Introduction to Formal Logic Syntax

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Introduction to Formal Logic Syntax Introduction to Formal Logic Syntax Greg O’Keefe 15th January 2007 This handout gives a summary and example exercises for the technical content of the first part of the course: syntax of PL and QL, and translation between English and these formal languages. This little note is not a substitute for the relevant sections of course text Logic by Paul Tomassi [Tom99]. This is just to emphasise the main points, and give a written form of my examples and explanations from the lectures. The first section outlines the syntax of propositional logic PL. The second discusses formal syntax more generally, and the third section introduces the syntax of quantified logic QL. 1 PL and Compound Statements in English Some English statements are made up of smaller English statements joined by words or phrases such as “and,” “or,” “if ... then ...” and “It is not the case that ...”. Sometimes the same logical structure is expressed less directly. For example, we would say “My car is not red” rather than “It is not the case that my car is red” and we might say “I have one but she has three” rather than “I have one and she has three.” The language of PL models the structure of these compound statements. The connectives of PL and their intuitive meaning are shown in Table 1. A & BA and B A ∨ BA or B A → B If A then B A ↔ BA if and only if B ∼A It is not the case that A Table 1: Connectives of PL Note that A and B here are not sentence letters, but metalinguistic variables which stand for complete PL formulae. To translate some English statements into PL, we first identify the smallest com- plete statements within the text, we assign statement letters P , Q, R, ... to these state- ments, then use the PL connectives to build the same structure as the English. Often 1 the smallest complete statements are not explicit in the text, because they inherit some information from their context. In these cases, we must paraphrase to make the sub- statements explicit. Consider the following example. If you go to university and do not study logic, then you are either foolish or ignorant. “You are either foolish or ignorant” is one sub-statement here connected by an “if ... then ...”, but we should be able to decompose it further. We paraphrase it (preserving the meaning) to “You are foolish or you are ignorant” and now we have two complete statements connected by an “or”. We therefore see that a translation into PL is as shown in Table 2. Key: U = You go to university. L = You study logic. F = You are foolish. I = You are ignorant. Formula: (U & ∼L) → (F ∨ I) Table 2: PL translation example Notice that we use letters which suggest the English sentences they stand for. This helps to make the formula readable. As with computer programming, the readabil- ity of the code or formula can be as important as its formal correctness in practical applications. 2 Formal Syntax in General Syntax is just another word for grammar. Grammar describes the rules for making sentences, but grammars for natural languages such as English are debatable and vague. The syntax for a formal language is perfectly precise what the formulae are, and what their structure is. Definition of a formal language begins with a collection of symbols. For PL it is the statement letters P, Q, R, S, ... the connectives & , ∨ , →, ↔ and ∼, and the brackets ( and ). Notice that each formula P → (Q ∨ R), (Q & ∼Q) ∨ S, . , is a string, that is, a list of these symbols, but not every string of these symbols is a formula: )& P QR, ∼QR∨, . That is, the formulae of a language are a subset of the strings of the languages symbols. The formulae are defined by a collection of formation rules. Usually there will be base rules, which say that certain strings are formulae, and recursive rules which make new formulae out of existing ones. For example, in PL, the base rule says that the 2 sentence letters P, Q, R, S, ... are formulae. Each connective has a recursive rule, so that for example, if A and B are formulae, then so is A & B. In fact, the language of PL is very similar to the expressions of ordinary arithmetic. In arithmetic, we have atomic expressions, the numerals, we have a unary connective, -, and we have several binary connectives, + × . (The - symbol is both a unary and binary connective, but we can determine which is intended from the context.) The formula (P & Q) ∨ (∼P ∨ ∼Q) has the same structure as (3 × 5) + (−3 + −5) . When we look at a formula, we can see which rules have been used to form it. This is the same as seeing what order to perform the operations to evaluate the expression. This structure is sometimes represented as a syntax tree. The structure of the formula determines how its meaning is built up from that of its basic elements, and determines which rules apply to it when doing deduction or semantic analysis. Do not panic about this. If you are able to evaluate the arithtmetic expression above, then you already have an intuitive understanding of the structure of the PL formula. The main connective is the symbol introduced in the last step of formation, or equivalently, the connective that you would evaluate last. In the formula above, the ∨ between the ) and the ( is the main connective. The scope of a connective is that connective and the formulae it connects. So, for example, the scope of the other ∨ (not the main connective) in the above formula is (∼P ∨ ∼Q). 