Disjunction and Implicatures: Some Notes on Recent Developments

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Disjunction and Implicatures: Some Notes on Recent Developments Disjunction and Implicatures: Some Notes on Recent Developments Uli Sauerland ZAS Berlin July 2009, revised November 2009 Use of disjunction often allows us to draw additional inferences about the speakers belief: For example, (1) uttered by someone out of the blue would lead us to draw at least three additional inferences about the speaker. For one, we would infer that he didn’t see both Kyle and Ryan. Furthermore, we would infer that the speaker is neither certain that he saw Kyle nor that he is certain that he saw Ryan. What is certain is that he saw one of the two. (1) I saw Kyle or Ryan in the crowd. What are the mental mechanisms deriving such inferences? This question is central question of the recent discussion targeting scalar implicatures as examples with disjunction have been crucial in this debate. One of the leading questions in this debate is the following: Can the mech- anism apply to constituents smaller than sentences? In work by Grice (1989) and work building on his intuitions, the computation of implica- tures is tied to the act of speaking, the intentions of speakers, and the assumption that speakers’ act cooperatively. Therefore implicatures are assumed to be generally computed at the sentence level only, though this is not necessarily the only option even on a Gricean approach if speech acts can be embedded. Recent work has contrasted Grice’s position with 1 systems where implicature computation is not tied to speakers’ intentions, but a purely grammatical procedure. This grammatical procedure could in principle apply to any subconstituent of a sentence structure – it can be applied locally. Since scalar implicature computation is semantically at least very similar to the meaning of only, namely exhaustification, work by Chierchia (2006), Fox (2007) and others has adopted the convention to mark constituents at which implicature computation applies with a silent operator abbreviated either as O (for only) or Exh (for Exhaustification). In this paper, I adopt Exh. As far as I am aware of, while it is generally ac- knowledged that constraints govern the distribution of Exh, a proposal for the distribution of Exh is still forthcoming. At this point, what espe- cially Chierchia et al. (2009) and Chierchia et al. 2008 claim to have shown, though, is that Exh can occur in embedded positions and they therefore reject Grice’s connection of implicature to speaker intention. The phe- nomenon of Exh applying below the sentence level is also referred to as local implicature computation, as opposed to global computation at the sen- tence level. This paper discusses two potential arguments against a Gricean account of implicatures due to Chierchia et al. (2009) (see also Chierchia et al. 2008; the Hurford’s constraint data) and Fox (2007) (the Free choice data). The two classes of data are illustrated in (2) and (3) respectively. (2) Hurford’s constraint datum (Gazdar, 1979): Mary read some or all of the books. (3) Free choice datum (Kamp, 1973): You may eat the cake or the ice-cream. Chierchia et al. (2008) claim that the account of these two classes of data requires local computation of implicatures. I take objection to this claim. In the following section I address Hurford’s constraint. I show that local implicature for each disjunct is in general not attested, but only global im- plicature computation. In particular, I argue that the another class of data 2 – the generalized xor data – have been mistakenly taken to argue for a lo- cal analysis of implicatures, while in fact the opposite is the case: only the global analysis can account for these data. The Hurford’s constraint data therefore constitute an exceptional case, and I propose to account for them as such. In the second section of this paper, I turn to the free choice data. I first set out to clarify Fox (2007) argument: these data are actually not an argument in favor of a local account of scalar implicature, but rather the global analysis. However, Fox is correct to point out that the free choice data are problematic the Gricean picture of entirely post-semantic impli- cature computation. However, Fox’s argument depends entirely on the claim that free choice inferences are implicatures. On this issue, the cur- rent state of the art Chemla (2009) says that implicatures and free choice inferences have different properties with respect to embedding under uni- versal quantifiers. Therefore, I conclude tentatively that Fox’s arguments do not threaten the global account. of implicatures. 