Negation, Scope and the Descriptive/Metalinguistic Distinction

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Negation, Scope and the Descriptive/Metalinguistic Distinction 1 NEGATION, SCOPE AND THE DESCRIPTIVE/METALINGUISTIC DISTINCTION Jacques Moeschler ([email protected]) 1. INTRODUCTION This paper is about negation and scope. Its main purpose is to try to build a general semantics- pragmatics interface framework where scope issues are explicitly described in a formalism accounting for scope properties of logical operators in natural language and their pragmatic interpretation. What is striking about negation is that it does not require a specific syntactic domain to trigger different scope effects. In other words, as far as French is concerned, ordinary negation is always a constituent negation, whereas it takes a whole proposition in its scope. More surprisingly, French negation does not occupy, as in most languages, a preceding position relative the constituent it modifies (the verb), but follows it. This is a very odd property, which is solved when negation is complete as in written French, where the expletive ne precedes the verb. So, in (1) for instance, there are two ways, and not three, of expressing a negative sentence: (1) a. Pierre ne vient pas. b. Pierre vient pas. c. * Pierre ne vient. ‘Peter does not come.’ One of the implications for a semantic and pragmatic comprehension of (1b) is to understand how negation can scope over the verb first, and scope over the whole sentence, as expressed in (2): (2) Pierre vient pas > Pierre pas [vient] > pas [Pierre vient] This issue, which mainly concerns the syntax-semantics interface, will not be discussed here.2 What we are concerned with here is the contrast between (3a) and (3b): (3) a. Pierre ne vient pas. b. Pierre ne vient pas, il court. In (3a), the scope of negation is given by (4a) – that is, negation scopes syntactically over the verb and semantically over the clause, whereas in (4b), negation does not scope over the clause, but over the speech act: 1 The author thanks Denis Delfitto, Luigi Rizzi and all the participants to SWIGG09 at Neuchâtel for their comments on the first presentation of this paper. Thanks to Gabriela Soare for her help in the revision of my paper. 2 What could be conjectured is that, as it has been demonstrated in the case of adverbials, the verb moves from a position after negation to a position before it: Pierre [ne pas [vient]] > Pierre [ne [vient] pas]. For more precise analyses, see Pollock (1989), Belletti (1990) and Chomsky (1991). GG@G (Generative Grammar in Geneva) 6:29-48, 2010 © 2010 Jacques Moeschler 30 JACQUES MOESCHLER (4) a. pas [Jean vient] b. pas [THE SPEAKER ASSERTS [Jean vient]] (3a) is traditionally described as a case of metalinguistic negation. In metalinguistic negation (Horn 1985, 1989), speakers use the standard negation just in order to make explicit that he cannot assert the clause that negation scopes over. What is surprising with metalinguistic negation is that first it does not require a specific morphological nor a syntactic device to convey a metalinguistic meaning, and second that a following string must be realized in order to insure the metalinguistic meaning. For instance, (3a) cannot in any context receive a metalinguistic meaning, whereas in (3b) the metalinguistic reading is the only possible one. Now, if such a difference occurs between these two simple uses of negation, the question is following: first, why does ordinary or descriptive negation not require a sequencing, for instance such as the one illustrated in (5): (5) Pierre ne vient pas, il reste chez lui. ‘Peter is not coming, he is staying at home.’ Second, what is the semantic and lexical limit between a corrective use and a metalinguistic use? For instance, is (6) an example of metalinguistic negation or a simple corrective use? (6) Pierre ne part pas, il arrive. ‘Peter is not leaving, he is arriving.’ As we see, the semantics-pragmatics issue leads us to a domain implying a lot of lexical semantics, and not only issues of scope. The aim of this paper is to give a rationale for the derivation of the interpretation of ordinary and metalinguistic negations. Our main hypothesis, following Carston (1994, 1996, 2002) and Moeschler (1997, 2006), is that negation takes wide scope at logical form and scopes over its specific domain (a verbal constituent) at the level of pragmatic derivation. In other words, referring to structures like (4a) and (4b), (4a) will be the typical semantic representation for the ordinary negation, and this representation will be specified, at the level of explicature to a representation as (7): (7) [Jean [pas-vient]] The way a representation like (4b) can be derived is the second aim of this paper. More generally, I will