Sequentially Rationalizable Choice

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Sequentially Rationalizable Choice Sequentially Rationalizable Choice By Paola Manzini and Marco Mariotti* A sequentially rationalizable choice function is a choice function that can be retrieved by applying sequentially to each choice problem the same fixed set of asymmetric binary relations (rationales) to remove inferior alternatives. These con- cepts translate into economic language some human choice heuristics studied in psychology and explain cyclical patterns of choice observed in experiments. We study some properties of sequential rationalizability and provide a full character- ization of choice functions rationalizable by two and three rationales. (JEL D0). Cyclical choice is persistently observed in a maximizer for it. In this paper, we propose experimental evidence. It typically occurs and study a family of boundedly rational choice in simple decision problems (involving only procedures that can account for these observed binary comparisons and few alternatives) and anomalies. in significant proportions, sometimes nearing In line with some prominent psychology and or even exceeding 50 percent. This is obviously marketing studies (see below), in our model we incompatible with the classical model of ratio­ assume that the decision maker uses sequen­ nal choice, in which choice is constructed as the tially two rationales to discriminate among maximizer of a single preference relation (which the available alternatives. These rationales are we call a rationale), or of a utility function. If applied in a fixed order, independently of the a decision maker exhibits cycles of choice over choice set, to remove inferior alternatives. This some set of alternatives, for any candidate procedure “sequentially rationalizes” a choice “best” alternative there is always another one in function if, for any feasible set, the process the set that is judged better still: it is not possible identifies the unique alternative specified by to express a decision maker’s preferences by a the choice function. In this case, we say that a utility function, since it is not possible to find choice function is a Rational Shortlist Method (RSM). Intuitively, the first rationale identifies * Manzini: Department of Economics, Queen Mary, Uni­ a shortlist of candidate alternatives from which versity of London, Mile End Road, London E 4NS, United the second rationale selects. The special case in Kingdom (e­mail: [email protected]); Mariotti: Depart­ ment of Economics, Queen Mary, University of London, Mile End Road, London E 4NS, United Kingdom (e­mail: [email protected]). This paper was previously cir­ (2000) find that the majority (52 percent) of choices exhib­ culated under the title “Rationalizing Boundedly Rational ited binary cycles in a universal choice set of four alterna­ Choice: Sequential Rationalizability and Rational Shortlist tives. In the experiment carried out in Loomes, Starmer, Methods.” Most of this work was carried out while we were and Sugden (99), between 4 percent and 29 percent of visiting Bocconi University in Milan. Their generous hos­ choices made by all subjects were cyclical, and a staggering pitality and financial support through fellowships are grate­ 64 percent of subjects exhibited at least one binary cycle in fully acknowledged. We thank the editor, two anonymous a universal choice set of just three alternatives. More recent referees, Geir Asheim, Sophie Bade, Walter Bossert, Robin results in this same line are in Pavlo Blavatskyy (2003), Cubitt, Eddie Dekel, Marc Fleurbay, Ozgur Kibris, Michele who finds that 55 percent of his experimental subjects Lombardi, Vincenzo Manzini, Efe Ok, Ariel Rubinstein, violate transitivity of choice. Humans seem to fare better Alejandro Saporiti, Rani Spiegler, Yves Sprumont, Bob than nonhuman animals: for instance, in an experiment of Sugden, Koichi Tadenuma, and seminar participants at choice behavior of gray jays, Thomas A. Waite (200) finds FUR XII, LSE, McGill University, and the Universities that all the birds preferred choices a to b and b to c, but none of Oslo, Osnabrueck, Pais Vasco in Bilbao, Sevilla, and preferred a over c, where all alternatives 1n, l2 consisted in Trento for useful comments. The responsibility for any going and getting n raisins at the end of a lcm long tube, error is our own. with a 5 1 raisin, 28 cm2, b 5 12 raisins, 42 cm2, and See, e.g., Amos Tversky (969), Graham Loomes, c 5 13 raisins, 56 cm2. Thus, none of the birds exhibited Chris Starmer, and Robert Sugden (99), and Peter H. M. transitive choice; moreover, 25 percent of them exhibited P. Roelofsma and Daniel Read (2000). Roelofsma and Read consistently intransitive choice. 