1 Scalars under Disjunction I want to situate the discussion of the data involving Hurford’s constraint in the context of the discussion of examples from Chierchia (2004) that were intensively discussed a few years ago (Sauerland, 2004b; Spector, 2005; van Rooij and Schulz, 2004). I want to call these data the Generalized Xor data for reasons that will become clear. I am to show that the gen- eralized xor data require that the scalar implicatures of disjuncts cannot be locally computed in general. This conclusion then leads me to propose that the Hurford’s constraint data are cases of a repair strategy. Multiple disjunctions are a well known problem of the implicatures (Mc- Cawley, 1993; Simons, 1998). For expository purposes, consider an ap- proach to the pragmatics of disjunction that assumes that disjunction is ambiguous between inclusive disjunction or and exclusive disjunction xor. Grice (1989) discusses and rejects this kind of approach, but it also fails in an instructive fashion with multiple disjunction like (A or B) or C. The salient attested interpretation of such an examples is that exactly one of A, 3 A A A B, or C is satisfied as shown by the Venn diagram on the left in the follow- ing figure.C But,B this interpretationC cannotB be derived by the ambiguity-or- or approach. The figure below illustrates (A or B) xor C andC (A xorB B) xor C which result in unintuitive interpretations. A A A C B C B C B correct (A or B) xor C (A xor B) xor C One may attempt to attach this problemA by postulating a novel ternary ex- clusive disjunction operator that is defined to make the correct prediction. However, this is not a promisingC approachB because the problem illustrated by multiple disjunction generalizes as Chierchia (2004) (as well as Bern- hard Schwarz in unpublished work) discovered. One example demon- strating this from my own work (Sauerland, 2004b) is (4). In (4), the weak scalar term some in the scope of disjunction triggers an implicature of not all, but this could not be derived correctly on an lexical ambiguity analysis: Specifically, if postulated an ambiguity of some between at least some and some and not all in addition to the or/xor ambiguity of or, we would predict that (4) should be felicitous in the following scenarios: On the xor and some and not all-reading if Kai ate both the broccoli and all of the peas, and on the xor and at least some-reading, if Kai ate all of the peas and none of the broccoli. (4) Kai had the broccoli or some of the peas last night. The xor data argue for the global approach to implicatures. As far as I know, any published account of the xor-data is global, even though the relevant data are discussed in much of the literature advocating a local 4 approach to implicatures starting (Chierchia, 2004; Sharvit and Gajewski, 2008; Gajewski and Sharvit, 2009). While this is as far as I can see largely due to confusion in the literature, there is some motivation for this confu- sion: In unpublished work that preceded his 2004 paper (Chierchia, 2004), Gennaro Chierchia attempted a solution of the xor-data making use of a local implicature computation where implicatures are then not part of the sentence semantics, but projected. Specifically, Chierchia (2004) devel- oped an account for A or B or C and (4) that made use of local implicature computation and assumed that local implicatures do not contribute to the semantic meaning of a sentence. In the published paper, Chierchia still appeals to this intuition, for example when he writes implicatures are pro- jected upwards and filtered out or adjusted. However, the published version of Chierchia’s work and all current work on the local approach has not ex- ecuted this intuition of Chierchia’s – and for good reasons, as I’ll show be- low –, but instead has adopted the semantic exh-operator. The exh-operator contributes an exhaustivized meaning to compositional semantics, rather than contributing subject to a implicature projection procedure. A first version of the exhaustification operator is given in (5). The subscript T of exh must denote a set of alternative propositions to S (the scope of exh). The content of T is determined jointly by context and by S itself.1 Exhaus- tification means that all the alternatives from T are false except for those entailed by S. (5) Exhaustification (preliminary version): 0 0 [[ExhT S]]= (S ^ 8 S 2 A ((S 6! S ) _: S) In case of a disjunction A or B, Chierchia et al. (2009) and others assume T to equal the set containing A or B and A and B. Therefore ExhT (A _ B) is predicted to be equivalent to A xor B. Therefore, it is plain to see that local computation of implicatures as in ExhT(ExhT (A or B) or C) is equivalent to (A xor B) xor C, and therefore in general makes the wrong predictions for multiple disjunctions. 1For example, T may defined as the set of scalar alternatives of S, i.e.
