Christian Garve

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Christian Garve HERR PROFESSOR CHRISTIAN GARVE “NARRATIVE HISTORY” AMOUNTS TO FABULATION, THE REAL STUFF BEING MERE CHRONOLOGY “Stack of the Artist of Kouroo” Project Herr Christian Garve HDT WHAT? INDEX HERR PROFESSOR CHRISTIAN GARVE HERR CHRISTIAN GARVE 1742 January 7, Thursday (Old Style): Christian Garve was born into a family of manual workers. He would study at the universities in Frankfurt an der Oder, and in Halle (Saale). NOBODY COULD GUESS WHAT WOULD HAPPEN NEXT Herr Christian Garve “Stack of the Artist of Kouroo” Project HDT WHAT? INDEX HERR CHRISTIAN GARVE HERR PROFESSOR CHRISTIAN GARVE 1766 Christian Garve received the Master’s Degree in Philosophy. LIFE IS LIVED FORWARD BUT UNDERSTOOD BACKWARD? — NO, THAT’S GIVING TOO MUCH TO THE HISTORIAN’S STORIES. LIFE ISN’T TO BE UNDERSTOOD EITHER FORWARD OR BACKWARD. “Stack of the Artist of Kouroo” Project Herr Christian Garve HDT WHAT? INDEX HERR PROFESSOR CHRISTIAN GARVE HERR CHRISTIAN GARVE 1769 Publication at Berlin, as a “Prize Essay” (Preisschrift), of Christian Garve’s OB MAN DIE NATÜRLICHEN NEIGUNGEN VERNICHTEN, ODER WELCHE ERWECKEN KÖNNE, DIE NATUR NICHT ERZEUGT HAT: UND WELCHES MITTEL SEYN, DEN NEIGUNGEN, WENN SIE GUT SIND, KRÄFTE ZU GEBEN, ODER, WENN SIE BÖSE SIND, ZU SCHWÄCHEN. VERSUCH ÜBER DIE VON DER AKADEMIE AUFGEGEBENE FRAGE. DO I HAVE YOUR ATTENTION? GOOD. Herr Christian Garve “Stack of the Artist of Kouroo” Project HDT WHAT? INDEX HERR CHRISTIAN GARVE HERR PROFESSOR CHRISTIAN GARVE 1770 Immanuel Kant became a Professor of Logic and Metaphysics at the University of Berlin. Christian Garve became Extraordinary Professor of Mathematics and Logic at the University of Leipzig. CHANGE IS ETERNITY, STASIS A FIGMENT Herr Christian Garve “Stack of the Artist of Kouroo” Project HDT WHAT? INDEX HERR PROFESSOR CHRISTIAN GARVE HERR CHRISTIAN GARVE 1772 Professor Christian Garve translated Professor Adam Ferguson’s INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY: FOR THE USE OF STUDENTS IN THE COLLEGE OF EDINBURGH (Edinburgh: Printed for A. Kincaid & J. Bell), as GRUNDSÄTZE DER MORALPHILOSOPHIE (Leipzig). He became a bookseller in Breslau. The greatest part of his short life would be spent with his mother, in that area. He would become a member of the Masonic Lodge “Friedrich zum goldenen Zepter” (“Frederick with the Golden Scepter”) in the municipality. He would be composing psychological, moral, and economic texts and reviews for the Neue Bibliothek der schönen Wissenschaften und der freyen Künste (New Library of the Beautiful Sciences and Free Arts). The reputation he would acquire would be that of a “Popularphilosoph” (accessible philosopher) rather than that of a system- builder with a seemingly endless supply of nonce vocabulary, such as for one fine instance Professor Immanuel Kant.1 THE FUTURE IS MOST READILY PREDICTED IN RETROSPECT 1. How insolent it seems of him to have insinuated that any major system-building philosopher ever might agree about anything with any other — that’s so not what system-building philosophy was all about! HDT WHAT? INDEX HERR CHRISTIAN GARVE HERR PROFESSOR CHRISTIAN GARVE 1773 Hannah More became one of the aspiring writers of London. She would become associated with Sir Joshua Reynolds, Dr. Johnson, Edmund Burke, and William Wilberforce. She would engage David Garrick to produce her plays. Professor Christian Garve translated Edmund Burke’s 1759 A PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY INTO THE ORIGIN OF OUR IDEAS OF THE SUBLIME AND BEAUTIFUL WITH SEVERAL OTHER ADDITIONS, as ÜBER DEN URSPRUNG UNSERER BEGRIFFE VOM ERHABENEN UND SCHÖNEN (Riga). The family of Gasparo Grimani was still in London, for they were godparents at an Italian christening. (They seem to have been in Paris as well, for the daughter is said to have been kidnapped there and never found. The wife Antonia Fabbri Grimani is said to have fallen ill