1824 VOL. 97 NO. 5 ManZINI anD MarIottI: SEQUentIallY RatIonalIZable CHOIce 1825 which the first rationale always yields a unique by c using the Pareto criterion, and, second, c maximal element corresponds to the standard is eliminated by b using the fairness criterion. model of rationality. On the other hand, g 15a, b62 5 a, given that the A notable aspect of these procedures is that Pareto criterion has no bite, and the arbitrator they are testable based on a “revealed prefer­ would select on the basis of fairness. Similarly, ence” type of analysis that, despite the highly g 15b, c62 5 b, whereas g 15a, c62 5 c by Pareto. nonstandard choices to be explained, is not more This seems an entirely reasonable way for the demanding than the standard one.2 In other arbitrator to come to a decision. In fact, this pro­ words, we ask the following question: when are cedure has been proposed in a social choice set­ observed choices compatible with the use of ting by Koichi Tadenuma (2002). Yet it produces our boundedly rational choice procedure? The a violation of WARP and pairwise cyclical pat­ answer is: if and only if the choice data satisfy tern of choice. two testable conditions. Of these conditions, one One can think of a wide array of other practi­ is a standard Expansion axiom, and the other is cal situations where RSMs may apply. A cau­ a modification of Samuelson’s Weak Axiom of tious investor comparing alternative portfolios Revealed Preference (WARP).3 The simplicity first eliminates those that are too risky relative of our tests stands in contrast to the indirect esti­ to others available, and then ranks the surviving mation algorithms normally used (notably in the ones on the basis of expected returns. A recruit­ marketing literature) to infer boundedly rational ing selector first excludes candidates with lower procedures.4 levels of some desired skills than other appli­ Typically, RSMs will lack standard menu­inde­ cants he is considering, and then selects based pendence properties, so that it may be possible on merit from the remaining ones. The notion of for an alternative to be revealed as preferable to RSM is relevant also in other fields in the social another alternative in some choice set, but for that sciences. For instance, psychologists have often preference to be reversed in a different choice set insisted on sequential “noncompensatory”5 heu­ (thus violating WARP). Because of this feature, ristics, as opposed to one single rationale, to RSMs can exhibit cyclical patterns of choice; explain choices (though axiomatic character­ however, they still rule out other types of irratio­ izations of such boundedly rational procedures nal choice. In this sense, an RSM is a nonvacuous are lacking). Notable in this respect are the notion and this gives it empirical content: it can “Elimination by Aspects” procedure of Tversky be tested by observable choice data. (972) and the idea of “fast and frugal heuris­ For a simple example of how an RSM works, tics” of Gerd Gigerenzer, Peter M. Todd, and suppose that an arbitrator has to pick one from the ABC Research Group (999). Similarly, this the available allocations a, b, or c. Suppose that type of model is widely used and documented c Pareto dominates a, while no other Pareto in the management/marketing literature. Yee et comparisons are possible. Assume further that al. (forthcoming) provide recent and compelling the arbitrator deems a fairer than b and b fairer evidence of the use by consumers of “two­stage than c. The arbitrator decides first on the basis consideration and choice” decision­making pro­ of the Pareto criterion, invoking the fairness cri­ cedures, and also refer to firms taking account terion only when Pareto is not decisive. Then, of this fact in product development. the arbitrator’s choice function g would be such In summary, RSMs are simple boundedly that g 15a, b, c62 5 b, since, first,a is eliminated rational procedures that are introspectively plausible and can explain empirically rel­ evant “anomalies” of choice patterns. Above 2 See Hal R. Varian (2005) for a recent survey on stan­ all, whether the choice pattern of a decision dard revealed preference theory. 3 Recall that WARP, in its general form, states that if maker can be explained by an RSM is a testable an alternative a is chosen from some menu of alternatives hypothesis. Last but not least, RSMs provide where some other alternative b is present (i.e., a is directly rigorous formal underpinnings to the heuristics revealed preferred to b), then it can never be the case that alternative b is selected from any other menu including both a and b. 4 For recent examples, see, e.g., Michael Yee et al. (forth­ 5 That is, in which the several “criteria” used for choice coming) and Rajeev Kohli (forthcoming). cannot be traded off against each other. 1826 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW DecEMBER 2007 approach central to much psychology and mar­ outcome of maximizing behavior. Formally, a keting literature. choice function g is rationalizable if there exists In addition to providing a characterization of an acyclic binary relation P, such that RSMs, we consider a natural extension whereby the decision maker applies sequentially more 5g 1S26 5 max 1S; P2 for all S [ P 1X2.