Recommended publications
  • UNIT-I Mathematical Logic Statements and Notations
    UNIT-I Mathematical Logic Statements and notations: A proposition or statement is a declarative sentence that is either true or false (but not both). For instance, the following are propositions: “Paris is in France” (true), “London is in Denmark” (false), “2 < 4” (true), “4 = 7 (false)”. However the following are not propositions: “what is your name?” (this is a question), “do your homework” (this is a command), “this sentence is false” (neither true nor false), “x is an even number” (it depends on what x represents), “Socrates” (it is not even a sentence). The truth or falsehood of a proposition is called its truth value. Connectives: Connectives are used for making compound propositions. The main ones are the following (p and q represent given propositions): Name Represented Meaning Negation ¬p “not p” Conjunction p q “p and q” Disjunction p q “p or q (or both)” Exclusive Or p q “either p or q, but not both” Implication p ⊕ q “if p then q” Biconditional p q “p if and only if q” Truth Tables: Logical identity Logical identity is an operation on one logical value, typically the value of a proposition that produces a value of true if its operand is true and a value of false if its operand is false. The truth table for the logical identity operator is as follows: Logical Identity p p T T F F Logical negation Logical negation is an operation on one logical value, typically the value of a proposition that produces a value of true if its operand is false and a value of false if its operand is true.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 1 Logic and Set Theory
    Chapter 1 Logic and Set Theory To criticize mathematics for its abstraction is to miss the point entirely. Abstraction is what makes mathematics work. If you concentrate too closely on too limited an application of a mathematical idea, you rob the mathematician of his most important tools: analogy, generality, and simplicity. – Ian Stewart Does God play dice? The mathematics of chaos In mathematics, a proof is a demonstration that, assuming certain axioms, some statement is necessarily true. That is, a proof is a logical argument, not an empir- ical one. One must demonstrate that a proposition is true in all cases before it is considered a theorem of mathematics. An unproven proposition for which there is some sort of empirical evidence is known as a conjecture. Mathematical logic is the framework upon which rigorous proofs are built. It is the study of the principles and criteria of valid inference and demonstrations. Logicians have analyzed set theory in great details, formulating a collection of axioms that affords a broad enough and strong enough foundation to mathematical reasoning. The standard form of axiomatic set theory is denoted ZFC and it consists of the Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) axioms combined with the axiom of choice (C). Each of the axioms included in this theory expresses a property of sets that is widely accepted by mathematicians. It is unfortunately true that careless use of set theory can lead to contradictions. Avoiding such contradictions was one of the original motivations for the axiomatization of set theory. 1 2 CHAPTER 1. LOGIC AND SET THEORY A rigorous analysis of set theory belongs to the foundations of mathematics and mathematical logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Folktale Documentation Release 1.0
    Folktale Documentation Release 1.0 Quildreen Motta Nov 05, 2017 Contents 1 Guides 3 2 Indices and tables 5 3 Other resources 7 3.1 Getting started..............................................7 3.2 Folktale by Example........................................... 10 3.3 API Reference.............................................. 12 3.4 How do I................................................... 63 3.5 Glossary................................................. 63 Python Module Index 65 i ii Folktale Documentation, Release 1.0 Folktale is a suite of libraries for generic functional programming in JavaScript that allows you to write elegant modular applications with fewer bugs, and more reuse. Contents 1 Folktale Documentation, Release 1.0 2 Contents CHAPTER 1 Guides • Getting Started A series of quick tutorials to get you up and running quickly with the Folktale libraries. • API reference A quick reference of Folktale’s libraries, including usage examples and cross-references. 3 Folktale Documentation, Release 1.0 4 Chapter 1. Guides CHAPTER 2 Indices and tables • Global Module Index Quick access to all modules. • General Index All functions, classes, terms, sections. • Search page Search this documentation. 5 Folktale Documentation, Release 1.0 6 Chapter 2. Indices and tables CHAPTER 3 Other resources • Licence information 3.1 Getting started This guide will cover everything you need to start using the Folktale project right away, from giving you a brief overview of the project, to installing it, to creating a simple example. Once you get the hang of things, the Folktale By Example guide should help you understanding the concepts behind the library, and mapping them to real use cases. 3.1.1 So, what’s Folktale anyways? Folktale is a suite of libraries for allowing a particular style of functional programming in JavaScript.