shortly after this, and she would die in Paris in about 1776.) THE FUTURE CAN BE EASILY PREDICTED IN RETROSPECT “Stack of the Artist of Kouroo” Project Herr Christian Garve HDT WHAT? INDEX HERR PROFESSOR CHRISTIAN GARVE HERR CHRISTIAN GARVE 1776 Christian Garve translated Alexander Gerard’s 1774 AN ESSAY ON GENIUS (London) as VERSUCH UEBER DAS GENEI (Leipzig: Weidmanns Erben & Reich). HDT WHAT? INDEX HERR CHRISTIAN GARVE HERR PROFESSOR CHRISTIAN GARVE 1782 On account of an anonymous review of the CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON that he had prepared for the Zugabe zu den Gottischen Anzeigen von Gelehrten Sachen, Christian Garve found that he was dragged into an extended argument with Herr Professor Immanuel Kant. He had committed the major sin of interpreting Professor Kant’s position as the same as the one that had been taken by Bishop George Berkeley, which was of course quite preposterous — Professor Kant the system-builder was not the fellow to merely repeat somebody else’s ideas! However, what Professor Garve had prepared had been shortened by about two-thirds prior to the publication of this, and had then been considerably augmented by the Göttingen philosopher Johann Georg Heinrich Feder, and in consequence his controversial review would need to be republished in the Allgemeine deutsche Bibliothek, this time in full and without those supplemental materials that had actually been supplied by Feder. Professor Kant would be, however, still so much displeased, as to author an Anti- Garve response — which response would then after a time be expanded by Kant until eventually it would become his renowned PROLEGOMENA TO ANY FUTURE METAPHYSICS THAT WILL BE ABLE TO PRESENT ITSELF AS A SCIENCE (1783). WHAT I’M WRITING IS TRUE BUT NEVER MIND YOU CAN ALWAYS LIE TO YOURSELF Herr Christian Garve “Stack of the Artist of Kouroo” Project HDT WHAT? INDEX HERR PROFESSOR CHRISTIAN GARVE HERR CHRISTIAN GARVE 1783 Herr Professor Immanuel Kant’s PROLEGOMENA TO ANY FUTURE METAPHYSICS THAT WILL BE ABLE TO PRESENT ITSELF AS A SCIENCE. July 13, Sunday: Christian Garve identified himself to Herr Professor Immanuel Kant as the author of the anonymous 1782 review of the CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON to which Professor Kant had objected, the guy who had opinioned that Kant’s idea was merely Bishop George Berkeley’s idea warmed over. He attempted to explain that two-thirds of what he had prepared had been deleted by the editor, and that about a third of the material actually published had been created not by him but instead by a third party, Johann Georg Heinrich Feder. He conceded to the aggrieved system-builder, nevertheless, that “I bear some responsibility for it.” HDT WHAT? INDEX HERR CHRISTIAN GARVE HERR PROFESSOR CHRISTIAN GARVE 1784 Herr Professor Immanuel Kant’s essay “An Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?” At the request of Frederick the Great, Christian Garve translated Cicero’s DE OFFICIIS (ON THE DUTIES OF LIFE, three volumes; the king would in consequence bestow upon Garve a pension of $200). HDT WHAT? INDEX HERR PROFESSOR CHRISTIAN GARVE HERR CHRISTIAN GARVE 1786 Christian Garve published a treatise on the Character of the Peasantry. HDT WHAT? INDEX HERR CHRISTIAN GARVE HERR PROFESSOR CHRISTIAN GARVE 1788 Christian Garve published a treatise on the relationship between Morality and Politics. HDT WHAT? INDEX HERR PROFESSOR CHRISTIAN GARVE HERR CHRISTIAN GARVE 1792 Volume I of Christian Garve’s collection of essays VERSUCHE ÜBER VERSCHIEDENE GEGENSTÄNDE AUS DER MORAL, DER LITTERATUR UND DEM GESELLSCHAFTLICHEN LEBEN (Breslau) (ESSAYS CONCERNING A NUMBER OF OBJECTS IN MORALITY, LITERATURE AND SOCIAL LIFE). HDT WHAT? INDEX HERR CHRISTIAN GARVE HERR PROFESSOR CHRISTIAN GARVE 1793 Christian Garve’s DISCOURS SUR L'UTILITÉ DES ACADÉMIES (Berlin). HDT WHAT? INDEX HERR PROFESSOR CHRISTIAN GARVE HERR CHRISTIAN GARVE 1794 Christian Garve’s translation into