3 QL and the Analysis of English Statements In PL, the simplest formulae are the statement letters, which stand for complete English statements. It is often necessary to analyse these sentences to show that an argument is valid. For example, in class, we discussed the argument in Figure 1. The drums are louder than the bass. The guitar is louder than the drums. Therefore, the guitar is louder than the bass. Figure 1: An example argument We agreed that the argument was valid, however, if we translate it into the lan- guage of PL, we obtain the sequent P, Q : R, which is clearly not valid, because P = true, Q = true, R = false is a counter-example. The validity of the English argument lies in details overlooked by PL. The language of QL allows us to exhibit the internal structure of sentences in terms of what individuals we are talking about, and what properties or relations are being asserted about them. A domain specific vocabulary, or key, for PL consists of assigning a sentence letter to each of the smallest complete sentences in the text we are translating. With QL, a key consists of three things: 3 • the domain - a description of the collection of individuals being discussed • name letters from a, b, c, ..., each assigned to an individual from the domain • Property and Relation letters P, Q, R, ..., each assigned to a property or relation used in the text Thus, we begin a translation into QL by identifying the kind of individuals be- ing talked about, the particular individuals named in the text, and the properties and relationships being asserted about them. In this example, the domain is the musical instraments in a band. The named individuals are the drums, the bass and the guitar. The only property or relation used is the relation “... is louder than ...” This is a two- place relation, or in other words, it is a statement with two holes in it, where names must be inserted. Each property and relation letter has a fixed arity, that is number of arguments. You must write exactly this number of names after it to make a well formed formula. A key for this translation is shown in Table 2. Domain = musical instruments in a band d = the drums b = the bass g = the guitar Lxy = x is louder than y Figure 2: Key for translation of the band example Given this key, the argument can be represented by the sequent Ldb, Lgd : Lgb. We do not yet have a clear enough notion of the semantics of QL to assess the validity of this sequent. In fact it is not valid until we add further axioms about the relation “... is louder than ...” This is as we should expect. To see this, consider the argument of the same form: Dianne loves Bill; George loves Dianne; Therefore George loves Bill. This one is not valid, because the relation is different. We will study properties of relations later in the course. The “Q” in QL stands for quantification, which means ideas like “some” and “all.” Let’s use an alternative key, as we did above with our “George loves Bill” argument. The domain is people, and L represents ...loves..., and b stands for “Bill.” Then we write “everybody loves Bill” as ∀x[Lxb]. Inside the square brackets, we have an unquantified formula, with a variable (x, y, z, ...) in place of a name. We could re- paraphrase the full formula into English as “For each person, that person loves Bill” or “For each person, who we temporarily name x, x loves Bill”. We can have compound formula inside the square brackets, and the variable can occur more than once. For example, if Gx means “x is a girl,” then we may write “All the girls love Bill” as ∀x[Gx → Lxb]. Translating this back into English, we get the awkward but equivalent statement “For each person, if that person is a girl then she loves Bill.” Formulae like this occur often, because we quite often make statements of the form “every something-or-other is a what-do-you-call-it.” 4 There is also an existential quantifier, which we use to formulate statements about “some” things, or “there exists” a such-and-such.
Recommended publications
  • CAS LX 522 Syntax I
    It is likely… CAS LX 522 IP This satisfies the EPP in Syntax I both clauses. The main DPj I′ clause has Mary in SpecIP. Mary The embedded clause has Vi+I VP is the trace in SpecIP. V AP Week 14b. PRO and control ti This specific instance of A- A IP movement, where we move a likely subject from an embedded DP I′ clause to a higher clause is tj generally called subject raising. I VP to leave Reluctance to leave Reluctance to leave Now, consider: Reluctant has two θ-roles to assign. Mary is reluctant to leave. One to the one feeling the reluctance (Experiencer) One to the proposition about which the reluctance holds (Proposition) This looks very similar to Mary is likely to leave. Can we draw the same kind of tree for it? Leave has one θ-role to assign. To the one doing the leaving (Agent). How many θ-roles does reluctant assign? In Mary is reluctant to leave, what θ-role does Mary get? IP Reluctance to leave Reluctance… DPi I′ Mary Vj+I VP In Mary is reluctant to leave, is V AP Mary is doing the leaving, gets Agent t Mary is reluctant to leave. j t from leave. i A′ Reluctant assigns its θ- Mary is showing the reluctance, gets θ roles within AP as A θ IP Experiencer from reluctant. required, Mary moves reluctant up to SpecIP in the main I′ clause by Spellout. ? And we have a problem: I vP But what gets the θ-role to Mary appears to be getting two θ-roles, from leave, and what v′ in violation of the θ-criterion.
