuel Coiïege and the Department of Theology of the Toronto School of Theology. In partiai fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Theology awarded by the University of St. Miehael9sCollege Toronto 1997 National Library Bibliothèque nationale du Canada Acquisitions and Acquisitions et Bibliographie Services services bibliographiques 395 Wellington Street 335, rwWeliington OüawaON K1AW atawaON K1AW Canada Cariada The author has granted a non- L'auteur a accordé une licence non exclusive licence allowing the exclusive permettant à la National Lîbraxy of Canada to Bibliothèque nationale du Canada de reproduce, loan, distniute or sell reproduire, prêter, distri'buer ou copies of this thesis in microfonn, vendre des copies de cette thèse sous paper or electronic fonmats. la forme de microfiche/lfilm, de reproduction sur papier ou sur format électronique. The author retains ownership of the L'auteur conseme la propriété du copyright in this thesis. Neither the droit d'auteur qui protège cette thése. thesis nor substantial extracts fkom it Ni la thèse ni des extraits substantiels may be printed or otherwise de celle-ci ne doivent être imprimés reproduced without the author's ou autrement reproduits sans son permissim. autorisation. TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction Chapter 1: The Roject of Mechsnicm Mechanism's concept of matter Four aspects of the inertness of matter in mechanism
    [Show full text]
  • Theodicy and Reason Logic, Metaphysics
    THEODICY AND REASONTHEODICY Philosophica 2 — Theodicy and Reason Logic, Metaphysics, GERETTO, PERISSINOTTO CAMPOSAMPIERO, FAVARETTI and Theology in Leibniz’s Essais de Théodicée (1710) edited by Matteo Favaretti Camposampiero, Mattia Geretto, and Luigi Perissinotto Edizioni Ca’Foscari Theodicy and Reason Philosophica Collana diretta da Luigi Perissinotto Cecilia Rofena 2 Edizioni Ca’Foscari Philosophica Direttori Luigi Perissinotto (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Cecilia Rofena (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Comitato scientifico Silvana Borutti (Università degli studi di Pavia, Italia) Jean-Pierre Cometti (Université de Provence - Aix-Marseille I, France) Arnold Davidson (University of Chicago, USA) Roberta Dreon (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Giuseppe Goisis (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Daniele Goldoni (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Mauro Nobile (Università degli Studi di Milano-Bicocca, Italia) Gian Luigi Paltrinieri (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Vicente Sanfélix Vidarte (Universitat de València-Estudi General, España) Direzione e redazione Univerisità Ca’ Foscari Venezia Dipartimento di Filosofia e Beni Culturali Palazzo Malcanton Marcorà Dorsoduro 3484/D, 30123 Venezia http://edizionicafoscari.unive.it/col/dbc/10/Philosophica Theodicy and Reason Logic, Metaphysics, and Theology in Leibniz’s Essais de Théodicée (1710) edited by Matteo Favaretti Camposampiero, Mattia Geretto, and Luigi Perissinotto Venezia Edizioni Ca’ Foscari - Digital Publishing 2016 Theodicy and Reason:
    [Show full text]
  • HERMES Literature, Science, Philosophy
    HERMES Literature, Science, Philosophy HERMES LITERA TURE, SCIENCE, PHILOSOPHY by MICHEL SERRES Edited by Josue V. Harari & David F. Bell THE JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS , BALTIMORE & LONDON This book has been brought to publication with the generous as­ sistance of the Andrew W. Mellon Foundation. Copyright © 1982 by The Johns Hopkins University Press All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America The Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, Maryland 21218 The Johns Hopkins Press Ltd., London Permissions are listed on page 157, which constitutes a continuation of the co pyright page. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Serres, Michel. Hermes: literature, science, philosophy. Includes index. Contents: The apparition of Hermes, Don Juan­ Knowledge in the classical age-Michelet, the soup -Language and space, from Oedipus to Zola-[etc.] 1. Harari, Josue V. II. Bell, David F. III. Title. PQ2679.E679A2 1981 844' .914 81-47601 ISBN 0-8018-2454-0 AACR2 ..... .......... Contents Editors' Note VIl INTRODUCTION: Journala plusieurs voies by Josue V. Harari and David F. Bell lX I. LITERATURE & SCIENCE 1. The Apparition of Hermes: Dam Juan 3 2. Knowledge in the Classical Age: La Fontaine and Descartes 15 3. Michelet: The Soup 29 4. Language and Space: From Oedipus to Zola 39 5. Turner Translates Carnot 54 II. PHILOSOPHY & SCIENCE 6. Platonic Dialogue 65 7. The Origin of Language: Biology, Information Theory, and Thermodynamics 71 8. Mathematics and Philosophy: What Thales Saw. 84 9. Lucretius: Science and Religion 98 10. The Origin of Geometry 125 POSTFACE: Dynamics from Leibniz to Lucretius by lIya Prigogine and Isabelle Stengers 135 Name Index 159 Subject Index 163 v ....