German of Professor Adam Smith’s 1776 AN INQUIRY INTO THE NATURE AND CAUSES OF THE WEALTH OF NATIONS (its four volumes would be complete by 1796). From this year until 1800, Jean-Baptiste Say would be editing La Decade philosophique, litteraire, et politique, a periodical favoring the doctrines of Professor Smith. WALDEN: If I wished a boy to know something about the arts and PEOPLE OF sciences, for instance, I would not pursue the common course, WALDEN which is merely to send him into the neighborhood of some professor, where any thing is professed and practised but the art of life; –to survey the world through a telescope or a microscope, and never with his natural eye; to study chemistry, and not learn how his bread is made, or mechanics, and not learn how it is earned; to discover new satellites to Neptune, and not detect the motes in his eyes, or to what vagabond he is a satellite himself; or to be devoured by the monsters that swarm all around him, while contemplating the monsters in a drop of vinegar. Which would have advanced the most at the end of a month, –the boy who had made his own jack-knife from the ore which he had dug and smelted, reading as much as would be necessary for this, –or the boy who had attended the lectures on metallurgy at the Institute in the mean while, and had received a Rodgers’ penknife from his father? Which would be most likely to cut his fingers? –To my astonishment I was informed on leaving college that I had studied navigation! –why, if I had taken one turn down the harbor I should have known more about it. Even the poor student studies and is taught only political economy, while that economy of living which is synonymous with philosophy is not even sincerely professed in our colleges. The consequence is, that while he is reading Adam Smith, Ricardo, and Say, he runs his father in debt irretrievably. ADAM SMITH DAVID RICARDO JEAN-BAPTISTE SAY HDT WHAT? INDEX HERR CHRISTIAN GARVE HERR PROFESSOR CHRISTIAN GARVE 1796 Volum e II o f Christian Garve’s collection of essays VERSUCHE ÜBER VERSCHIEDENE GEGENSTÄNDE AUS DER MORAL, DER LITTERATUR UND DEM GESELLSCHAFTLICHEN LEBEN (Breslau) (ESSAYS CONCERNING A NUMBER OF OBJECTS IN MORALITY, LITERATURE AND SOCIAL LIFE).
Recommended publications
  • 'The Supreme Principle of Morality'? in the Preface to His Best
    The Supreme Principle of Morality Allen W. Wood 1. What is ‘The Supreme Principle of Morality’? In the Preface to his best known work on moral philosophy, Kant states his purpose very clearly and succinctly: “The present groundwork is, however, nothing more than the search for and establishment of the supreme principle of morality, which already constitutes an enterprise whole in its aim and to be separated from every other moral investigation” (Groundwork 4:392). This paper will deal with the outcome of the first part of this task, namely, Kant’s attempt to formulate the supreme principle of morality, which is the intended outcome of the search. It will consider this formulation in light of Kant’s conception of the historical antecedents of his attempt. Our first task, however, must be to say a little about the meaning of the term ‘supreme principle of morality’. For it is not nearly as evident to many as it was to Kant that there is such a thing at all. And it is extremely common for people, whatever position they may take on this issue, to misunderstand what a ‘supreme principle of morality’ is, what it is for, and what role it is supposed to play in moral theorizing and moral reasoning. Kant never directly presents any argument that there must be such a principle, but he does articulate several considerations that would seem to justify supposing that there is. Kant holds that moral questions are to be decided by reason. Reason, according to Kant, always seeks unity under principles, and ultimately, systematic unity under the fewest possible number of principles (Pure Reason A298-302/B355-359, A645- 650/B673-678).