extend the domain of metalinguistic negation to capture the logical and pragmatic properties of utterance as (8), where negation scopes over a presupposition (8a), an implicature (8b) and a speech act (8c): (8) a. The king of France is not bald, since there is no king of France. b. Anne doesn’t have three children; she has four. c. I don’t advise you to clean your room, I order you. 2. A LONG STORY FOR A BIG ISSUE Let us start with the beginning of this story, that is, Russell’s analysis of definite descriptions (Russell 1905). Russell’s analysis leads to a classical distinction between external and internal negation: external negation has in its scope a full logical proposition, containing no free NEGATION, SCOPE AND NEGATIVE EVENTS 31 variables, whereas internal negation has in its scope a propositional function, i.e. a non- propositional form containing free variables. The king of France example is a good example to illustrate the formal difference between external and internal negation: (9) The king of France is bald. (10) The king of France is not bald. (11) The king of France is not bald, since there is no king of France. (9) and (10) have a common presupposition, that is, (12): (12) There is a unique king of France. (12) is a presupposition in the sense of the classical semantic definition of presupposition, that is, a proposition entailed by a positive clause and its negation (Gazdar 1979). This presupposition is cancelled in (13), and such an effect is responsible for the metalinguistic interpretation of (11). In other words, one possible paraphrase of (11) is the traditional metalinguistic description: (13) I cannot assert that the king of France is bald, since there is no king of France. Now the issue is the following: since the negative clauses in (10) and (11) are identical (the king of France is not bald), how can we account for their different interpretations. Russell’s analysis is a logical one, which is based on the analysis of (9): (9) is an existential sentence composed of the conjunction of three propositional functions3, as given in (14): (14) ∃x [K(x) ∧ ¬∃y[(y≠x) ∧ K(y)] ∧ B(x)] ‘There is an x such that x is king and there is no y such that y is different of x and king, and x is bald.’ Now what are the possible insertions for negation? Logically, there are four possible solutions, since negation is a propositional operator and applies, to a full proposition or a propositional function. (15) gives the four possible insertions for a negation in (14): (15) a. ¬∃x [K(x) ∧ ¬∃y[(y≠x) ∧ K(y)] ∧ B(x)] b. ∃x [¬K(x)∧ ¬∃y[(y≠x) ∧ K(y)] ∧ B(x)] c. ∃x [K(x) ∧ ¬ ¬∃y[(y≠x) ∧ K(y)] ∧ B(x)] d. ∃x [K(x)∧ ¬∃y[(y≠x) ∧ K(y)] ∧ ¬B(x)] (15a) is a consistent reading and corresponds to the wide scope reading of negation: it means that there is NOT such an x that is a king, that is unique and bald. The reading fits the interpretation in (11); that is, the denial of a presupposition, or the metalinguistic use of negation (13). So the first conclusion is that the wide scope of negation cancels existential presuppositions. 3 A propositional function is a logical form containing at least one free variable, that is, a variable that is not bound by a quantifier. Taken individually, K(x), ¬∃y[(y≠x) ∧ K(y)] and B(x) are propositional functions. 32 JACQUES MOESCHLER (15b) and (15c) are inconsistent readings with the negative clause the king of France is not bald. Why? (15b) asserts the existence of an individual, that is, a unique individual who is not king of France and bald. Even if this description would imply that we are all kings of France except one person, this description does not fit with the content of the negative clause the king of France is not bald. The only possible description corresponding to (15b) is something difficult to express, maybe (16): (16) The only one who is not king of France is bald. (15c) is not consistent with the meaning of the negative clause either, because it states that there is a king who is not unique and bald. (17) could be a possible linguistic expression of (15c): (17) The kings of France are bald. So, the last logical possible reading is (15d): it states that there is a unique king of France who is NOT bald. Here, negation is internal, that is, modifies a propositional function (Bx). This reading is the exact reading of the ordinary negation of (9), that is, (10). So negation can have, relative to the logical form given in (14), only two targets: the whole proposition and the propositional function corresponding to the description of the predicate. Now, we have a very nice explanation of the two readings: external negation has in its scope a quantified logical form, that is, a full interpretable proposition; internal negation has in its scope the predicate (bald) its argument (the king of France) modifies.
