Download Article (PDF)

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Download Article (PDF) Semiotica 2016; 208: 49–77 Dinda L. Gorlée* Wittgenstein’s persuasive rhetoric DOI 10.1515/sem-2015-0121 Abstract: Wittgenstein surprised with the rhetorical inversion of his style of writing, often at the expense of thought. In his works, he skillfully constructed the fragmentary paragraphs to solve the “confusions” of language. The result of Wittgenstein’s conscious endeavor is the persuasive effect of new reasoning in the “ornamental” type of the philosophical writings about language. Wittgenstein’s verbal genres are the interplay of deduction, induction, and abduction, formed consciously and subconsciously, following the three categories of Peirce’s semio-logical reasoning. Wittgenstein’s rhetoric changed the first certainty of philosophy into the abductive uncertainty of his later works, keeping the story of Wittgenstein’s reasoning in suspense. Keywords: Wittgenstein, stylistics, linguïculture, Peirce, speculative rhetoric, deduction-induction-abduction, Barthes If I do not quite know how to begin a book that is because something is still unclear. For I should like to begin with the original data of philosophy, written & spoken sentences, with books as it were. And here we encounter the difficulty of “Everything is in flux.” And perhaps that is the very point at which to begin. (Wittgenstein 1930, CV 1998: 11) 1 Persuasive and ornamental speech Ludwig Wittgenstein’s (1889–1951) “new” philosophy, as he envisaged it, was to be the idea of writing books and writings in conflicting rhetoric to question the readers. Wittgenstein’s philosophy has become so diversified and specialized in the secondary literature, that we would need a number of examples to show that the first form of systematic knowledge developed into Wittgenstein’s creative philosophy of language. Perhaps he could derive his twentieth-century moder- nity from the difference between his present knowledge and the knowledge of our ancestors. Instead of talking in monologue for himself, Wittgenstein’s life also decided to feature the dialogue as didactic tool of persuasion. Regardless of *Corresponding author: Dinda L. Gorlée, University of Bergen, Bergen, Norway, E-mail: [email protected] 50 Dinda L. Gorlée fame or adversity, Wittgenstein in his later years kept true to his first vocation of finding the social dialogue with the readers. Perhaps Wittgenstein’s personal development could make sense of the world in which he lived by following the footsteps of the orator of Athens, Demosthenes (c. 384–322, BCE). So the legendary story goes that the lawyer Demosthenes was a stutterer (Ostwald 1973: 356–366; Gray 2012: 34). After years of practicing law in the courts of Athens, Demosthenes wanted to overcome his weak voice to become a famous orator with passionate orations to persuade the Greek audience. Standing on the beach of Athens, Demosthenes put a mouthful of pebbles in his mouth to improve the tone of his voice. This handicap practiced his vocal appropriateness or political adequacy to train the acoustics of his eloquent voice against the noise of the sea. The Greek statesman won his own battles, composing and delivering his series of political speeches, and reaching his success in public policy as the great orator of the golden age of Greek oratory. Demosthenes and young Wittgenstein stuttered for words in the articulation in public, inhibiting their power to speak straightforwardly (McGuinness 1988: 52). When writing the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, Wittgenstein’s first speech dis- fluency was clearly observed by his friend Paul Engelmann, when he listened to his explanation of the work. Nervously, Wittgenstein stammered the paragraphs of the incomprehensible and controversial manuscript, while Engelmann, as he said, with a “sensitive understanding for what he wanted to say” helped him find the “right words by stating myself the proposition he had in mind” (qtd. in CPE: 94). Perhaps the blocking of sounds and articulation of words remained after the disappearance of the stammer as the desire of Wittgenstein’s fragmentariness in narrative speech. Wittgenstein also seemed to fulfill the biblical story of Ezekiel’s prophetic vision (c. 600 BCE). During the hard times of the Jewish exile in Babylon, the prophet Ezekiel pronounced divine speeches