    [Show full text]
  • Theorem Proving in Classical Logic
    MEng Individual Project Imperial College London Department of Computing Theorem Proving in Classical Logic Supervisor: Dr. Steffen van Bakel Author: David Davies Second Marker: Dr. Nicolas Wu June 16, 2021 Abstract It is well known that functional programming and logic are deeply intertwined. This has led to many systems capable of expressing both propositional and first order logic, that also operate as well-typed programs. What currently ties popular theorem provers together is their basis in intuitionistic logic, where one cannot prove the law of the excluded middle, ‘A A’ – that any proposition is either true or false. In classical logic this notion is provable, and the_: corresponding programs turn out to be those with control operators. In this report, we explore and expand upon the research about calculi that correspond with classical logic; and the problems that occur for those relating to first order logic. To see how these calculi behave in practice, we develop and implement functional languages for propositional and first order logic, expressing classical calculi in the setting of a theorem prover, much like Agda and Coq. In the first order language, users are able to define inductive data and record types; importantly, they are able to write computable programs that have a correspondence with classical propositions. Acknowledgements I would like to thank Steffen van Bakel, my supervisor, for his support throughout this project and helping find a topic of study based on my interests, for which I am incredibly grateful. His insight and advice have been invaluable. I would also like to thank my second marker, Nicolas Wu, for introducing me to the world of dependent types, and suggesting useful resources that have aided me greatly during this report.
    [Show full text]
  • Learning Dependency-Based Compositional Semantics
    Learning Dependency-Based Compositional Semantics Percy Liang∗ University of California, Berkeley Michael I. Jordan∗∗ University of California, Berkeley Dan Klein† University of California, Berkeley Suppose we want to build a system that answers a natural language question by representing its semantics as a logical form and computing the answer given a structured database of facts. The core part of such a system is the semantic parser that maps questions to logical forms. Semantic parsers are typically trained from examples of questions annotated with their target logical forms, but this type of annotation is expensive. Our goal is to instead learn a semantic parser from question–answer pairs, where the logical form is modeled as a latent variable. We develop a new semantic formalism, dependency-based compositional semantics (DCS) and define a log-linear distribution over DCS logical forms. The model parameters are estimated using a simple procedure that alternates between beam search and numerical optimization. On two standard semantic parsing benchmarks, we show that our system obtains comparable accuracies to even state-of-the-art systems that do require annotated logical forms. 1. Introduction One of the major challenges in natural language processing (NLP) is building systems that both handle complex linguistic phenomena and require minimal human effort. The difficulty of achieving both criteria is particularly evident in training semantic parsers, where annotating linguistic expressions with their associated logical forms is expensive but until recently, seemingly unavoidable. Advances in learning latent-variable models, however, have made it possible to progressively reduce the amount of supervision ∗ Computer Science Division, University of California, Berkeley, CA 94720, USA.