    [Show full text]
  • Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics CAMBRIDGE TEXTS in the HISTORY of PHILOSOPHY
    CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY IMMANUEL KANT Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY Series editors KARL AMERIKS Professor of Philosophy at the University of Notre Dame DESMOND M. CLARKE Professor of Philosophy at University College Cork The main objective of Cambridge Textsin the History of Philosophy is to expand the range, variety and quality of texts in the history of philosophy which are available in English. The series includes texts by familiar names (such as Descartes and Kant) and also by less well-known authors. Wherever possible, texts are published in complete and unabridged form, and translations are specially commissioned for the series. Each volume contains a critical introduction together with a guide to further reading and any necessary glossaries and textual apparatus. The volumes are designed for student use at undergraduate and postgraduate level and will be of interest not only to students of philosophy, but also to a wider audience of readers in the history of science, the history of theology and the history of ideas. For a list of titles published in the series, please see end of book. IMMANUEL KANT Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics That Will Be Able to Come Forward as Science with Selections from the Critique of Pure Reason TRANSLATED AND EDITED BY GARY HATFIELD University of Pennsylvania Revised Edition cambridge university press Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb2 2ru, UK Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521828246 © Cambridge University Press 1997, 2004 This publication is in copyright.
    [Show full text]
  • German Editions of Adam Smith's Wealth of Nations
    GERMAN EDITIONS OF ADAM SMITH’S WEALTH OF NATIONS HARALD HAGEMANN UNIVERSITÄT HOHENHEIM STUTTGART, GERMANY [email protected] The first German edition of Adam Smith’s Wealth of Nations was already published as early as 1776-78 in two volumes. The editor and translator of this edition, which was entitled Untersuchungen der Natur und Ursachen von Nationalreichthümern, was Johann Friedrich Schiller (1737-1814), a cousin of the famous poet Friedrich Schiller. However, the quality of the translation was heavily criticized, and until the early 1790s Smith’s Wealth of Nations, which was largely ignored by the cameralists, had only little impact on German economic discourse. Due to the effects of the French Revolution and a new and better German translation by Christian Garve, entitled as Untersuchung über die Natur und die Ursachen des Nationalreichthums and published in two volumes in 1794-96, the Smithian doctrines were now perceived and discussed on a much broader scale. A particular role was played in this process by the two universities of Göttingen and Königsberg (see Winkel 1986). Georg Sartorius (1765-1828) taught Smithian ideas from 1792 onwards. He wrote a long review essay of the new German edition of the Wealth of Nations whose essential ideas entered into his own textbook (Sartorius 1806). As the University in the Kingdom of Hanover, Göttingen had a high number of British students, including princes, for which special lectures had to be given. However, among the students were also many Germans who later became liberal reformers or well-known economists such as Johann Heinrich von Thünen (1783- 1850) who studied with Sartorius in 1803-04.
    [Show full text]
  • Leonie Koch- Schwarzer Christian Garve: Buchmarktorientierung Und Selbstverständnis Als Autor
    Leonie Koch- Christian Garve: Schwarzer Buchmarktorientierung und Selbstverständnis als Autor* In der zweiten Hälfte des 18. Jahrhunderts versuchten deutschsprachige Autoren erstmals frei und selbstständig nur von ihrer schriftstellerischen Tätigkeit und den daraus resultierenden Verdiensten zu leben. Aus welchen Gründen heraus und mit welchem Selbstverständnis taten sie dies? Welche ökonomischen Voraussetzungen fanden diese sogenannten freien Schrift- steller in der literarischen Szene und vor allem am Buchmarkt? Und wie genau definierten sie dabei ihren Begriff vom »Schriftstellersein« und ihre konkreten Aufgaben gegenüber dem Publikum? Die folgenden Ausführungen wollen diese Fragen am Beispiel des Essay- isten und Popularphilosophen Christian Garve (1742-1798) verfolgen. Für die Zeitgenossen waren vor allem in den 1760er und 1770er Jahren Leipzi- ger und Berliner Autoren wie Christian Garve oder Moses Mendelssohn, Georg Forster oder Friedrich Nicolai, Johann Jacob Engel oder Johann Erich Biester, sowohl philosophische wie auch schriftstellerische Vorbilder. Ihre Philosophierichtung und ihre Schreibart --- kondensiert in Zeitschriften wie dem »Philosoph für die Welt« --- wurden als Popularphilosophie be- zeichnet, d. h. in essayistisch-reflektierender Schreibweise nahmen diese Autoren ihre Themen direkt aus der konkreten Lebenswelt und deren Problemlagen auf, um sie dann mit Blick auf ein interessiertes Publikum in einer klaren, verständlichen (»popularen«) sowie präzisen Sprache darzustel- len und kritisch zu analysieren. Ziel und »Nutzen« dieser Schriften war, ei- ne sich im Prozess der fortschreitenden Vervollkommnung befindende Ge- sellschaft in diesem Prozess der moralischen Verbesserung, der geistigen Bildung und ökonomischem Fortschritt zu unterstützen und zu beför- dern.271 Typisch für diese Schriftsteller waren hierbei die »kleine Formen« des Schreibens: Essays, Aufsätze, Rezensionen, Kommentare in Zeitschriften * Meiner Mutter zum 81.