promising to the banished Israelite people the “garden of Eden” (Ezek. 36: 35 Authorized King James Version). The vision of the future fixed on the future in the Promised Land. Following the exile, the Jews would restore the ruins of the Temple at Jerusalem (Ezek. 40–48). Ezekiel’s spiritual images explained the process of restoration in the volumes of the outer wall, the dimensions of the inner courtyard and the sanctuary of the Hebrew Temple. The complex dimensionality of Jerusalem’s sacred temple was measured exactly by Ezekiel. His gift of prediction was full of detailed information about the numerical and algebraic dimensions of the breadth and length, the height and depth of the parts of the Temple. Metaphorically, the deduction of the outer wall, the induction of the inner courtyard, and the abduction of the sanctuary gave the three dimensions of Ezekiel’s building tools to draw an analogy between the shape or form of the architectural framework and Wittgenstein’s narrative style and genre. Wittgenstein’s persuasive rhetoric 51 The domain of Wittgenstein’s life started with the philosophical “oratory” of his early work, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. The basic thoughts of this book were about solving the questions of grammar and logic. The effectiveness of this academic volume was in the paragraphs measured in the numbered and subnumbered items. Tractatus is the only work of Wittgenstein that was published during Wittgenstein’s lifetime. The other writings, from the 1930s onwards, The Blue and Brown Book and his masterwork Philosophical Investigations right up to his last pages in On Certainty (OC) feature his mature philosophy. These and other “new” works (articles, lectures, andnotebooks)werewrittenandrewrittenbyWittgensteintoachievethefinal formulation of his world view. However, Wittgenstein’sworksandwritingswere circulated in the provisional form of stencils produced to be read by interested colleagues and students suitable for early dialogue in academia. The dimensionality of the contemporary scientific rules shaped Wittgenstein’s early linguistics of the Tractatus. Wittgenstein focused on true or false proposi- tions, which he judged not only by appearances but from the facts of logic and mathematics. In the series of propositions, he revealed the list of free vari- ables used in the “confusions” of language in order to clear up the doubtful points. According to Lunsford, the “subversive” difficulties indicate the relativism of the “vitality, the sense of excitement and playful purpose” (1992: 77) regarding the production of words with a new meaning. As a creative philosopher, Wittgenstein’s new ideas solved the “good” and “false” meaning of linguistic problems through the cultural background of the community. The novelty of Wittgenstein’s language philosophy animates and inspires the fact that language is not a fixed collection of words and sentences, but a shared instrument for all speakers and readers. Language shows the linguistic-and-cultural mannerisms of linguïculture (Anderson and Gorlée 2011: 222–226). Wittgenstein did not write only logical “books” but composed his “albums” written in daily language (PI 2009 [1953]: 4; see Pichler 2002, 2004, 2009; Gorlée 2012: 68–69, 187, 228). Like Barthes, Wittgenstein transformed the ordinary state- ments of language into literature, creating for the author “akindofsocial,theolo- gical, mythic, aesthetic, moral end” (Barthes 1983 [1979]: 492). The literary speeches and conversations signify that the traditional type of the “architectural and preme- ditated” book existed to “reproduce an order of the world” as opposed to chaos; but the relative order led Wittgenstein to transfigure it into “a kind of written word according to a special code” (Barthes 1983 [1979]: 491–492). After publishing the coded form of the Tractatus, Wittgenstein wrote that he was, as Barthes, not able to: … achieve the status of the Book (of the Work); it is only an Album … The Album is a collection of leaflets not only interchangeable (even this would be nothing), but above all infinitely suppressible … to the complete annihilation of the Album, with 52 Dinda L. Gorlée theexcusethat“Idon’t like this one”: this is the method of Groucho and Chico Marx, reading aloud and tearing up each clause of the contract which is meant to bind them. (Barthes 1983 [1979]: 492) Wittgenstein’s