    [Show full text]
  • Syntax and Semantics of Propositional Logic
    INTRODUCTIONTOLOGIC Lecture 2 Syntax and Semantics of Propositional Logic. Dr. James Studd Logic is the beginning of wisdom. Thomas Aquinas Outline 1 Syntax vs Semantics. 2 Syntax of L1. 3 Semantics of L1. 4 Truth-table methods. Examples of syntactic claims ‘Bertrand Russell’ is a proper noun. ‘likes logic’ is a verb phrase. ‘Bertrand Russell likes logic’ is a sentence. Combining a proper noun and a verb phrase in this way makes a sentence. Syntax vs. Semantics Syntax Syntax is all about expressions: words and sentences. ‘Bertrand Russell’ is a proper noun. ‘likes logic’ is a verb phrase. ‘Bertrand Russell likes logic’ is a sentence. Combining a proper noun and a verb phrase in this way makes a sentence. Syntax vs. Semantics Syntax Syntax is all about expressions: words and sentences. Examples of syntactic claims ‘likes logic’ is a verb phrase. ‘Bertrand Russell likes logic’ is a sentence. Combining a proper noun and a verb phrase in this way makes a sentence. Syntax vs. Semantics Syntax Syntax is all about expressions: words and sentences. Examples of syntactic claims ‘Bertrand Russell’ is a proper noun. ‘Bertrand Russell likes logic’ is a sentence. Combining a proper noun and a verb phrase in this way makes a sentence. Syntax vs. Semantics Syntax Syntax is all about expressions: words and sentences. Examples of syntactic claims ‘Bertrand Russell’ is a proper noun. ‘likes logic’ is a verb phrase. Combining a proper noun and a verb phrase in this way makes a sentence. Syntax vs. Semantics Syntax Syntax is all about expressions: words and sentences. Examples of syntactic claims ‘Bertrand Russell’ is a proper noun.
    [Show full text]
  • Syntax: Recursion, Conjunction, and Constituency
    Syntax: Recursion, Conjunction, and Constituency Course Readings Recursion Syntax: Conjunction Recursion, Conjunction, and Constituency Tests Auxiliary Verbs Constituency . Syntax: Course Readings Recursion, Conjunction, and Constituency Course Readings Recursion Conjunction Constituency Tests The following readings have been posted to the Moodle Auxiliary Verbs course site: I Language Files: Chapter 5 (pp. 204-215, 216-220) I Language Instinct: Chapter 4 (pp. 74-99) . Syntax: An Interesting Property of our PS Rules Recursion, Conjunction, and Our Current PS Rules: Constituency S ! f NP , CP g VP NP ! (D) (A*) N (CP) (PP*) Course Readings VP ! V (NP) f (NP) (CP) g (PP*) Recursion PP ! P (NP) Conjunction CP ! C S Constituency Tests Auxiliary Verbs An Interesting Feature of These Rules: As we saw last time, these rules allow sentences to contain other sentences. I A sentence must have a VP in it. I A VP can have a CP in it. I A CP must have an S in it. Syntax: An Interesting Property of our PS Rules Recursion, Conjunction, and Our Current PS Rules: Constituency S ! f NP , CP g VP NP ! (D) (A*) N (CP) (PP*) Course Readings VP ! V (NP) f (NP) (CP) g (PP*) Recursion ! PP P (NP) Conjunction CP ! C S Constituency Tests Auxiliary Verbs An Interesting Feature of These Rules: As we saw last time, these rules allow sentences to contain other sentences. S NP VP N V CP Dave thinks C S that . he. is. cool. Syntax: An Interesting Property of our PS Rules Recursion, Conjunction, and Our Current PS Rules: Constituency S ! f NP , CP g VP NP ! (D) (A*) N (CP) (PP*) Course Readings VP ! V (NP) f (NP) (CP) g (PP*) Recursion PP ! P (NP) Conjunction CP ! CS Constituency Tests Auxiliary Verbs Another Interesting Feature of These Rules: These rules also allow noun phrases to contain other noun phrases.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 1: Propositional Logic
    Lecture 1: Propositional Logic Syntax Semantics Truth tables Implications and Equivalences Valid and Invalid arguments Normal forms Davis-Putnam Algorithm 1 Atomic propositions and logical connectives An atomic proposition is a statement or assertion that must be true or false. Examples of atomic propositions are: “5 is a prime” and “program terminates”. Propositional formulas are constructed from atomic propositions by using logical connectives. Connectives false true not and or conditional (implies) biconditional (equivalent) A typical propositional formula is The truth value of a propositional formula can be calculated from the truth values of the atomic propositions it contains. 