Recommended publications
  • Stability and Median Rationalizability for Aggregate Matchings
    games Article Stability and Median Rationalizability for Aggregate Matchings Federico Echenique 1, SangMok Lee 2, Matthew Shum 1 and M. Bumin Yenmez 3,* 1 Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences, California Institute of Technology, Pasadena, CA 91125, USA; [email protected] (F.E.); [email protected] (M.S.) 2 Department of Economics, Washington University in St. Louis, St. Louis, MO 63130, USA; [email protected] 3 Department of Economics, Boston College, Chestnut Hill, MA 02467, USA * Correspondence: [email protected] Abstract: We develop the theory of stability for aggregate matchings used in empirical studies and establish fundamental properties of stable matchings including the result that the set of stable matchings is a non-empty, complete, and distributive lattice. Aggregate matchings are relevant as matching data in revealed preference theory. We present a result on rationalizing a matching data as the median stable matching. Keywords: aggregate matching; median stable matching; rationalizability; lattice 1. Introduction Following the seminal work of [1], an extensive literature has developed regarding matching markets with non-transferable utility. This literature assumes that there are agent-specific preferences, and studies the existence of stable matchings in which each Citation: Echenique, F.; Lee, S.; agent prefers her assigned partner to the outside option of being unmatched, and there Shum, M.; Yenmez, M.B. Stability and are no pairs of agents that would like to match with each other rather than keeping their Median Rationalizability for assigned partners. Aggregate Matchings. Games 2021, 12, In this paper, we develop the theory of stability for aggregate matchings, which we 33.
    [Show full text]
  • Rationalizable Implementation of Correspondences∗
    Rationalizable Implementation of Correspondences∗ Takashi Kunimotoyand Roberto Serranoz This Version: May 2016 Abstract We come close to characterizing the class of social choice correspon- dences that are implementable in rationalizable strategies. We identify a new condition, which we call set-monotonicity, and show that it is necessary and almost sufficient for rationalizable implementation. Set-monotonicity is much weaker than Maskin monotonicity, which is the key condition for Nash implementation and which also had been shown to be necessary for rationalizable implementation of social choice functions. Set-monotonicity reduces to Maskin monotonicity in the case of functions. We conclude that the conditions for rationalizable implementation are not only starkly differ- ent from, but also much weaker than those for Nash implementation, when we consider social choice correspondences. JEL Classification: C72, D78, D82. Keywords: Complete information, implementation, Maskin monotonicity, rationalizability, set-monotonicity, social choice correspondence. 1 Introduction The design of institutions to be used by rational agents has been an important research agenda in economic theory. As captured by the notion of Nash equilib- rium, rationality is encapsulated in two aspects: these are (i) the best responses of agents to their beliefs, and (ii) that those beliefs are correct, the so-called rational ∗Financial support from the Japan Society for the Promotion of Science (24330078, 25780128) (Kunimoto) is gratefully acknowledged. All remaining errors are our own. ySchool of Economics, Singapore Management University, 90 Stamford Road, Singapore 178903; [email protected] zDepartment of Economics, Brown University, Providence, RI 02912, U.S.A.; roberto [email protected] 1 expectations assumption. One can drop the latter and retain the former, moving then into the realm of rationalizability.