fragmentary albums unite the unbroken and broken signs in his stream of discourse (Gorlée 2007). In the theory of logic in the literary frame- work, Wittgenstein attempted to operate the simple and complex signs of language to create a permanent fixture between the official form of published book and the intimacy of the album. One could argue that Wittgenstein followed the Peircean categories of sense, meaning, and significance (NEM 3: 844), expressing in his reasoning the three stages of thought. Wittgenstein created the pragmatic stages formulated in words, paraphrases, and arguments. Although the three stages of thought would suggest Wittgenstein’s reading of Peirce’s work, the inescapable truth is that Wittgenstein did not read Peirce, although he could have discussed the semiotic themes, and particularly Peirce’s semiotics, with his English friend, mathematician Frank Ramsey (Gorlée 2012: 27–30). This
Recommended publications
  • BWS Newsletter No 18 24/11/2015, 20:45
    BWS Newsletter no 18 24/11/2015, 20:45 From: British Wittgenstein Society [[email protected]] Subject: Newsletter no.18 BWS website home August 2013 BWS Newsletter Issue no 18 Contents Nota Bene The Wittgenstein-Skinner Archive Pdf version (216 kb) Nota Bene Arthur Gibson on Wittgenstein’s Conferences rediscovered archive Around the world Wittgenstein postings In early October 1941 German bombers Lecture series attacked Oakington RAF base. Victims Pastures new were rushed to hospital in Cambridge. Housekeeping The only slightly later admission of a Executive Committee polio patient was unnoticed, by-passed, being left untreated for very many hours in a corridor. This is how Wittgenstein’s closest friend Francis Skinner came to die at the age of 29. About BWS Within the week of Skinner’s funeral, in a state of trauma, Ludwig attempted to resign his Philosophy Chair; arranged to leave Cambridge for Guy’s Hospital working to fulfil his, now memorial, plan with Francis; attended Francis’ funeral; reclaimed from Skinner’s family the Wittgenstein- BWS is a British focal point for research and exchange Skinner Archive, and posted them to Skinner’s school of ideas among Wittgenstein scholars and students friend, Reuben Goodstein. Eventually Goodstein gave the throughout the world. Archive to the Mathematical Association. It was a much- appreciated invitation from the Association (and full This Newsletter will be sent exclusively to members of acknowledgement to it in references here), with the the BWS, on a regular basis, in order to draw attention support of Trinity College, for me to research and prepare to updates on the website, or to share as yet unpublished this unpublished Archive for book publication.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein in Exile
    Wittgenstein in Exile “My thoughts are one hundred per cent Hebraic.” -Wittgenstein to Drury, 19491 Wittgenstein was born in 1889 into one of the richest families in Central Europe. He lived and learned at home, in Vienna, until 1903, when he was 14. We have no record of his thoughts about the turn of the last century, but it is unlikely that it seemed very significant to him. The Viennese of the time had little inclination to consider the possibilities of change, and the over-ripe era in which Wittgenstein grew up did not really end until Austria-Hungary’s defeat, in World War I, and subsequent dismantling. But the family in which Wittgenstein grew up apparently felt that European culture had already come to an end in the 1840’s. And Wittgenstein himself felt he belonged to an era that had vanished with the death of the composer Robert Schumann (1810-1856).2 Somewhere in the middle of the Nineteenth Century there was an important change into the contemporary era, of which Wittgenstein did not feel a part. Wittgenstein’s understanding of history, and his consequent self-understanding in relation to his times, was deeply influenced by Oswald Spengler, who in 1918 published The Decline of the West [Der Untergang des Abenlandes]. This book, expanded to a second volume in 1922, and revised in 1923, became a best-seller in post-war Europe. Wittgenstein made numerous references to it in 1930-1931, and acknowledged Spengler as one of his ten noteworthy influences.3 According to Spengler, cultures grow, flower, and deteriorate naturally, according to their own internal form, much as a human being does.
