Advice on the Logic of Argument†
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Deduction Systems Based on Resolution, We Limit the Following Considerations to Transition Systems Based on Analytic Calculi
Author’s Address Norbert Eisinger European Computer–Industry Research Centre, ECRC Arabellastr. 17 D-8000 M¨unchen 81 F. R. Germany [email protected] and Hans J¨urgen Ohlbach Max–Planck–Institut f¨ur Informatik Im Stadtwald D-6600 Saarbr¨ucken 11 F. R. Germany [email protected] Publication Notes This report appears as chapter 4 in Dov Gabbay (ed.): ‘Handbook of Logic in Artificial Intelligence and Logic Programming, Volume I: Logical Foundations’. It will be published by Oxford University Press, 1992. Fragments of the material already appeared in chapter two of Bl¨asis & B¨urckert: Deduction Systems in Artificial Intelligence, Ellis Horwood Series in Artificial Intelligence, 1989. A draft version has been published as SEKI Report SR-90-12. The report is also published as an internal technical report of ECRC, Munich. Acknowledgements The writing of the chapters for the handbook has been a highly coordinated effort of all the people involved. We want to express our gratitude for their many helpful contributions, which unfortunately are impossible to list exhaustively. Special thanks for reading earlier drafts and giving us detailed feedback, go to our second reader, Bob Kowalski, and to Wolfgang Bibel, Elmar Eder, Melvin Fitting, Donald W. Loveland, David Plaisted, and J¨org Siekmann. Work on this chapter started when both of us were members of the Markgraf Karl group at the Universit¨at Kaiserslautern, Germany. With our former colleagues there we had countless fruitful discus- sions, which, again, cannot be credited in detail. During that time this research was supported by the “Sonderforschungsbereich 314, K¨unstliche Intelligenz” of the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG). -
Domain Theory and the Logic of Observable Properties
Domain Theory and the Logic of Observable Properties Samson Abramsky Submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Queen Mary College University of London October 31st 1987 Abstract The mathematical framework of Stone duality is used to synthesize a number of hitherto separate developments in Theoretical Computer Science: • Domain Theory, the mathematical theory of computation introduced by Scott as a foundation for denotational semantics. • The theory of concurrency and systems behaviour developed by Milner, Hennessy et al. based on operational semantics. • Logics of programs. Stone duality provides a junction between semantics (spaces of points = denotations of computational processes) and logics (lattices of properties of processes). Moreover, the underlying logic is geometric, which can be com- putationally interpreted as the logic of observable properties—i.e. properties which can be determined to hold of a process on the basis of a finite amount of information about its execution. These ideas lead to the following programme: 1. A metalanguage is introduced, comprising • types = universes of discourse for various computational situa- tions. • terms = programs = syntactic intensions for models or points. 2. A standard denotational interpretation of the metalanguage is given, assigning domains to types and domain elements to terms. 3. The metalanguage is also given a logical interpretation, in which types are interpreted as propositional theories and terms are interpreted via a program logic, which axiomatizes the properties they satisfy. 2 4. The two interpretations are related by showing that they are Stone duals of each other. Hence, semantics and logic are guaranteed to be in harmony with each other, and in fact each determines the other up to isomorphism. -
John P. Burgess Department of Philosophy Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08544-1006, USA [email protected]