Recommended publications
  • Chapter 18 Negation
    Chapter 18 Negation Jong-Bok Kim Kyung Hee University, Seoul Each language has a way to express (sentential) negation that reverses the truth value of a certain sentence, but employs language-particular expressions and gram- matical strategies. There are four main types of negatives in expressing sentential negation: the adverbial negative, the morphological negative, the negative auxil- iary verb, and the preverbal negative. This chapter discusses HPSG analyses for these four strategies in marking sentential negation. 1 Modes of expressing negation There are four main types of negative markers in expressing negation in lan- guages: the morphological negative, the negative auxiliary verb, the adverbial negative, and the clitic-like preverbal negative (see Dahl 1979; Payne 1985; Zanut- tini 2001; Dryer 2005).1 Each of these types is illustrated in the following: (1) a. Ali elmalar-i ser-me-di-;. (Turkish) Ali apples-ACC like-NEG-PST-3SG ‘Ali didn’t like apples.’ b. sensayng-nim-i o-ci anh-usi-ess-ta. (Korean) teacher-HON-NOM come-CONN NEG-HON-PST-DECL ‘The teacher didn’t come.’ c. Dominique (n’) écrivait pas de lettre. (French) Dominique NEG wrote NEG of letter ‘Dominique did not write a letter.’ 1The term negator or negative marker is a cover term for any linguistic expression functioning as sentential negation. Jong-Bok Kim. 2021. Negation. In Stefan Müller, Anne Abeillé, Robert D. Borsley & Jean- Pierre Koenig (eds.), Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar: The handbook. Prepublished version. Berlin: Language Science Press. [Pre- liminary page numbering] Jong-Bok Kim d. Gianni non legge articoli di sintassi. (Italian) Gianni NEG reads articles of syntax ‘Gianni doesn’t read syntax articles.’ As shown in (1a), languages like Turkish have typical examples of morphological negatives where negation is expressed by an inflectional category realized on the verb by affixation.
    [Show full text]
  • UNIT-I Mathematical Logic Statements and Notations
    UNIT-I Mathematical Logic Statements and notations: A proposition or statement is a declarative sentence that is either true or false (but not both). For instance, the following are propositions: “Paris is in France” (true), “London is in Denmark” (false), “2 < 4” (true), “4 = 7 (false)”. However the following are not propositions: “what is your name?” (this is a question), “do your homework” (this is a command), “this sentence is false” (neither true nor false), “x is an even number” (it depends on what x represents), “Socrates” (it is not even a sentence). The truth or falsehood of a proposition is called its truth value. Connectives: Connectives are used for making compound propositions. The main ones are the following (p and q represent given propositions): Name Represented Meaning Negation ¬p “not p” Conjunction p q “p and q” Disjunction p q “p or q (or both)” Exclusive Or p q “either p or q, but not both” Implication p ⊕ q “if p then q” Biconditional p q “p if and only if q” Truth Tables: Logical identity Logical identity is an operation on one logical value, typically the value of a proposition that produces a value of true if its operand is true and a value of false if its operand is false. The truth table for the logical identity operator is as follows: Logical Identity p p T T F F Logical negation Logical negation is an operation on one logical value, typically the value of a proposition that produces a value of true if its operand is false and a value of false if its operand is true.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 1 Logic and Set Theory
    Chapter 1 Logic and Set Theory To criticize mathematics for its abstraction is to miss the point entirely. Abstraction is what makes mathematics work. If you concentrate too closely on too limited an application of a mathematical idea, you rob the mathematician of his most important tools: analogy, generality, and simplicity. – Ian Stewart Does God play dice? The mathematics of chaos In mathematics, a proof is a demonstration that, assuming certain axioms, some statement is necessarily true. That is, a proof is a logical argument, not an empir- ical one. One must demonstrate that a proposition is true in all cases before it is considered a theorem of mathematics. An unproven proposition for which there is some sort of empirical evidence is known as a conjecture. Mathematical logic is the framework upon which rigorous proofs are built. It is the study of the principles and criteria of valid inference and demonstrations. Logicians have analyzed set theory in great details, formulating a collection of axioms that affords a broad enough and strong enough foundation to mathematical reasoning. The standard form of axiomatic set theory is denoted ZFC and it consists of the Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) axioms combined with the axiom of choice (C). Each of the axioms included in this theory expresses a property of sets that is widely accepted by mathematicians. It is unfortunately true that careless use of set theory can lead to contradictions. Avoiding such contradictions was one of the original motivations for the axiomatization of set theory. 1 2 CHAPTER 1. LOGIC AND SET THEORY A rigorous analysis of set theory belongs to the foundations of mathematics and mathematical logic.