    [Show full text]
  • John P. Burgess Department of Philosophy Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08544-1006, USA [email protected]
    John P. Burgess Department of Philosophy Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08544-1006, USA [email protected] LOGIC & PHILOSOPHICAL METHODOLOGY Introduction For present purposes “logic” will be understood to mean the subject whose development is described in Kneale & Kneale [1961] and of which a concise history is given in Scholz [1961]. As the terminological discussion at the beginning of the latter reference makes clear, this subject has at different times been known by different names, “analytics” and “organon” and “dialectic”, while inversely the name “logic” has at different times been applied much more broadly and loosely than it will be here. At certain times and in certain places — perhaps especially in Germany from the days of Kant through the days of Hegel — the label has come to be used so very broadly and loosely as to threaten to take in nearly the whole of metaphysics and epistemology. Logic in our sense has often been distinguished from “logic” in other, sometimes unmanageably broad and loose, senses by adding the adjectives “formal” or “deductive”. The scope of the art and science of logic, once one gets beyond elementary logic of the kind covered in introductory textbooks, is indicated by two other standard references, the Handbooks of mathematical and philosophical logic, Barwise [1977] and Gabbay & Guenthner [1983-89], though the latter includes also parts that are identified as applications of logic rather than logic proper. The term “philosophical logic” as currently used, for instance, in the Journal of Philosophical Logic, is a near-synonym for “nonclassical logic”. There is an older use of the term as a near-synonym for “philosophy of language”.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1889-1951) by Craig Kaczorowski
    Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1889-1951) by Craig Kaczorowski Encyclopedia Copyright © 2015, glbtq, Inc. Entry Copyright © 2004, glbtq, inc. Reprinted from http://www.glbtq.com The Austrian-British philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein is considered one of the most significant thinkers of the twentieth century, especially for his valuable contributions within the field of Linguistic Philosophy. His major works on language and linguistics include Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (1922), and Philosophical Investigations (1953), which was published posthumously. Early Life and Education Born Ludwig Josef Johann Wittgenstein in Vienna on April 26, 1889, he was the youngest of eight children raised in a wealthy and cultured Jewish family. Initially educated privately at home, at the age of 14 he began attending a school in Linz, Austria that specialized in mathematics and natural science. In 1906, he went to Berlin to study mechanical engineering and two years later registered at the University of Manchester in England to study for his doctorate in engineering. Over time, however, Wittgenstein developed a greater interest in mathematics and mathematical logic, and he transferred to Trinity College, University of Cambridge, where he took courses from 1912 to 1913 given by the distinguished philosopher and mathematician Bertrand Russell. In November 1912, on the recommendation of fellow student John Maynard Keynes, Wittgenstein was elected to the elite Cambridge society known as the Apostles, which at that time had an aura of homoeroticism. This homoerotic atmosphere made Wittgenstein uncomfortable, however, and he stopped attending meetings. Finding Cambridge a less than ideal place to work, since he felt that his fellow academics lacked depth, Wittgenstein went to Skjolden in Norway and continued his mathematical and philosophical investigations in seclusion.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Relation of Informal to Formal Logic
    University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 2 May 15th, 9:00 AM - May 17th, 5:00 PM On the Relation of Informal to Formal Logic Dale Jacquette The Pensylvania State University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive Part of the Philosophy Commons Jacquette, Dale, "On the Relation of Informal to Formal Logic" (1997). OSSA Conference Archive. 60. https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/OSSA2/papersandcommentaries/60 This Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences and Conference Proceedings at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in OSSA Conference Archive by an authorized conference organizer of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ON THE RELATION OF INFORMAL TO FORMAL LOGIC Dale Jacquette Department of Philosophy The Pennsylvania State University ©1998, Dale Jacquette Abstract: The distinction between formal and informal logic is clarified as a prelude to considering their ideal relation. Aristotle's syllogistic describes forms of valid inference, and is in that sense a formal logic. Yet the square of opposition and rules of middle term distribution of positive or negative propositions in an argument's premises and conclusion are standardly received as devices of so- called informal logic and critical reasoning. I propose a more exact criterion for distinguishing between formal and informal logic, and then defend a model for fruitful interaction between informal and formal methods of investigating and critically assessing the logic of arguments. *** 1. A Strange Dichotomy In the history of logic a division between formal and informal methods has emerged.