John P. Burgess Department of Philosophy Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08544-1006, USA [email protected] LOGIC & PHILOSOPHICAL METHODOLOGY Introduction For present purposes “logic” will be understood to mean the subject whose development is described in Kneale & Kneale [1961] and of which a concise history is given in Scholz [1961]. As the terminological discussion at the beginning of the latter reference makes clear, this subject has at different times been known by different names, “analytics” and “organon” and “dialectic”, while inversely the name “logic” has at different times been applied much more broadly and loosely than it will be here. At certain times and in certain places — perhaps especially in Germany from the days of Kant through the days of Hegel — the label has come to be used so very broadly and loosely as to threaten to take in nearly the whole of metaphysics and epistemology. Logic in our sense has often been distinguished from “logic” in other, sometimes unmanageably broad and loose, senses by adding the adjectives “formal” or “deductive”. The scope of the art and science of logic, once one gets beyond elementary logic of the kind covered in introductory textbooks, is indicated by two other standard references, the Handbooks of mathematical and philosophical logic, Barwise [1977] and Gabbay & Guenthner [1983-89], though the latter includes also parts that are identified as applications of logic rather than logic proper. The term “philosophical logic” as currently used, for instance, in the Journal of Philosophical Logic, is a near-synonym for “nonclassical logic”. There is an older use of the term as a near-synonym for “philosophy of language”. -
Arguing Or Reasoning? Argumentation in Rhetorical Context
University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 10 May 22nd, 9:00 AM - May 25th, 5:00 PM Arguing or reasoning? Argumentation in rhetorical context Manfred Kraus University of Tübingen, Philologisches Seminar Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive Part of the Philosophy Commons Kraus, Manfred, "Arguing or reasoning? Argumentation in rhetorical context" (2013). OSSA Conference Archive. 97. https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/OSSA10/papersandcommentaries/97 This Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences and Conference Proceedings at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in OSSA Conference Archive by an authorized conference organizer of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Arguing or reasoning? Argumentation in rhetorical context MANFRED KRAUS Philologisches Seminar University of Tübingen Wilhelmstraße 36 72074 Tübingen Germany [email protected] ABSTRACT: If dialogue is a necessary condition for argument, argumentation in oratory becomes questionable, since rhetoric is not a dialogically structured activity. If special norms apply to the ‘solo’ performances of rhetoric, the orator’s activity may be more appropriately described as reasoning than as arguing. By analyzing in what respect rhetorical texts can be interpreted as dialogue-based and subject to criteria of Informal Logic, the virtues of rhetorical argumentation in contrast to logic and dialectic emerge. KEYWORDS: acceptability, audience, dialectic, dialogue, oratory, reasoning, relevance, rhetoric, solo performance, sufficiency 1. INTRODUCTION Alongside the two main schools of pragma-dialectics and informal logic, in recent years rhetoric has established itself as an independent third approach to argumentation theory. -
John Hayden Woods, FRSC Curriculum Vitae
John Hayden Woods, FRSC Curriculum Vitae Personal Information Date of Birth: March 16, 1937 Place of Birth: Barrie, Ontario Citizenship: Canadian Degrees B.A. Hon. Philosophy University of Toronto 1958 M.A. Philosophy University of Toronto 1959 Ph.D. Philosophy University of Michigan 1965 LL.D. (Honoris Causa) Mount Allison University 1997 D. A. (Honoris Causa) University of Lethbridge 2003 Doctoral Thesis Entailment and the Paradoxes of Strict Implication, vi, 308, Ann Arbor: University Microfilms, 1965. Current Appointments 1. Director, The Abductive Systems Group, University of British Columbia, 2002 and, since 2010, The UBC Honorary Professor of Logic 2. President Emeritus and Emeritus Professor of Philosophy, University of Lethbridge, 2002. Past Appointments (Regular) 1. University of Toronto, 1962 – 1971 2. University of Victoria, 1971 – 1976 3. University of Calgary, 1976 – 1979 4. University of Lethbridge, 1979 – 2002 5. Charles S. Peirce Professor of Logic, King’s College London, 2000-2012 Past Appointments (Visiting) 1. Visiting Associate Professor, The Summer Institute of Philosophy, University of Calgary, 1965 2. Visiting Associate Professor, University of Michigan, 1967 3. Visiting Professor, Stanford University, 1968-69, 1971, 1994 4. Visiting Professor, Laurentian University, 1969 5. Regular Visiting Professor, Department of Discourse Analysis, University of Amsterdam (third trimester), 6. 1987-2001 7. Visiting Professor, University of Groningen, 1987, 1988 8. Fellow, The Netherlands Institute for Advanced Study, 1990 9. Vonhoff Professor of Humanities, Faculty of Philosophy, University of Groningen, 2001 1 List of Publications BOOKS l969 1. Necessary Truth, edited, vi, 266, New York: Random House, 1969 (with L.W. Sumner). 1974 2. Proof and Truth, xiv, 192, Toronto: Peter Martin Associates, 1974. -