    [Show full text]
  • Logical Vs. Natural Language Conjunctions in Czech: a Comparative Study
    ITAT 2016 Proceedings, CEUR Workshop Proceedings Vol. 1649, pp. 68–73 http://ceur-ws.org/Vol-1649, Series ISSN 1613-0073, c 2016 K. Prikrylová,ˇ V. Kubon,ˇ K. Veselovská Logical vs. Natural Language Conjunctions in Czech: A Comparative Study Katrin Prikrylová,ˇ Vladislav Kubon,ˇ and Katerinaˇ Veselovská Charles University in Prague, Faculty of Mathematics and Physics Czech Republic {prikrylova,vk,veselovska}@ufal.mff.cuni.cz Abstract: This paper studies the relationship between con- ceptions and irregularities which do not abide the rules as junctions in a natural language (Czech) and their logical strictly as it is the case in logic. counterparts. It shows that the process of transformation Primarily due to this difference, the transformation of of a natural language expression into its logical representa- natural language sentences into their logical representation tion is not straightforward. The paper concentrates on the constitutes a complex issue. As we are going to show in most frequently used logical conjunctions, and , and it the subsequent sections, there are no simple rules which analyzes the natural language phenomena which∧ influence∨ would allow automation of the process – the majority of their transformation into logical conjunction and disjunc- problematic cases requires an individual approach. tion. The phenomena discussed in the paper are temporal In the following text we are going to restrict our ob- sequence, expressions describing mutual relationship and servations to the two most frequently used conjunctions, the consequences of using plural. namely a (and) and nebo (or). 1 Introduction and motivation 2 Sentences containing the conjunction a (and) The endeavor to express natural language sentences in the form of logical expressions is probably as old as logic it- The initial assumption about complex sentences contain- self.
    [Show full text]
  • Presupposition Projection and Entailment Relations
    Presupposition Projection and Entailment Relations Amaia Garcia Odon i Acknowledgements I would like to thank the members of my thesis committee, Prof. Dr. Rob van der Sandt, Dr. Henk Zeevat, Dr. Isidora Stojanovic, Dr. Cornelia Ebert and Dr. Enric Vallduví for having accepted to be on my thesis committee. I am extremely grateful to my adviser, Louise McNally, and to Rob van der Sandt. Without their invaluable help, I would not have written this dissertation. Louise has been a wonderful adviser, who has always provided me with excellent guid- ance and continuous encouragement. Rob has been a mentor who has generously spent much time with me, teaching me Logic, discussing my work, and helping me clear up my thoughts. Very special thanks to Henk Zeevat for having shared his insights with me and for having convinced me that it was possible to finish on time. Thanks to Bart Geurts, Noor van Leusen, Sammie Tarenskeen, Bob van Tiel, Natalia Zevakhina and Corien Bary in Nijmegen; to Paul Dekker, Jeroen Groe- nendijk, Frank Veltman, Floris Roelofsen, Morgan Mameni, Raquel Fernández and Margot Colinet in Amsterdam; to Fernando García Murga, Agustín Vicente, Myriam Uribe-Etxebarria, Javier Ormazabal, Vidal Valmala, Gorka Elordieta, Urtzi Etxeberria and Javi Fernández in Vitoria-Gasteiz, to David Beaver and Mari- bel Romero. Also thanks to the people I met at the ESSLLIs of Bordeaux, Copen- hagen and Ljubljana, especially to Nick Asher, Craige Roberts, Judith Tonhauser, Fenghui Zhang, Mingya Liu, Alexandra Spalek, Cornelia Ebert and Elena Pa- ducheva. I gratefully acknowledge the financial help provided by the Basque Government – Departamento de Educación, Universidades e Investigación (BFI07.96) and Fun- dación ICREA (via an ICREA Academia award to Louise McNally).