    [Show full text]
  • Advice on the Logic of Argument†
    Revista del Instituto de Filosofía, Universidad de Valparaíso, Año 1, N° 1. Junio 2013. Pags. 7 – 34 Advice on the Logic of Argument† John Woods Resumen Desde su creación moderna a principios de la década de los 70, la lógica informal ha puesto un especial énfasis en el análisis de las falacias y los esquemas de diálogo argumentativo. Desarrollos simultáneos en los círculos que se ocupan de los actos de comunicación de habla exhiben una concentración en el carácter dialéctico de la discusión. PALABRAS CLAVE: Lógica informal, argumento, diálogos Abstract Since its modern inception in the early 1970s, informal logic has placed a special emphasis on the analysis of fallacies and argumentative dialogue schemes. Concurrent developments in speech communication circles exhibit a like concentration on the dialectical character of argument. KEYWORDS: Informal logic, argument, dialogues “But the old connection [of logic] with philosophy is closest to my heart right now . I hope that logic will have another chance in its mother area.” Johan van Benthem “On [the] traditional view of the subject, the phrase ‘formal logic’ is pleonasm and ‘informal logic’ oxymoron.” John Burgess 1. Background remarks Logic began abstractly, as the theoretical core of a general theory of real-life argument. This was Aristotle’s focus in Topics and On Sophistical Refutations and a † Recibido: abril 2013. Aceptado: mayo 2013. The Abductive Systems Group, Department of Philosophy, University of British Columbia 8 / Revista de Humanidades de Valparaíso, Año 1, N° 1 dominant theme of mediaeval dialectic. In our own day, the intellectual skeins that matter for argument-minded logicians are the formal logics of dialogues and games and on the less technical side of the street informal logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Informal Logic
    Document generated on 09/28/2021 9:04 a.m. Informal Logic A Dialectical View on Conduction: Reasons, Warrants, and Normal Suasory Inclinations Shiyang Yu and Frank Zenker Volume 39, Number 1, 2019 Article abstract When Carl Wellman (1971) introduced the reasoning-type conduction, he URI: https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1060809ar endorsed a dialectical view on natural language argumentation. Contemporary DOI: https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v39i1.5080 scholarship, by contrast, treats conductive argument predominantly on a product view. Not only did Wellman’s reasons for a dialectical view thus fall See table of contents into disregard; a product-treatment of conduction also flouts the standard semantics of ‘argument’. Attempting to resolve these difficulties, our paper traces Wellman’s preference for a dialectical view to the role of defeasible Publisher(s) warrants. These act as stand-ins for (parts of) value hierarchies that arguers of normal suasory inclination find acceptable. We also improve on extant ways of Informal Logic diagramming conduction and distinguish two of its structural variants. ISSN 0824-2577 (print) 2293-734X (digital) Explore this journal Cite this article Yu, S. & Zenker, F. (2019). A Dialectical View on Conduction: Reasons, Warrants, and Normal Suasory Inclinations. Informal Logic, 39(1), 32–69. https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v39i1.5080 Copyright (c), 2019 Shiyang Yu, Frank Zenker This document is protected by copyright law. Use of the services of Érudit (including reproduction) is subject to its terms and conditions, which can be viewed online. https://apropos.erudit.org/en/users/policy-on-use/ This article is disseminated and preserved by Érudit.