2 Well-formed propositional formulas The well-formed formulas of propositional logic are obtained by using the construction rules below: An atomic proposition is a well-formed formula. If is a well-formed formula, then so is . If and are well-formed formulas, then so are , , , and . If is a well-formed formula, then so is . Alternatively, can use Backus-Naur Form (BNF) : formula ::= Atomic Proposition formula formula formula formula formula formula formula formula formula formula 3 Truth functions The truth of a propositional formula is a function of the truth values of the atomic propositions it contains. A truth assignment is a mapping that associates a truth value with each of the atomic propositions . Let be a truth assignment for . If we identify with false and with true, we can easily determine the truth value of under . The other logical connectives can be handled in a similar manner. Truth functions are sometimes called Boolean functions. 4 Truth tables for basic logical connectives A truth table shows whether a propositional formula is true or false for each possible truth assignment.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Logic, Language and Meaning 2 Syntax and Semantics of Predicate
    Semantics and Pragmatics 2 Winter 2011 University of Chicago Handout 1 1 Logic, language and meaning • A formal system is a set of primitives, some statements about the primitives (axioms), and some method of deriving further statements about the primitives from the axioms. • Predicate logic (calculus) is a formal system consisting of: 1. A syntax defining the expressions of a language. 2. A set of axioms (formulae of the language assumed to be true) 3. A set of rules of inference for deriving further formulas from the axioms. • We use this formal system as a tool for analyzing relevant aspects of the meanings of natural languages. • A formal system is a syntactic object, a set of expressions and rules of combination and derivation. However, we can talk about the relation between this system and the models that can be used to interpret it, i.e. to assign extra-linguistic entities as the meanings of expressions. • Logic is useful when it is possible to translate natural languages into a logical language, thereby learning about the properties of natural language meaning from the properties of the things that can act as meanings for a logical language. 2 Syntax and semantics of Predicate Logic 2.1 The vocabulary of Predicate Logic 1. Individual constants: fd; n; j; :::g 2. Individual variables: fx; y; z; :::g The individual variables and constants are the terms. 3. Predicate constants: fP; Q; R; :::g Each predicate has a fixed and finite number of ar- guments called its arity or valence. As we will see, this corresponds closely to argument positions for natural language predicates.
    [Show full text]
  • Lambda Calculus and the Decision Problem
    Lambda Calculus and the Decision Problem William Gunther November 8, 2010 Abstract In 1928, Alonzo Church formalized the λ-calculus, which was an attempt at providing a foundation for mathematics. At the heart of this system was the idea of function abstraction and application. In this talk, I will outline the early history and motivation for λ-calculus, especially in recursion theory. I will discuss the basic syntax and the primary rule: β-reduction. Then I will discuss how one would represent certain structures (numbers, pairs, boolean values) in this system. This will lead into some theorems about fixed points which will allow us have some fun and (if there is time) to supply a negative answer to Hilbert's Entscheidungsproblem: is there an effective way to give a yes or no answer to any mathematical statement. 1 History In 1928 Alonzo Church began work on his system. There were two goals of this system: to investigate the notion of 'function' and to create a powerful logical system sufficient for the foundation of mathematics. His main logical system was later (1935) found to be inconsistent by his students Stephen Kleene and J.B.Rosser, but the 'pure' system was proven consistent in 1936 with the Church-Rosser Theorem (which more details about will be discussed later). An application of λ-calculus is in the area of computability theory. There are three main notions of com- putability: Hebrand-G¨odel-Kleenerecursive functions, Turing Machines, and λ-definable functions. Church's Thesis (1935) states that λ-definable functions are exactly the functions that can be “effectively computed," in an intuitive way.