    [Show full text]
  • 4 Social Interactions
    Beta September 2015 version 4 SOCIAL INTERACTIONS Les Joueurs de Carte, Paul Cézanne, 1892-95, Courtauld Institute of Art A COMBINATION OF SELF-INTEREST, A REGARD FOR THE WELLBEING OF OTHERS, AND APPROPRIATE INSTITUTIONS CAN YIELD DESIRABLE SOCIAL OUTCOMES WHEN PEOPLE INTERACT • Game theory is a way of understanding how people interact based on the constraints that limit their actions, their motives and their beliefs about what others will do • Experiments and other evidence show that self-interest, a concern for others and a preference for fairness are all important motives explaining how people interact • In most interactions there is some conflict of interest between people, and also some opportunity for mutual gain • The pursuit of self-interest can lead either to results that are considered good by all participants, or sometimes to outcomes that none of those concerned would prefer • Self-interest can be harnessed for the general good in markets by governments limiting the actions that people are free to take, and by one’s peers imposing punishments on actions that lead to bad outcomes • A concern for others and for fairness allows us to internalise the effects of our actions on others, and so can contribute to good social outcomes See www.core-econ.org for the full interactive version of The Economy by The CORE Project. Guide yourself through key concepts with clickable figures, test your understanding with multiple choice questions, look up key terms in the glossary, read full mathematical derivations in the Leibniz supplements, watch economists explain their work in Economists in Action – and much more.
    [Show full text]
  • Solution Concepts in Cooperative Game Theory
    1 A. Stolwijk Solution Concepts in Cooperative Game Theory Master’s Thesis, defended on October 12, 2010 Thesis Advisor: dr. F.M. Spieksma Mathematisch Instituut, Universiteit Leiden 2 Contents 1 Introduction 7 1.1 BackgroundandAims ................................. 7 1.2 Outline .......................................... 8 2 The Model: Some Basic Concepts 9 2.1 CharacteristicFunction .............................. ... 9 2.2 Solution Space: Transferable and Non-Transferable Utilities . .......... 11 2.3 EquivalencebetweenGames. ... 12 2.4 PropertiesofSolutions............................... ... 14 3 Comparing Imputations 15 3.1 StrongDomination................................... 15 3.1.1 Properties of Strong Domination . 17 3.2 WeakDomination .................................... 19 3.2.1 Properties of Weak Domination . 20 3.3 DualDomination..................................... 22 3.3.1 Properties of Dual Domination . 23 4 The Core 25 4.1 TheCore ......................................... 25 4.2 TheDualCore ...................................... 27 4.2.1 ComparingtheCorewiththeDualCore. 29 4.2.2 Strong ǫ-Core................................... 30 5 Nash Equilibria 33 5.1 Strict Nash Equilibria . 33 5.2 Weak Nash Equilibria . 36 3 4 CONTENTS 6 Stable Sets 39 6.1 DefinitionofStableSets ............................... .. 39 6.2 Stability in A′ ....................................... 40 6.3 ConstructionofStronglyStableSets . ...... 41 6.3.1 Explanation of the Strongly Stable Set: The Standard of Behavior in the 3-personzero-sumgame ............................
    [Show full text]
  • Games in Coalitional Form 1
    GAMES IN COALITIONAL FORM EHUD KALAI Forthcoming in the New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, second edition Abstract. How should a coalition of cooperating players allocate payo¤s to its members? This question arises in a broad range of situations and evokes an equally broad range of issues. For example, it raises technical issues in accounting, if the players are divisions of a corporation, but involves issues of social justice when the context is how people behave in society. Despite the breadth of possible applications, coalitional game theory o¤ers a uni…ed framework and solutions for addressing such questions. This brief survey presents some of its major models and proposed solutions. 1. Introduction In their seminal book, von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944) introduced two theories of games: strategic and coalitional. Strategic game theory concentrates on the selection of strategies by payo¤-maximizing players. Coalitional game theory concentrates on coalition formation and the distribution of payo¤s. The next two examples illustrate situations in the domain of the coalitional approach. 1.1. Games with no strategic structure. Example 1. Cost allocation of a shared facility. Three municipalities, E, W, and S, need to construct water puri…cation facilities. Costs of individual and joint facilities are described by the cost function c: c(E) = 20, c(W ) = 30, and c(S) = 50; c(E; W ) = 40, c(E; S) = 60, and c(W; S) = 80; c(E; W; S) = 80. For example, a facility that serves the needs of W and S would cost $80 million. The optimal solution is to build, at the cost of 80, one facility that serves all three municipalities.