    [Show full text]
  • Defense of Fallacy Theory
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Scholarship at UWindsor University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 11 May 18th, 9:00 AM - May 21st, 5:00 PM A (Modest) Defense of Fallacy Theory Scott F. Aikin Vanderbilt University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive Part of the Philosophy Commons Aikin, Scott F., "A (Modest) Defense of Fallacy Theory" (2016). OSSA Conference Archive. 92. https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/OSSA11/papersandcommentaries/92 This Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences and Conference Proceedings at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in OSSA Conference Archive by an authorized conference organizer of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A Modest Defense of Fallacy Theory SCOTT F. AIKIN Philosophy Vanderbilt University 111 Furman Hall Nashville, TN 37240 USA [email protected] Abstract: Fallacy theory has three significant challenges to it: the generality, scope, and negativity problems. To the generality problem, the connection between general types of bad arguments and tokens is a matter of refining the use of the vocabulary. To the scope problem, the breadth of fallacy’s instances is cause for development. To the negativity problem, fallacy theory must be coordinated with a program of adversariality-management. Keywords: fallacy theory; minimal adversariality 1. Introduction Fallacy theory is the convergence of three broad programs in the study of argument. First is the first-order research program of defining fallacy, taxonomizing and finding new types.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Logic and Critical Thinking
    Introduction to Logic and Critical Thinking Version 1.4 Matthew J. Van Cleave Lansing Community College Introduction to Logic and Critical Thinking by Matthew J. Van Cleave is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License. To view a copy of this license, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. Table of contents Preface Chapter 1: Reconstructing and analyzing arguments 1.1 What is an argument? 1.2 Identifying arguments 1.3 Arguments vs. explanations 1.4 More complex argument structures 1.5 Using your own paraphrases of premises and conclusions to reconstruct arguments in standard form 1.6 Validity 1.7 Soundness 1.8 Deductive vs. inductive arguments 1.9 Arguments with missing premises 1.10 Assuring, guarding, and discounting 1.11 Evaluative language 1.12 Evaluating a real-life argument Chapter 2: Formal methods of evaluating arguments 2.1 What is a formal method of evaluation and why do we need them? 2.2 Propositional logic and the four basic truth functional connectives 2.3 Negation and disjunction 2.4 Using parentheses to translate complex sentences 2.5 “Not both” and “neither nor” 2.6 The truth table test of validity 2.7 Conditionals 2.8 “Unless” 2.9 Material equivalence 2.10 Tautologies, contradictions, and contingent statements 2.11 Proofs and the 8 valid forms of inference 2.12 How to construct proofs 2.13 Short review of propositional logic 2.14 Categorical logic 2.15 The Venn test of validity for immediate categorical inferences 2.16 Universal statements and existential commitment 2.17 Venn validity for categorical syllogisms Chapter 3: Evaluating inductive arguments and probabilistic and statistical fallacies 3.1 Inductive arguments and statistical generalizations 3.2 Inference to the best explanation and the seven explanatory virtues 3.3 Analogical arguments 3.4 Causal arguments 3.5 Probability 3.6 The conjunction fallacy 3.7 The base rate fallacy 3.8 The small numbers fallacy 3.9 Regression to the mean fallacy 3.10 Gambler’s fallacy Chapter 4: Informal fallacies 4.1 Formal vs.