    [Show full text]
  • Experiencing Music in the North German Enlightenment
    SENSITIVITY, INSPIRATION, AND RATIONAL AESTHETICS: EXPERIENCING MUSIC IN THE NORTH GERMAN ENLIGHTENMENT Kimary E. Fick, B.M., M.M. Dissertation Prepared for the Degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY University of North Texas December 2015 APPROVED: Hendrik Schulze, Major Professor Peter Mondelli, Committee Member Christoph Weber, Committee Member Paul Leenhouts, Related Field Committee Member and Director of Early Music Studies Benjamin Brand, Director of Graduate Studies, College of Music James Scott, Dean of College of Music Costas Tsatsoulis, Dean of Toulouse Graduate School Fick, Kimary E. Sensitivity, Inspiration, and Rational Aesthetics: Experiencing Music in the North German Enlightenment. Doctor of Philosophy (Musicology), December 2015, 295 pp., 2 tables, 3 figures, 19 musical examples, references, 166 titles. This dissertation examines pre-Kantian rational philosophy and the development of the discipline of aesthetics in the North German Enlightenment. With emphasis on the historical conception of the physiological and psychological experience of music, this project determines the function of music both privately and socially in the eighteenth century. As a result, I identify the era of rational aesthetics (ca.1750-1800) as a music-historical period unified by the aesthetic function and metaphysical experience of music, which inform the underlying motivation for musical styles, genres, and means of expression, leading to a more meaningful and compelling historical periodization. The philosophy of Alexander Baumgarten, Johann Georg Sulzer, and others enable definitions of the experience of beautiful objects and those concepts related to music composition, listening, and taste, and determine how rational aesthetics impacted the practice, function, and ultimately the prevailing style of music in the era.
    [Show full text]
  • Stoic Ethics in Kant's Religion
    A version of this paper is forthcoming in the European Journal of Philosophy; please cite the published version. Nature, Corruption, and Freedom: Stoic Ethics in Kant’s Religion Melissa Merritt, University of New South Wales 1. Introduction This paper is an invitation to take seriously Kant’s debt to Stoic ethics and moral psychology. Scholars have given some attention to this connection, though often in the form of drive-by remarks, where, often for perfectly good reasons, the matter cannot be fully taken up.1 When it is taken up, scholarly caution sometimes recommends a deflationary verdict, citing either uncertainty about Kant’s access to Stoic texts, or systematic differences. 2 But there is no great mystery about Kant’s access to Stoicism, which comes primarily through Seneca and Cicero, as it has for most philosophers since the Renaissance. And while there are genuine systematic differences — Kant, for example, is not a eudaimonist3 — I would argue that his moral psychology, in particular, has clear and profound Stoic roots. Of course, a full argument for the influence of Stoicism on Kant’s ethics and moral psychology is a bigger project than can be undertaken here: my present aim is to make a case for Kant’s debt to the Stoics on one topic, in one work. Kant’s account of “the radical evil in human nature” in Part 1 of Religion within the Bounds of Reason Alone is typically interpreted as a reworking of the Augustinian doctrine of original sin, in a manner intended to establish its compatibility with Enlightenment morality.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy and German Literature –
    PHILOSOPHY AND GERMAN LITERATURE – EDITED BY NICHOLAS SAUL University of Liverpool PUBLISHED BY THE PRESS SYNDICATE OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CBRU,UK West th Street, New York, NY -, USA Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC , Australia Ruiz de Alarc´on , Madrid, Spain Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town , South Africa http://www.cambridge.org C Cambridge University Press This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions ofrelevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction ofany part may take place without the written permission ofCambridge University Press. First published Printed in the United Kingdom at the University Press, Cambridge Typeface Baskerville Monotype /. pt. System LATEX ε [TB] A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloguing in Publication data Philosophy and German literature – / edited by Nicholas Saul. p. cm. – (Cambridge studies in German) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN --- . German literature – History and criticism. Literature and philosophy. Philosophy, German. I. Saul, Nicholas. II. Series. PT .M . –dc ISBN hardback Contents Contributors page viii Acknowledgements x List of abbreviations xi Introduction: German literature and philosophy Nicholas Saul Criticism and experience: philosophy and literature in the German Enlightenment John A.McCarthy The pursuit ofthe subject: literature as critic and perfecter ofphilosophy – Nicholas Saul Two realisms: German literature and philosophy – John Walker Modernism and the self – Ritchie Robertson The subjects ofcommunity: aspiration, memory,resistance – Russell A.Berman Coming to terms with the past in postwar literature and philosophy Robert C.Holub Bibliography Index vii CHAPTER ONE Criticism and experience: philosophy and literature in the German Enlightenment John A.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of History of Adam Ferguson and Immanuel Kant Artigos / Articles