    [Show full text]
  • The Human Machine René Descartes (1596-1650)
    Self-Negotiated Unit// MSN 1 // Research 006 // The Human Machine The Human Machine René Descartes (1596-1650) A french philosopher, “the father of modern philosophy”, scientist and mathematician, whose philosophical conclusion, “Cogito; ergo sum” (Je pense, donc je suis; I think, therefore I am), is the best-known quotation in all philosophy and which revolutio- nized the ways of thinking. Being a mathematician Descartes decided to apply the so certain-seeming methods of mathematical reasoning to philosophy. “Good sense is of all things in the world the most equally distributed, for everybody thinks he is so well supplied with it, that even those most difficult to please in all other matters never desire more of it than they already possess.” (from Le Discours de la Méthode, 1637) A Great and Difficult Thing, Michael Hawkins (...) René Descartes provided, in his “Treatise on Man”, what is now perhaps the most familiar account of the challenges associated with explaining the relations between the body and the soul and his formulation of the problems has served as the starting point for most historical inquiries. The bodies of humans and brutes according to Descartes were complex machines whose many actions and physiological functions were caused by the mechanical motions of their parts following ‘from the mere arrangement of the machine’s organs every bit as naturally as the movements of a clock or other automaton follow from the arrangement of its counter-weights and wheels.’ Having only a corporeal existence, brute animals were just complex physical automata driven by the mechanical force of their passions.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz on Privations, Limitations, and the Metaphysics of Evil
    Leibniz on Privations, Limitations, and the Metaphysics of Evil SAMUEL NEWLANDS* 1 . introduction there was a consensus in late Scholasticism that evils are privations, the lacks of appropriate perfections. For something to be evil is for it to lack an excellence that, by its nature, it ought to have. This widely accepted ontology of evil was used, in part, to help explain the source of evil in a world created and sustained by a perfect being. During the second half of the seventeenth century, progressive early moderns began to criticize the traditional privative account of evil on a variety of philosophical and theological grounds. Embedded in Scholastic Aristotelianism and applied to problems of evil, privation theory seemed to some like yet another instance of pre-modern pseudo-explanation.1 Against this growing rejection of privation theory in the late seventeenth cen- tury, Leibniz stands out as an enigmatic exception. In his early writings, Leibniz too sharply rejects the standard use of privation theory. He describes it as “a mani- fest illusion,” a “joke,” a “leftover from the visionary philosophy of the past; it is a subterfuge with which a reasonable person will never be satisfied” CP( 111).2 But within fifteen years, Leibniz changes his mind, or at least his tune. Around 1685, he admits that although privation theory “seems illusory,” it is actually “more solid than it first seems” A( k 6.4.1605). This more positive evaluation continues throughout the rest of Leibniz’s life. In his late writings on the problem of evil, 1For more on the general reception of privation theory in the seventeenth century, see Newlands, “Evils, Privations, and the Early Moderns.” 2A ll translations from Leibniz are mine, except where I cite an English edition, though I have sometimes consulted existing English translations of other passages when available.
    [Show full text]