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Logic 1
    Introduction to logic 1. Logic and Artificial Intelligence: some historical remarks One of the aims of AI is to reproduce human features by means of a computer system. One of these features is reasoning. Reasoning can be viewed as the process of having a knowledge base (KB) and manipulating it to create new knowledge. Reasoning can be seen as comprised of 3 processes: 1. Perceiving stimuli from the environment; 2. Translating the stimuli in components of the KB; 3. Working on the KB to increase it. We are going to deal with how to represent information in the KB and how to reason about it. We use logic as a device to pursue this aim. These notes are an introduction to modern logic, whose origin can be found in George Boole’s and Gottlob Frege’s works in the XIX century. However, logic in general traces back to ancient Greek philosophers that studied under which conditions an argument is valid. An argument is any set of statements – explicit or implicit – one of which is the conclusion (the statement being defended) and the others are the premises (the statements providing the defense). The relationship between the conclusion and the premises is such that the conclusion follows from the premises (Lepore 2003). Modern logic is a powerful tool to represent and reason on knowledge and AI has traditionally adopted it as working tool. Within logic, one research tradition that strongly influenced AI is that started by the German philosopher and mathematician Gottfried Leibniz. His aim was to formulate a Lingua Rationalis to create a universal language based only on rationality, which could solve all the controversies between different parties.
    [Show full text]
  • The Composition of Logical Constants
    the morphosemantic makeup of exclusive-disjunctive markers ∗ Moreno Mitrovi´c university of cyprus & bled institute . abstract. The spirit of this paper is strongly decompositional and its aim to meditate on the idea that natural language conjunction and disjunction markers do not necessarily (directly) incarnate Boo- lean terms like ‘0’ and ‘1’,respectively. Drawing from a rich collec- tion of (mostly dead) languages (Ancient Anatolian, Homeric Greek, Tocharian, Old Church Slavonic, and North-East Caucasian), I will examine the morphosemantics of ‘XOR’ (‘exclusive or’) markers, i.e. exclusive (or strong/enriched) disjunction markers of the “ei- Do not cite without consultation. ⭒ ther ...or ...”-type, and demonstrate that the morphology of the XOR marker does not only contain the true (generalised) disjunc- tion marker (I dub it κ), as one would expect on the null (Boolean hy- pothesis), but that the XOR-marker also contains the (generalised) conjunction marker (I dub it μ). After making the case for a fine- April 15, 2017 structure of the Junction Phrase (JP), a common structural denom- ⭒ inator for con- and dis-junction, the paper proposes a new syntax for XOR constructions involving five functional heads (two pairs of κ ver. 6 and μ markers, forming the XOR-word and combining with the respective coordinand, and a J-head pairing up the coordinands). draft I then move on to compose the semantics of the syntactically de- ⭒ composed structure by providing a compositional account obtain- ing the exclusive component, qua the semantic/pragmatic signa- ture of these markers. To do so, I rely on an exhaustification-based system of ‘grammaticised implicatures’ (Chierchia, 2013b) in as- manuscript suming silent exhaustification operators in the narrow syntax, which (in concert with the presence of alternative-triggering κ- and μ-ope- rators) trigger local exclusive (scalar) implicature (SI) computation.
    [Show full text]
  • Working with Logic
    Working with Logic Jordan Paschke September 2, 2015 One of the hardest things to learn when you begin to write proofs is how to keep track of everything that is going on in a theorem. Using a proof by contradiction, or proving the contrapositive of a proposition, is sometimes the easiest way to move forward. However negating many different hypotheses all at once can be tricky. This worksheet is designed to help you adjust between thinking in “English” and thinking in “math.” It should hopefully serve as a reference sheet where you can quickly look up how the various logical operators and symbols interact with each other. Logical Connectives Let us consider the two propositions: P =“Itisraining.” Q =“Iamindoors.” The following are called logical connectives,andtheyarethemostcommonwaysof combining two or more propositions (or only one, in the case of negation) into a new one. Negation (NOT):ThelogicalnegationofP would read as • ( P )=“Itisnotraining.” ¬ Conjunction (AND):ThelogicalconjunctionofP and Q would be read as • (P Q) = “It is raining and I am indoors.” ∧ Disjunction (OR):ThelogicaldisjunctionofP and Q would be read as • (P Q)=“ItisrainingorIamindoors.” ∨ Implication (IF...THEN):ThelogicalimplicationofP and Q would be read as • (P = Q)=“Ifitisraining,thenIamindoors.” ⇒ 1 Biconditional (IF AND ONLY IF):ThelogicalbiconditionalofP and Q would • be read as (P Q)=“ItisrainingifandonlyifIamindoors.” ⇐⇒ Along with the implication (P = Q), there are three other related conditional state- ments worth mentioning: ⇒ Converse:Thelogicalconverseof(P = Q)wouldbereadas • ⇒ (Q = P )=“IfIamindoors,thenitisraining.” ⇒ Inverse:Thelogicalinverseof(P = Q)wouldbereadas • ⇒ ( P = Q)=“Ifitisnotraining,thenIamnotindoors.” ¬ ⇒¬ Contrapositive:Thelogicalcontrapositionof(P = Q)wouldbereadas • ⇒ ( Q = P )=“IfIamnotindoors,thenIitisnotraining.” ¬ ⇒¬ It is worth mentioning that the implication (P = Q)andthecontrapositive( Q = P ) are logically equivalent.