    Philosophy of History of Adam Ferguson and Immanuel Kant Artigos / Articles PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY OF ADAM FERGUSON AND IMMANUEL KANT Sandra ZÁKUTNÁ1 Kant’s philosophy of history concentrated in his short political writings is an important part of his philosophical legacy. His approach to political themes was influenced not only by political situation and events of his present, e.g. American or French Revolution, but also by other philosophers of his era. Well-known is his philosophical dialogue with Jean Jacques Rousseau who influenced him in answering his fourth question “What is man?”. Another important source of ideas which shaped Kant’s position in the matter of philosophy of history were definitively Scottish philosophers, especially David Hume, Adam Smith and Adam Ferguson. According to Norbert Waszek the major continental impact of Scottish Enlightenment thought was in German-speaking countries (2006, p. 55). In the article The Scottish Enlightenment in Germany and its Translator, Christian Garve (1742-98) Waszek provides interesting information about the facts how books of Scottish authors, and translations of these books, formed Kant, Lessing, Schiller, or Hegel. He also quotes Goethe to illustrate the influence of Scottish thought on Germany: “We Germans who aspire to the most universal culture have for many years been aware of the merits of the respectable Scots” (Goethe in Waszek 2006, p. 55). 2 In this article I will try to focus on the issue of progress in history represented by formation and development of civil society, the role of people and people as citizens in it, the question of conflict as the main driving impulse, and the portrayal of possible future in the works of Adam Ferguson and Immanuel Kant.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant on Moral Satisfaction
    Kantian Review, 22, 2, 281–303 © Kantian Review, 2017 doi:10.1017/S136941541700005X Kant on Moral Satisfaction michael walschots University of St. Andrews Email: [email protected] Abstract This paper gives an account of Kant’s concept of self-contentment (Selbstzufriedenheit), i.e. the satisfaction involved in the performance of moral action. This concept is vulnerable to an important objection: if moral action is satisfying, it might only ever be performed for the sake of this satisfaction. I explain Kant’s response to this objection and argue that it is superior to Francis Hutcheson’s response to a similar objection. I conclude by showing that two other notions of moral satisfaction in Kant’s moral philosophy, namely ‘sweet merit’ and the highest good, also avoid the objection. Keywords: self-contentment, Garve, Hutcheson, eudaimonism, pleasure, happiness, moral motivation 1. Introduction Almost since its inception, Kant’s moral philosophy has been thought by many to imply that action from duty cannot be pleasing in any way. Perhaps the most well known but also the most extreme version of this kind of 1 response is suggested by Friedrich Schiller’sfamousremark that, on Kant’s account, one can only be certain that one has acted virtuously if one does what duty commands ‘with disgust’ (see Schiller 1987: 299–300, translation from Timmermann 2007: 152). On this reading, acting from duty involves or even requires that one dislike performing one’s duty, but similar and more moderate readings at the very least suggest that there is nothing pleasing about doing one’s duty. This is an important challenge to Kant’smoral 2 philosophy and is one which is still very much under discussion, for if Kant truly does suggest that acting morally is divorced from satisfaction entirely, then perhaps his is a moral theory unsuitable to human beings.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Kant's Moderate Cynicism and the Harmony Between Virtue and Worldly Happiness David Forman the University of Nevada, Las