On the Relation of Informal to Formal Logic
University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 2 May 15th, 9:00 AM - May 17th, 5:00 PM On the Relation of Informal to Formal Logic Dale Jacquette The Pensylvania State University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive Part of the Philosophy Commons Jacquette, Dale, "On the Relation of Informal to Formal Logic" (1997). OSSA Conference Archive. 60. https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/OSSA2/papersandcommentaries/60 This Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences and Conference Proceedings at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in OSSA Conference Archive by an authorized conference organizer of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ON THE RELATION OF INFORMAL TO FORMAL LOGIC Dale Jacquette Department of Philosophy The Pennsylvania State University ©1998, Dale Jacquette Abstract: The distinction between formal and informal logic is clarified as a prelude to considering their ideal relation. Aristotle's syllogistic describes forms of valid inference, and is in that sense a formal logic. Yet the square of opposition and rules of middle term distribution of positive or negative propositions in an argument's premises and conclusion are standardly received as devices of so- called informal logic and critical reasoning. I propose a more exact criterion for distinguishing between formal and informal logic, and then defend a model for fruitful interaction between informal and formal methods of investigating and critically assessing the logic of arguments. *** 1. A Strange Dichotomy In the history of logic a division between formal and informal methods has emerged. -
Are Dogs Logical Animals ? Jean-Yves Beziau University of Brazil, Rio De Janeiro (UFRJ) Brazilian Research Council (Cnpq) Brazilian Academy of Philosophy (ABF)
Are Dogs Logical Animals ? Jean-Yves Beziau University of Brazil, Rio de Janeiro (UFRJ) Brazilian Research Council (CNPq) Brazilian Academy of Philosophy (ABF) Autre être fidèle du tonneau sans loques malgré ses apparitions souvent loufoques le chien naît pas con platement idiot ne se laisse pas si facilement mener en rat d’eau il ne les comprend certes pas forcément toutes à la première coupe ne sait pas sans l’ombre deux doutes la fière différance antre un loup et une loupe tout de foi à la croisade des parchemins il saura au non du hasard dès trousser la chienlit et non en vain reconnaître celle qui l’Amen à Rhum sans faim Baron Jean Bon de Chambourcy 1. Human beings and other animals In Ancient Greece human beings have been characterized as logical animals. This traditional catching is a bit lost or/and nebulous. What this precisely means is not necessarily completely clear because the word Logos has four important aspects: language, science, reasoning, relation. The Latinized version of “logical”, i.e. “rational”, does not fully preserve these four meanings. Moreover later on human beings were qualified as “homo sapiens” (see Beziau 2017). In this paper we will try to clarify the meaning of “logical animals” by examining if dogs can also be considered logical animals. An upside question of “Are dogs logical animals?” is: “Are human beings the only rational animals?”. It is one thing to claim that human beings are logical animals, but another thing is to super claim that human beings are the only logical animals. -
Maurice Finocchiaro Discusses the Lessons and the Cultural Repercussions of Galileo’S Telescopic Discoveries.” Physics World, Vol