    [Show full text]
  • THE HUMAN SIDE of MECHANISM DESIGN a Tribute to Leo Hurwicz and Jean-Jacque Laffont
    THE HUMAN SIDE OF MECHANISM DESIGN A Tribute to Leo Hurwicz and Jean-Jacque Laffont Daniel McFadden Department of Economics University of California, Berkeley December 4, 2008 [email protected] http://www.econ.berkeley.edu/~mcfadden/index.shtml ABSTRACT This paper considers the human side of mechanism design, the behavior of economic agents in gathering and processing information and responding to incentives. I first give an overview of the subject of mechanism design, and then examine a pervasive premise in this field that economic agents are rational in their information processing and decisions. Examples from applied mechanism design identify the roles of perceptions and inference in agent behavior, and the influence of systematic irrationalities and sociality on agent responses. These examples suggest that tolerance of behavioral faults be added to the criteria for good mechanism design. In principle-agent problems for example, designers should consider using experimental treatments in contracts, and statistical post-processing of agent responses, to identify and mitigate the effects of agent non-compliance with contract incentives. KEYWORDS: mechanism_design, principal-agent_problem, juries, welfare_theory JEL CLASSIFICATION: D000, D600, D610, D710, D800, C420, C700 THE HUMAN SIDE OF MECHANISM DESIGN A Tribute to Leo Hurwicz and Jean-Jacque Laffont Daniel McFadden1 1. Introduction The study of mechanism design, the systematic analysis of resource allocation institutions and processes, has been the most fundamental development
    [Show full text]
  • The Antinomy of Coherence and Determinacy William A
    Georgia State University College of Law Reading Room Faculty Publications By Year Faculty Publications 1-1-1996 The Antinomy of Coherence and Determinacy William A. Edmundson Georgia State University College of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://readingroom.law.gsu.edu/faculty_pub Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Law and Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation William A. Edmundson, The Antinomy of Coherence and Determinacy, 82 Iowa L. Rev. 1 (1996). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Publications at Reading Room. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications By Year by an authorized administrator of Reading Room. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Antinomy of Coherence and Determinacy William A. Edmundson* "We must keep up the boundaries of actions, otherwise we shall introduce the utmost confusion." -Lord Raymond, in Reynokls v. Clark1 I. INTRODUCTION Two appealing ideas about law turn out to be in conflict. The first idea is that the law is or should be coherent in some sense. That is, the law should or does make sense as a whole, hang together, or fit together in some way. The second idea is that the law is or should be determinate, that is, what the law demands is or should be fixed and unambiguous, and in that sense objective and independent of what courts or other legal interpreters make of it. I will assume that both of these ideas are appealing both in the sense of actually possessing an appeal to many people and in the sense of meriting the appeal they have.