    [Show full text]
  • Datafun: a Functional Datalog
    Datafun: a Functional Datalog Michael Arntzenius Neelakantan R. Krishnaswami University of Birmingham (UK) {daekharel, neelakantan.krishnaswami}@gmail.com Abstract Since proof search is in general undecidable, designers of logic Datalog may be considered either an unusually powerful query lan- programming languages must be careful both about the kinds guage or a carefully limited logic programming language. Datalog of formulas they admit as programs, and about the proof search is declarative, expressive, and optimizable, and has been applied algorithm they implement. Prolog offers a very expressive language successfully in a wide variety of problem domains. However, most — full Horn clauses — and so faces an undecidable proof search use-cases require extending Datalog in an application-specific man- problem. Therefore, Prolog specifies its proof search strategy: depth- ner. In this paper we define Datafun, an analogue of Datalog sup- first goal-directed/top-down search. This lets Prolog programmers porting higher-order functional programming. The key idea is to reason about the behaviour of their programs; however, it also means track monotonicity with types. many logically natural programs fail to terminate. Notoriously, transitive closure calculations are much less elegant in Prolog Categories and Subject Descriptors F.3.2 [Logics and Meanings than one might hope, since their most natural specification is best of Programs]: Semantics of Programming Languages computed with a bottom-up (aka “forwards chaining”) proof search strategy. Keywords Prolog, Datalog, logic programming, functional pro- This view of Prolog suggests other possible design choices, gramming, domain-specific languages, type theory, denotational such as restricting the logical language so as to make proof search semantics, operational semantics, adjoint logic decidable.
    [Show full text]
  • Exclusive Or from Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia
    New features Log in / create account Article Discussion Read Edit View history Exclusive or From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia "XOR" redirects here. For other uses, see XOR (disambiguation), XOR gate. Navigation "Either or" redirects here. For Kierkegaard's philosophical work, see Either/Or. Main page The logical operation exclusive disjunction, also called exclusive or (symbolized XOR, EOR, Contents EXOR, ⊻ or ⊕, pronounced either / ks / or /z /), is a type of logical disjunction on two Featured content operands that results in a value of true if exactly one of the operands has a value of true.[1] A Current events simple way to state this is "one or the other but not both." Random article Donate Put differently, exclusive disjunction is a logical operation on two logical values, typically the values of two propositions, that produces a value of true only in cases where the truth value of the operands differ. Interaction Contents About Wikipedia Venn diagram of Community portal 1 Truth table Recent changes 2 Equivalencies, elimination, and introduction but not is Contact Wikipedia 3 Relation to modern algebra Help 4 Exclusive “or” in natural language 5 Alternative symbols Toolbox 6 Properties 6.1 Associativity and commutativity What links here 6.2 Other properties Related changes 7 Computer science Upload file 7.1 Bitwise operation Special pages 8 See also Permanent link 9 Notes Cite this page 10 External links 4, 2010 November Print/export Truth table on [edit] archived The truth table of (also written as or ) is as follows: Venn diagram of Create a book 08-17094 Download as PDF No.
    [Show full text]