    [Show full text]
  • Informal Logic 25 Years Later the First International Symposium On
    Informal logic 25 years later The First International Symposium on Informal Logic, held on this campus on June 26 to 28, 1978, was a rise to self-consciousness of a newly distinguished sub-field of philosophy. This sub-field differentiated itself through the belief of some philosophy instructors in North American colleges and universities that the traditional introductory logic course was not much good at helping to improve students’ abilities to deal with the arguments they encountered in everyday life and in academic contexts. Courses centred on formal systems–whether the systems of categorical syllogistic and propositional logic done by truth tables or the more comprehensive and up-to-date system of first-order logic–had no relevance to the highly charged debates of the late 1960s and early 1970s about such issues as American military action in Vietnam and the position of women in society. In response, a new kind of textbook began to emerge, often focussed on the informal fallacies, which had been a neglected backwater of the traditional introductory logic course. A pioneer among these textbooks was Howard Kahane’s Logic and Contemporary Rhetoric, subtitled “The Use of Reason in Everyday Life”, the first edition of which was published in 1971 (Kahane 1971); it is now in its ninth edition. Kahane, who gave a paper at the First International Symposium on Informal Logic entitled “The Nature and Classification of Fallacies” (Kahane 1980), died two years ago, on May 2, 2001. The notice of his death in the Proceedings And Addresses of the American Philosophical Association (Hausman et al.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein's Philosophical Development: Phenomenology, Grammar, Method, and the Anthropological View
    Nordic Wittgenstein Review 5 (2) 2016 INVITED PAPER Juliet Floyd jfloyd @ bu.edu Chains of Life: Turing, Lebensform, and the Emergence of Wittgenstein’s Later Style Abstract This essay accounts for the notion of Lebensform by assigning it a logical role in Wittgenstein’s later philosophy. Wittgenstein’s additions of the notion to his manuscripts of the PI occurred during the initial drafting of the book 1936-7, after he abandoned his effort to revise The Brown Book. It is argued that this constituted a substantive step forward in his attitude toward the notion of simplicity as it figures within the notion of logical analysis. Next, a reconstruction of his later remarks on Lebensformen is offered which factors in his reading of Alan Turing’s “On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem“ (1936/7), as well as his discussions with Turing 1937-1939. An interpretation of the five occurrences of Lebensform in the PI is then given in terms of a logical “regression” to Lebensform as a fundamental notion. This regression characterizes Wittgenstein’s mature answer to the question, “What is the nature of the logical?” 1. Introduction Lebensform is an important gauge of the development of Wittgenstein’s thought. It represents, from a regressive point of view, the place he finally chased down to. In foundational matters such as these, it is often the simplest, naïve perspective that comes last in a thinker’s (or a tradition’s) evolution, the working through 7 Juliet Floyd CC-BY of how to get back home to the primordial basis, the extraction of fundamentals from a jungle of technical accretions.
    [Show full text]
  • A Philosophical Examination of Proofs in Mathematics Eric Almeida
    Undergraduate Review Volume 3 Article 13 2007 A Philosophical Examination of Proofs in Mathematics Eric Almeida Follow this and additional works at: http://vc.bridgew.edu/undergrad_rev Part of the Logic and Foundations Commons, and the Logic and foundations of mathematics Commons Recommended Citation Almeida, Eric (2007). A Philosophical Examination of Proofs in Mathematics. Undergraduate Review, 3, 80-84. Available at: http://vc.bridgew.edu/undergrad_rev/vol3/iss1/13 This item is available as part of Virtual Commons, the open-access institutional repository of Bridgewater State University, Bridgewater, Massachusetts. Copyright © 2007 Eric Almeida 0 A Philosophical Examination of Proofs in Mathematics Eric Almeida Eric Almeida is a Philosophy Major. This “The purpose of a proof is to understand, not verify”-- Arnold Ross. project was mentored by Dr. Catherine n mathematics, a proof is a demonstration that, given certain axioms, some Womack. statement of interest is necessarily true. Proofs employ logic but usually include some amount of natural language which of course admits some ambiguity. In fact, the vast majority of proofs in written mathematics can be considered as applications of informal logic. The distinction has led to much Iexamination of current and historical mathematical practice, quasi-empiricism in mathematics. One of the concerns with the philosophy of mathematics is the role of language and logic in proofs, and mathematics as a language. Regardless of one’s attitude to formalism, the result that is proved to be true is a theorem; in a completely formal proof it would be the final word, and the complete proof shows how it follows from the axioms alone.
    [Show full text]