MAURICE A. FINOCCHIARO: CURRICULUM VITAE CONTENTS: §0. Summary and Highlights; §1. Miscellaneous Details; §2. Teaching Experience; §3. Major Awards and Honors; §4. Publications: Books; §5. Publications: Articles, Chapters, and Discussions; §6. Publications: Book Reviews; §7. Publications: Proceedings, Abstracts, Translations, Reprints, Popular Media, etc.; §8. Major Lectures at Scholarly Meetings: Keynote, Invited, Funded, Honorarium, etc.; §9. Other Lectures at Scholarly Meetings; §10. Public Lectures; §11. Research Activities: Out-of-Town Libraries, Archives, and Universities; §12. Professional Service: Journal Editorial Boards; §13. Professional Service: Refereeing; §14. Professional Service: Miscellaneous; §15. Community Service §0. SUMMARY AND HIGHLIGHTS Address: Department of Philosophy; University of Nevada, Las Vegas; Box 455028; Las Vegas, NV 89154-5028. Education: B.S., 1964, Massachusetts Institute of Technology; Ph.D., 1969, University of California, Berkeley. Position: Distinguished Professor of Philosophy, Emeritus; University of Nevada, Las Vegas. Previous Positions: UNLV: Assistant Professor, 1970-74; Associate Professor, 1974-77; Full Professor, 1977-91; Distinguished Professor, 1991-2003; Department Chair, 1989-2000. Major Awards and Honors: 1976-77 National Science Foundation; one-year grant; project “Galileo and the Art of Reasoning.” 1983-84 National Endowment for the Humanities, one-year Fellowship for College Teachers; project “Gramsci and the History of Dialectical Thought.” 1987 Delivered the Fourth Evert Willem Beth Lecture, sponsored by the Evert Willem Beth Foundation, a committee of the Royal Netherlands Academy of Sciences, at the Universities of Amsterdam and of Groningen. 1991-92 American Council of Learned Societies; one-year fellowship; project “Democratic Elitism in Mosca and Gramsci.” 1992-95 NEH; 3-year grant; project “Galileo on the World Systems.” 1993 State of Nevada, Board of Regents’ Researcher Award. -
A Mistake on My Part, Volume 1, Pp 665-659 in We Will Show Them!
A Mistake on My Part Melvin Fitting 1 The Background I first met Dov at a logic conference in Manchester, in August 1969, though we had begun a mathematical correspondence the previous year. Here are a few photos from the conference. As I recall, Dov planned to get married shortly after the conference. I found a letter in my files mentioning that I sent Dov a copy of the pictures in 1969, so this is for everybody else. Figure 1 shows Dov at Jodrell Bank, the huge radio telescope complex run by the University of Manchester. Figure 1. 2 Melvin Fitting Figure 2 shows, from left to right, Saul Kripke, Dov, Michael Rabin, and someone I can’t identify. Figure 2. Figure 3 shows the following. Back row: David Pincus, Miriam Lucian, Dov, Saul Kripke; front row: George Rousseau, and me. It was also at this conference that a mistake I made got straightened out. I don’t know if it had an effect on Dov’s work, but it may have. But let’s discuss that in a section of its own. 2 Where I Went Wrong Kripke’s semantics for intuitionistic logic came along in [Kripke, 1965], and prompted a considerable amount of research. It was a possible worlds se- mantics, and in it domains for quantifiers varied from world to world, though subject to a monotonicity condition. It was a natural question: what would a restriction to constant domain intuitionistic models impose. In my dis- sertation, [Fitting, 1969], I had shown in passing that, for formulas without universal quantifiers, constant domain and monotonic domain semantics validated the same formulas (unlike in classical logic, the two quantifiers are not interdefinable intuitionistically). -
Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Logic
Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Logic: Inductive Logic Volume 10 edited by Dov M. Gabbay, Stephan Hartmann, and John Woods CONTENTS Introduction vii Dov Gabbay, Stephan Hartman and John Woods List of Authors ix Induction before Hume 1 J. R. Milton Hume and the Problem of Induction 43 Marc Lange The Debate between Whewell and Mill on the Nature of 93 Scientific Induction Malcolm Forster An Explorer upon Untrodden Ground: Peirce on Abduction 117 Stathis Psillos The Modern Epistemic Interpretations of Probability: Logicism 153 and Subjectivism Maria Carla Galavotti Popper and Hypothetico-deductivism 205 Alan Musgrave Hempel and the Paradoxes of Confirmation 235 Jan Sprenger Carnap and the Logic of Induction 265 Sandy Zabell The Development of the Hintikka Program 311 Ilkka Niiniluoto Hans Reichenbach’s Probability Logic 357 Frederick Eberhardt and Clark Glymour 