    [Show full text]
  • A Logical Approach to Grammar Description Lionel Clément, Jérôme Kirman, Sylvain Salvati
    A logical approach to grammar description Lionel Clément, Jérôme Kirman, Sylvain Salvati To cite this version: Lionel Clément, Jérôme Kirman, Sylvain Salvati. A logical approach to grammar description. Jour- nal of Language Modelling, Institute of Computer Science, Polish Academy of Sciences, Poland, 2015, Special issue on High-level methodologies for grammar engineering, 3 (1), pp. 87-143 10.15398/jlm.v3i1.94. hal-01251222 HAL Id: hal-01251222 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01251222 Submitted on 19 Jan 2016 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. A logical approach to grammar description Lionel Clément, Jérôme Kirman, and Sylvain Salvati Université de Bordeaux LaBRI France abstract In the tradition of Model Theoretic Syntax, we propose a logical ap- Keywords: proach to the description of grammars. We combine in one formal- grammar ism several tools that are used throughout computer science for their description, logic, power of abstraction: logic and lambda calculus. We propose then a Finite State high-level formalism for describing mildly context sensitive grammars Automata, and their semantic interpretation. As we rely on the correspondence logical between logic and finite state automata, our method combines con- transduction, ciseness with effectivity.
    [Show full text]
  • FOL Syntax: You Will Be Expected to Know
    First-Order Logic A: Syntax CS271P, Fall Quarter, 2018 Introduction to Artificial Intelligence Prof. Richard Lathrop Read Beforehand: R&N 8, 9.1-9.2, 9.5.1-9.5.5 Common Sense Reasoning Example, adapted from Lenat You are told: John drove to the grocery store and bought a pound of noodles, a pound of ground beef, and two pounds of tomatoes. • Is John 3 years old? • Is John a child? • What will John do with the purchases? • Did John have any money? • Does John have less money after going to the store? • Did John buy at least two tomatoes? • Were the tomatoes made in the supermarket? • Did John buy any meat? • Is John a vegetarian? • Will the tomatoes fit in John’s car? • Can Propositional Logic support these inferences? Outline for First-Order Logic (FOL, also called FOPC) • Propositional Logic is Useful --- but Limited Expressive Power • First Order Predicate Calculus (FOPC), or First Order Logic (FOL). – FOPC has expanded expressive power, though still limited. • New Ontology – The world consists of OBJECTS. – OBJECTS have PROPERTIES, RELATIONS, and FUNCTIONS. • New Syntax – Constants, Predicates, Functions, Properties, Quantifiers. • New Semantics – Meaning of new syntax. • Unification and Inference in FOL • Knowledge engineering in FOL FOL Syntax: You will be expected to know • FOPC syntax – Syntax: Sentences, predicate symbols, function symbols, constant symbols, variables, quantifiers • De Morgan’s rules for quantifiers – connections between ∀ and ∃ • Nested quantifiers – Difference between “∀ x ∃ y P(x, y)” and “∃ x ∀ y P(x, y)”
    [Show full text]
  • On Synthetic Undecidability in Coq, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem
    On Synthetic Undecidability in Coq, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem Yannick Forster Dominik Kirst Gert Smolka Saarland University Saarland University Saarland University Saarbrücken, Germany Saarbrücken, Germany Saarbrücken, Germany [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] Abstract like decidability, enumerability, and reductions are avail- We formalise the computational undecidability of validity, able without reference to a concrete model of computation satisfiability, and provability of first-order formulas follow- such as Turing machines, general recursive functions, or ing a synthetic approach based on the computation native the λ-calculus. For instance, representing a given decision to Coq’s constructive type theory. Concretely, we consider problem by a predicate p on a type X, a function f : X ! B Tarski and Kripke semantics as well as classical and intu- with 8x: p x $ f x = tt is a decision procedure, a function itionistic natural deduction systems and provide compact д : N ! X with 8x: p x $ ¹9n: д n = xº is an enumer- many-one reductions from the Post correspondence prob- ation, and a function h : X ! Y with 8x: p x $ q ¹h xº lem (PCP). Moreover, developing a basic framework for syn- for a predicate q on a type Y is a many-one reduction from thetic computability theory in Coq, we formalise standard p to q. Working formally with concrete models instead is results concerning decidability, enumerability, and reducibil- cumbersome, given that every defined procedure needs to ity without reference to a concrete model of computation. be shown representable by a concrete entity of the model.