    Kant’s Moderate Cynicism and the Harmony between Virtue and Worldly Happiness David Forman The University of Nevada, Las Vegas An edited version will appear in The Journal of the History of Philosophy ABSTRACT: For Kant, any authentic moral demands are wholly distinct from the demands of prudence. This has led critics to complain that Kantian moral demands are incompatible with our human nature as happiness-seekers. To address this worry, Kant would need to show us that aiming at morality does not require us to abandon our hope for happiness in this life. This paper argues that Kant—building on insights from Rousseau that Kant identifies with Cynicism— offers an account of a harmony between virtue and worldly happiness that can sustain such a hope. 1. Happiness in Kant’s Pure Moral Philosophy One of the central tenets of Kant’s practical philosophy is that the demands of morality are wholly distinct from and not at all subservient to the demands of self-interest or happiness. This tenet is already implicit in the famous opening claim of Part One of the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals that only the “good will” could be good without qualification (GMS 4:393).1 Happiness is not owed the same respect as morality because it is “an effect and not an activity of the will” (4:400). This fundamental difference between happiness and morality is revealed in the way each engages our practical reason: prudential demands are expressed in hypothetical imperatives instructing us merely to take the means to a given end, whereas the demands of morality are expressed in a categorical imperative concerned solely with “the form and principle” of the action rather than its expected result (GMS 4:415–16).
    [Show full text]
  • Scottish Political Ideas in Eighteenth Century Germany: the Case of Adam Ferguson
    Scottish Political Ideas in Eighteenth Century Germany: The Case of Adam Ferguson By Fania Oz-Salzberger Thesis submitted for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy at the University of Oxford Wolfson College Trinity Term, 1991 For Eli Abstract Fania Oz-Saizberger Submitted for the Wolf son College degree of D.Phil. Oxford Trinity Term, 1991 Scottish Political Ideas in Eighteenth Century Germany: The Case of Adam Ferguson This thesis examines the reception of the works of Adam Ferguson, a major thinker of the Scottish Enlightenment, by a range of German readers in the late eighteenth century. It provides a survey of Ferguson's main political ideas, and argues that many of his prominent German readers did not come to terms with them. The thesis contrasts the political realities and concerns of Ferguson's Scotland with the profoundly different political concerns of his German readers, and their often vague and inaccurate ideas of Scotland, and of the British constitution. Their documented responses to Ferguson's works are brought as evidence for a cumulative and complex case of misreception. The terms in which Ferguson expressed his political ideas can be fruitfully analyzed as a political language, a vocabulary of recognizable and mutually complementing political terms. After a close examination of this particular vocabulary, the thesis proceeds to show in detail how Ferguson's German translators, commentators, reviewers and readers unwittingly dismantled this vocabulary, lost or ignored its republican and activist elements, and sometimes shifted it into other vocabularies which were far removed from the author's political intentions. However, the differences between the individual readers are emphasized, not only with respect to their varied intellectual backgrounds and works, but also touching on their personal profiles as readers and thinkers.
    [Show full text]
  • Adam Smith in Immanuel Kant's Moral Philosophy
    Adam Smith in Immanuel Kant’s Moral Philosophy Guy Richardson Thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Politics and International Studies The University of Adelaide August 2017 Contents Contents ................................................................................................................... ii Abstract .................................................................................................................... v Declaration .............................................................................................................. vi Note on Sources ..................................................................................................... vii Acknowledgements .................................................................................................. x Introduction .............................................................................................................. 1 PART 1 – BACKGROUND TO THE KANT-SMITH RELATIONSHIP ....... 7 Chapter 1: The Apparently Strange Relationship between Immanuel Kant and Adam Smith ............................................................................................................. 8 Kant’s References to The Wealth of Nations ........................................................ 13 Kant’s References to The Theory of Moral Sentiments ........................................ 19 Conclusion ............................................................................................................. 24 Chapter 2: Smith’s
    [Show full text]