    [Show full text]
  • A Symmetric Lambda-Calculus Corresponding to the Negation
    A Symmetric Lambda-Calculus Corresponding to the Negation-Free Bilateral Natural Deduction Tatsuya Abe Software Technology and Artificial Intelligence Research Laboratory, Chiba Institute of Technology, 2-17-1 Tsudanuma, Narashino, Chiba, 275-0016, Japan [email protected] Daisuke Kimura Department of Information Science, Toho University, 2-2-1 Miyama, Funabashi, Chiba, 274-8510, Japan [email protected] Abstract Filinski constructed a symmetric lambda-calculus consisting of expressions and continuations which are symmetric, and functions which have duality. In his calculus, functions can be encoded to expressions and continuations using primitive operators. That is, the duality of functions is not derived in the calculus but adopted as a principle of the calculus. In this paper, we propose a simple symmetric lambda-calculus corresponding to the negation-free natural deduction based bilateralism in proof-theoretic semantics. In our calculus, continuation types are represented as not negations of formulae but formulae with negative polarity. Function types are represented as the implication and but-not connectives in intuitionistic and paraconsistent logics, respectively. Our calculus is not only simple but also powerful as it includes a call-value calculus corresponding to the call-by-value dual calculus invented by Wadler. We show that mutual transformations between expressions and continuations are definable in our calculus to justify the duality of functions. We also show that every typable function has dual types. Thus, the duality of function is derived from bilateralism. 2012 ACM Subject Classification Theory of computation → Logic; Theory of computation → Type theory Keywords and phrases symmetric lambda-calculus, formulae-as-types, duality, bilateralism, natural deduction, proof-theoretic semantics, but-not connective, continuation, call-by-value Acknowledgements The author thanks Yosuke Fukuda, Tasuku Hiraishi, Kentaro Kikuchi, and Takeshi Tsukada for the fruitful discussions, which clarified contributions of the present paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Journal of Linguistics Negation, 'Presupposition'
    Journal of Linguistics http://journals.cambridge.org/LIN Additional services for Journal of Linguistics: Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here Negation, ‘presupposition’ and the semantics/pragmatics distinction ROBYN CARSTON Journal of Linguistics / Volume 34 / Issue 02 / September 1998, pp 309 ­ 350 DOI: null, Published online: 08 September 2000 Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S0022226798007063 How to cite this article: ROBYN CARSTON (1998). Negation, ‘presupposition’ and the semantics/pragmatics distinction. Journal of Linguistics, 34, pp 309­350 Request Permissions : Click here Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/LIN, IP address: 144.82.107.34 on 12 Oct 2012 J. Linguistics (), –. Printed in the United Kingdom # Cambridge University Press Negation, ‘presupposition’ and the semantics/pragmatics distinction1 ROBYN CARSTON Department of Phonetics and Linguistics, University College London (Received February ; revised April ) A cognitive pragmatic approach is taken to some long-standing problem cases of negation, the so-called presupposition denial cases. It is argued that a full account of the processes and levels of representation involved in their interpretation typically requires the sequential pragmatic derivation of two different propositions expressed. The first is one in which the presupposition is preserved and, following the rejection of this, the second involves the echoic (metalinguistic) use of material falling in the scope of the negation. The semantic base for these processes is the standard anti- presuppositionalist wide-scope negation. A different view, developed by Burton- Roberts (a, b), takes presupposition to be a semantic relation encoded in natural language and so argues for a negation operator that does not cancel presuppositions.