4 Goodman and the Demise of Syntactic and Semantics Models 391 Robert Schwartz The Development of Subjective Bayesianism 415 James Joyce Varieties of Bayesianism 477 Jonathan Weisberg Inductive Logic and Empirical Psychology 553 Nick Chater, Mike Oaksford, Ulrike Hahn and Evan Heit Inductive Logic and Statistics 625 Jan-Willem Romeijn Statistical Learning Theory 651 Ulrike von Luxburg and Bernhard Schoelkopf Formal Learning Theory in Context 707 Daniel Osherson and Scott Weinstein Mechanizing Induction 719 Ronald Ortner and Hannes Leitgeb Index 773 PREFACE While the more narrow research program of inductive logic is an invention of the 20th century, philosophical reflection about induction as a mode of inference is as old as philosophical reflection about deductive inference. Aristotle was concerned with what he calls epagoge and he studied it, with the same systematic intent with which he approached the logic of syllogisms. -
Informal Logic
Document generated on 09/28/2021 9:04 a.m. Informal Logic A Dialectical View on Conduction: Reasons, Warrants, and Normal Suasory Inclinations Shiyang Yu and Frank Zenker Volume 39, Number 1, 2019 Article abstract When Carl Wellman (1971) introduced the reasoning-type conduction, he URI: https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1060809ar endorsed a dialectical view on natural language argumentation. Contemporary DOI: https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v39i1.5080 scholarship, by contrast, treats conductive argument predominantly on a product view. Not only did Wellman’s reasons for a dialectical view thus fall See table of contents into disregard; a product-treatment of conduction also flouts the standard semantics of ‘argument’. Attempting to resolve these difficulties, our paper traces Wellman’s preference for a dialectical view to the role of defeasible Publisher(s) warrants. These act as stand-ins for (parts of) value hierarchies that arguers of normal suasory inclination find acceptable. We also improve on extant ways of Informal Logic diagramming conduction and distinguish two of its structural variants. ISSN 0824-2577 (print) 2293-734X (digital) Explore this journal Cite this article Yu, S. & Zenker, F. (2019). A Dialectical View on Conduction: Reasons, Warrants, and Normal Suasory Inclinations. Informal Logic, 39(1), 32–69. https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v39i1.5080 Copyright (c), 2019 Shiyang Yu, Frank Zenker This document is protected by copyright law. Use of the services of Érudit (including reproduction) is subject to its terms and conditions, which can be viewed online. https://apropos.erudit.org/en/users/policy-on-use/ This article is disseminated and preserved by Érudit. -
Defense of Fallacy Theory
View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Scholarship at UWindsor University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 11 May 18th, 9:00 AM - May 21st, 5:00 PM A (Modest) Defense of Fallacy Theory Scott F. Aikin Vanderbilt University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive Part of the Philosophy Commons Aikin, Scott F., "A (Modest) Defense of Fallacy Theory" (2016). OSSA Conference Archive. 92. https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/OSSA11/papersandcommentaries/92 This Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences and Conference Proceedings at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in OSSA Conference Archive by an authorized conference organizer of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A Modest Defense of Fallacy Theory SCOTT F. AIKIN Philosophy Vanderbilt University 111 Furman Hall Nashville, TN 37240 USA [email protected] Abstract: Fallacy theory has three significant challenges to it: the generality, scope, and negativity problems. To the generality problem, the connection between general types of bad arguments and tokens is a matter of refining the use of the vocabulary. To the scope problem, the breadth of fallacy’s instances is cause for development. To the negativity problem, fallacy theory must be coordinated with a program of adversariality-management. Keywords: fallacy theory; minimal adversariality 1. Introduction Fallacy theory is the convergence of three broad programs in the study of argument. First is the first-order research program of defining fallacy, taxonomizing and finding new types.