    [Show full text]
  • Syntax and Logic Errors Teacher’S Notes
    Syntax and logic errors Teacher’s Notes Lesson Plan Length 60 mins Specification Link 2.1.7/p_q Candidates should be able to: Learning objective (a) describe syntax errors and logic errors which may occur while developing a program (b) understand and identify syntax and logic errors Time (min) Activity Further Notes 10 Explain that syntax errors are very common, not just when programming, but in everyday life. Using a projector, display the Interactive Starter greatful, you’re, their, CD’s, Activity and ask the students to suggest where the Although there is much discussion of five syntax errors are. Internet security. Stress that even though there are syntax errors, we can still interpret the meaning of the message but computers are not as accommodating and will reject anything that does not meet the rules of the language being used. 15 Watch the set of videos pausing to discuss the content. 5 Discuss the videos to assess learning. Ask questions such as: • What is a syntax error? A syntax error is an error in the source code of a program. Since computer programs must follow strict syntax to compile correctly, any aspects of the code that do not conform to the syntax of the • Can you list some common syntax errors? programming language will produce a syntax error. • Spelling mistakes • Missing out quotes • Missing out brackets • Using upper case characters in key words e.g. IF instead of if • Missing out a colon or semicolon at end of a statement • What is a logic (or logical error)? • Using tokens in the wrong order A logic error (or logical error) is a ‘bug’ or mistake in a program’s source code that results in incorrect or unexpected behaviour.
    [Show full text]
  • Symbolic Logic: Grammar, Semantics, Syntax
    Symbolic Logic: Grammar, Semantics, Syntax Logic aims to give a precise method or recipe for determining what follows from a given set of sentences. So we need precise definitions of `sentence' and `follows from.' 1. Grammar: What's a sentence? What are the rules that determine whether a string of symbols is a sentence, and when it is not? These rules are known as the grammar of a particular language. We have actually been operating with two different but very closely related grammars this term: a grammar for propositional logic and a grammar for first-order logic. The grammar for propositional logic (thus far) is simple: 1. There are an indefinite number of propositional variables, which we have been symbolizing as A; B; ::: and P; Q; :::; each of these is a sen- tence. ? is also a sentence. 2. If A; B are sentences, then: •:A is a sentence, • A ^ B is a sentence, and • A _ B is a sentence. 3. Nothing else is a sentence: anything that is neither a member of 1, nor constructable via successive applications of 2 to the members of 1, is not a sentence. The grammar for first-order logic (thus far) is more complex. 2 and 3 remain exactly the same as above, but 1 must be replaced by some- thing more complex. First, a list of all predicates (e.g. Tet or SameShape) and proper names (e.g. max; b) of a particular language L must be specified. Then we can define: 1F OL. A series of symbols s is an atomic sentence = s is an n-place predicate followed by an ordered sequence of n proper names.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Logic Propositional Logic
    Mathematical Logic Propositional Logic. Syntax and Semantics Nikolaj Popov and Tudor Jebelean Research Institute for Symbolic Computation, Linz [email protected] Outline Syntax Semantics Syntax The syntax of propositional logic consists in the definition of the set of all propositional logic formulae, or the language of propositional logic formulae, which will contain formulae like: :A A ^ B A ^ :B (:A ^ B) , (A ) B) A ^ :A The language L L is defined over a certain set Σ of symbols: the parentheses, the logical connectives, the logical constants, and an infinite set Θ of propositional variables. Set of symbols: alphabet Σ = f(; )g [ f:; ^; _; ); ,g [ fT; Fg [ Θ Syntax The syntax of propositional logic consists in the definition of the set of all propositional logic formulae, or the language of propositional logic formulae, which will contain formulae like: :A A ^ B A ^ :B (:A ^ B) , (A ) B) A ^ :A The language L L is defined over a certain set Σ of symbols: the parentheses, the logical connectives, the logical constants, and an infinite set Θ of propositional variables. Set of symbols: alphabet Σ = f(; )g [ f:; ^; _; ); ,g [ fT; Fg [ Θ Syntax The syntax of propositional logic consists in the definition of the set of all propositional logic formulae, or the language of propositional logic formulae, which will contain formulae like: :A A ^ B A ^ :B (:A ^ B) , (A ) B) A ^ :A The language L L is defined over a certain set Σ of symbols: the parentheses, the logical connectives, the logical constants, and an infinite set Θ of propositional variables.
    [Show full text]