    [Show full text]
  • Folktale Documentation Release 1.0
    Folktale Documentation Release 1.0 Quildreen Motta Nov 05, 2017 Contents 1 Guides 3 2 Indices and tables 5 3 Other resources 7 3.1 Getting started..............................................7 3.2 Folktale by Example........................................... 10 3.3 API Reference.............................................. 12 3.4 How do I................................................... 63 3.5 Glossary................................................. 63 Python Module Index 65 i ii Folktale Documentation, Release 1.0 Folktale is a suite of libraries for generic functional programming in JavaScript that allows you to write elegant modular applications with fewer bugs, and more reuse. Contents 1 Folktale Documentation, Release 1.0 2 Contents CHAPTER 1 Guides • Getting Started A series of quick tutorials to get you up and running quickly with the Folktale libraries. • API reference A quick reference of Folktale’s libraries, including usage examples and cross-references. 3 Folktale Documentation, Release 1.0 4 Chapter 1. Guides CHAPTER 2 Indices and tables • Global Module Index Quick access to all modules. • General Index All functions, classes, terms, sections. • Search page Search this documentation. 5 Folktale Documentation, Release 1.0 6 Chapter 2. Indices and tables CHAPTER 3 Other resources • Licence information 3.1 Getting started This guide will cover everything you need to start using the Folktale project right away, from giving you a brief overview of the project, to installing it, to creating a simple example. Once you get the hang of things, the Folktale By Example guide should help you understanding the concepts behind the library, and mapping them to real use cases. 3.1.1 So, what’s Folktale anyways? Folktale is a suite of libraries for allowing a particular style of functional programming in JavaScript.
    [Show full text]
  • Theorem Proving in Classical Logic
    MEng Individual Project Imperial College London Department of Computing Theorem Proving in Classical Logic Supervisor: Dr. Steffen van Bakel Author: David Davies Second Marker: Dr. Nicolas Wu June 16, 2021 Abstract It is well known that functional programming and logic are deeply intertwined. This has led to many systems capable of expressing both propositional and first order logic, that also operate as well-typed programs. What currently ties popular theorem provers together is their basis in intuitionistic logic, where one cannot prove the law of the excluded middle, ‘A A’ – that any proposition is either true or false. In classical logic this notion is provable, and the_: corresponding programs turn out to be those with control operators. In this report, we explore and expand upon the research about calculi that correspond with classical logic; and the problems that occur for those relating to first order logic. To see how these calculi behave in practice, we develop and implement functional languages for propositional and first order logic, expressing classical calculi in the setting of a theorem prover, much like Agda and Coq. In the first order language, users are able to define inductive data and record types; importantly, they are able to write computable programs that have a correspondence with classical propositions. Acknowledgements I would like to thank Steffen van Bakel, my supervisor, for his support throughout this project and helping find a topic of study based on my interests, for which I am incredibly grateful. His insight and advice have been invaluable. I would also like to thank my second marker, Nicolas Wu, for introducing me to the world of dependent types, and suggesting useful resources that have aided me greatly during this report.
    [Show full text]
  • Learning Dependency-Based Compositional Semantics
    Learning Dependency-Based Compositional Semantics Percy Liang∗ University of California, Berkeley Michael I. Jordan∗∗ University of California, Berkeley Dan Klein† University of California, Berkeley Suppose we want to build a system that answers a natural language question by representing its semantics as a logical form and computing the answer given a structured database of facts. The core part of such a system is the semantic parser that maps questions to logical forms. Semantic parsers are typically trained from examples of questions annotated with their target logical forms, but this type of annotation is expensive. Our goal is to instead learn a semantic parser from question–answer pairs, where the logical form is modeled as a latent variable. We develop a new semantic formalism, dependency-based compositional semantics (DCS) and define a log-linear distribution over DCS logical forms. The model parameters are estimated using a simple procedure that alternates between beam search and numerical optimization. On two standard semantic parsing benchmarks, we show that our system obtains comparable accuracies to even state-of-the-art systems that do require annotated logical forms. 1. Introduction One of the major challenges in natural language processing (NLP) is building systems that both handle complex linguistic phenomena and require minimal human effort. The difficulty of achieving both criteria is particularly evident in training semantic parsers, where annotating linguistic expressions with their associated logical forms is expensive but until recently, seemingly unavoidable. Advances in learning latent-variable models, however, have made it possible to progressively reduce the amount of supervision ∗ Computer Science Division, University of California, Berkeley, CA 94720, USA.
    [Show full text]
  • Expressing Negation
    Expressing Negation William A. Ladusaw University of California, Santa Cruz Introduction* My focus in this paper is the syntax-semantics interface for the interpretation of negation in languages which show negative concord, as illustrated in the sentences in (1)-(4). (1) Nobody said nothing to nobody. [NS English] ‘Nobody said anything to anyone.’ (2) Maria didn’t say nothing to nobody. [NS English] ‘Maria didn’t say anything to anyone.’ (3) Mario non ha parlato di niente con nessuno. [Italian] ‘Mario hasn’t spoken with anyone about anything.’ (4) No m’ha telefonat ningú. [Catalan] ‘Nobody has telephoned me.’ Negative concord (NC) is the indication at multiple points in a clause of the fact that the clause is to be interpreted as semantically negated. In a widely spoken and even more widely understood nonstandard dialect of English, sentences (1) and (2) are interpreted as synonymous with those given as glosses, which are also well-formed in the dialect. The examples in (3) from Italian and (4) from Catalan illustrate the same phenomenon. The occurrence in these sentences of two or three different words, any one of which when correctly positioned would be sufficient to negate a clause, does not guarantee that their interpretation involves two or three independent expressions of negation. These clauses express only one negation, which is, on one view, simply redundantly indicated in two or three different places; each of the italicized terms in these sentences might be seen as having an equal claim to the function of expressing negation. However closer inspection indicates that this is not the correct view.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic, Sets, and Proofs David A
    Logic, Sets, and Proofs David A. Cox and Catherine C. McGeoch Amherst College 1 Logic Logical Statements. A logical statement is a mathematical statement that is either true or false. Here we denote logical statements with capital letters A; B. Logical statements be combined to form new logical statements as follows: Name Notation Conjunction A and B Disjunction A or B Negation not A :A Implication A implies B if A, then B A ) B Equivalence A if and only if B A , B Here are some examples of conjunction, disjunction and negation: x > 1 and x < 3: This is true when x is in the open interval (1; 3). x > 1 or x < 3: This is true for all real numbers x. :(x > 1): This is the same as x ≤ 1. Here are two logical statements that are true: x > 4 ) x > 2. x2 = 1 , (x = 1 or x = −1). Note that \x = 1 or x = −1" is usually written x = ±1. Converses, Contrapositives, and Tautologies. We begin with converses and contrapositives: • The converse of \A implies B" is \B implies A". • The contrapositive of \A implies B" is \:B implies :A" Thus the statement \x > 4 ) x > 2" has: • Converse: x > 2 ) x > 4. • Contrapositive: x ≤ 2 ) x ≤ 4. 1 Some logical statements are guaranteed to always be true. These are tautologies. Here are two tautologies that involve converses and contrapositives: • (A if and only if B) , ((A implies B) and (B implies A)). In other words, A and B are equivalent exactly when both A ) B and its converse are true.
    [Show full text]
  • RELATIONAL PARAMETRICITY and CONTROL 1. Introduction the Λ
    Logical Methods in Computer Science Vol. 2 (3:3) 2006, pp. 1–22 Submitted Dec. 16, 2005 www.lmcs-online.org Published Jul. 27, 2006 RELATIONAL PARAMETRICITY AND CONTROL MASAHITO HASEGAWA Research Institute for Mathematical Sciences, Kyoto University, Kyoto 606-8502 Japan, and PRESTO, Japan Science and Technology Agency e-mail address: [email protected] Abstract. We study the equational theory of Parigot’s second-order λµ-calculus in con- nection with a call-by-name continuation-passing style (CPS) translation into a fragment of the second-order λ-calculus. It is observed that the relational parametricity on the tar- get calculus induces a natural notion of equivalence on the λµ-terms. On the other hand, the unconstrained relational parametricity on the λµ-calculus turns out to be inconsis- tent. Following these facts, we propose to formulate the relational parametricity on the λµ-calculus in a constrained way, which might be called “focal parametricity”. Dedicated to Prof. Gordon Plotkin on the occasion of his sixtieth birthday 1. Introduction The λµ-calculus, introduced by Parigot [26], has been one of the representative term calculi for classical natural deduction, and widely studied from various aspects. Although it still is an active research subject, it can be said that we have some reasonable un- derstanding of the first-order propositional λµ-calculus: we have good reduction theories, well-established CPS semantics and the corresponding operational semantics, and also some canonical equational theories enjoying semantic completeness [16, 24, 25, 36, 39]. The last point cannot be overlooked, as such complete axiomatizations provide deep understand- ing of equivalences between proofs and also of the semantic structure behind the syntactic presentation.
    [Show full text]
  • Frege and the Logic of Sense and Reference
    FREGE AND THE LOGIC OF SENSE AND REFERENCE Kevin C. Klement Routledge New York & London Published in 2002 by Routledge 29 West 35th Street New York, NY 10001 Published in Great Britain by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane London EC4P 4EE Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper. Copyright © 2002 by Kevin C. Klement All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any infomration storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Klement, Kevin C., 1974– Frege and the logic of sense and reference / by Kevin Klement. p. cm — (Studies in philosophy) Includes bibliographical references and index ISBN 0-415-93790-6 1. Frege, Gottlob, 1848–1925. 2. Sense (Philosophy) 3. Reference (Philosophy) I. Title II. Studies in philosophy (New York, N. Y.) B3245.F24 K54 2001 12'.68'092—dc21 2001048169 Contents Page Preface ix Abbreviations xiii 1. The Need for a Logical Calculus for the Theory of Sinn and Bedeutung 3 Introduction 3 Frege’s Project: Logicism and the Notion of Begriffsschrift 4 The Theory of Sinn and Bedeutung 8 The Limitations of the Begriffsschrift 14 Filling the Gap 21 2. The Logic of the Grundgesetze 25 Logical Language and the Content of Logic 25 Functionality and Predication 28 Quantifiers and Gothic Letters 32 Roman Letters: An Alternative Notation for Generality 38 Value-Ranges and Extensions of Concepts 42 The Syntactic Rules of the Begriffsschrift 44 The Axiomatization of Frege’s System 49 Responses to the Paradox 56 v vi Contents 3.
    [Show full text]