    [Show full text]
  • Strategy-Proofness and Essentially Single-Valued Cores Author(S): Tayfun Sonmez Source: Econometrica, Vol
    Strategy-Proofness and Essentially Single-Valued Cores Author(s): Tayfun Sonmez Source: Econometrica, Vol. 67, No. 3 (May, 1999), pp. 677-689 Published by: The Econometric Society Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2999552 Accessed: 10/08/2009 18:29 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=econosoc. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The Econometric Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Econometrica. http://www.jstor.org Economnteica, Vol. 67, No. 3 (May,1999), 677-689 STRATEGY-PROOFNESS AND ESSENTIALLY SINGLE-VALUED CORES BY TAYFUNS6NMEZ' 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Matching Theory
    Matching Theory Mihai Manea MIT Based on slides by Fuhito Kojima. Market Design I Traditional economics focuses mostly on decentralized markets. I Recently, economists are helping to design economic institutions for centralized markets. I placing students in schools I matching workers to firms in labor markets I matching patients to compatible organ donors I allocating space, positions, tasks I auctioning electromagnetic spectrum, landing slots at aiports I The economics of market design analyzes and develops institutions. Practical solutions require attention to the details and objectives of concrete markets. Mihai Manea (MIT) Matching Theory June 27, 2016 2 / 53 Hospitals and Residents I Graduating medical students are hired as residents at hospitals. I In the US more than 20,000 doctors and 4,000 hospitals are matched through a clearinghouse, the National Resident Matching Program. I Doctors and hospitals submit preference rankings and the clearinghouse uses an algorithm to assign positions. I Some centralized markets succeed, while others fail. What makes a good matching mechanism? Mihai Manea (MIT) Matching Theory June 27, 2016 4 / 53 School Choice I School districts use centralized student placement mechanisms. I School districts take into account the preferences of students and decide the priorities each school assigns to students. I What is a desirable student placement mechanism? Walking distance, siblings, affirmative action, test scores. Mihai Manea (MIT) Matching Theory June 27, 2016 5 / 53 Kidney Exchange I Some patients who need a kidney find a willing donor. The patient may be incompatible with the donor, in which case a direct transplant is not feasible. Figure : Blood type compatibility I A kidney exchange matches two (or more) incompatible donor-patient pairs and swaps donors.
    [Show full text]
  • Cooperative Games: Core and Shapley Value
    COOPERATIVE GAMES: CORE AND SHAPLEY VALUE Roberto Serrano CEMFI Working Paper No. 0709 July 2007 CEMFI Casado del Alisal 5; 28014 Madrid Tel. (34) 914 290 551. Fax (34) 914 291 056 Internet: www.cemfi.es CEMFI Working Paper 0709 July 2007 COOPERATIVE GAMES: CORE AND SHAPLEY VALUE Abstract This article describes the basic elements of the cooperative approach to game theory, one of the two counterparts of the discipline. After the presentation of some basic definitions, the focus will be on the core and the Shapley value, two of the most central solution concepts in cooperative game theory. JEL Codes: C7. Keywords: Game theory; cooperative game; characteristic function; solution concept; core; Shapley value; axiomatics; equivalence principle; non-cooperative implementation. Roberto Serrano Brown University and IMDEA [email protected] COOPERATIVE GAMES: CORE AND SHAPLEY VALUE by Roberto Serrano Department of Economics, Brown University and IMDEA-Social Sciences July 2007 (to appear in Encyclopedia of Complexity and Systems Science, Springer, Berlin) Outline: 1. Introduction. 2. Cooperative Games. 2.1. Representations of Games. The Characteristic Function. 2.2. Assumptions on the Characteristic Function. 2.3. Solution Concepts. 3. The Core. 3.1. Non-Emptiness. 3.2. The Connections with Competitive Equilibrium. 3.3. Axiomatic Characterizations. 3.4. Non-Cooperative Implementation. 3.5. An Application. 4. The Shapley Value. 4.1. Axiomatics. 4.2. The Connections with Competitive Equilibrium. 4.3. Non-Cooperative Implementation. 4.4. An Application. 1 Glosary of keywords: game theory; cooperative game; characteristic function; solution concept; core; Shapley value; axiomatics; equivalence principle; non-cooperative implementation. Summary: This article describes the basic elements of the cooperative approach to game theory, one of the two counterparts of the discipline.
    [Show full text]
  • Equilibrium Existence and Approximation of Regular Discontinuous Games∗
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Research Papers in Economics Equilibrium Existence and Approximation of Regular Discontinuous Games∗ forthcoming, Economic Theory Luciano I. de Castroy First version: May 2009 This version: August 2010 Abstract Many conditions have been introduced to ensure equilibrium existence in games with discontinuous payoff functions. This paper introduces a new condition, called regularity, that is simple and easy to verify. Regularity requires that if there is a sequence of strategies converging to s∗ such that the players’ payoffs along the sequence converge to the best-reply payoffs at s∗, then s∗ is an equilibrium. We show that regularity is implied both by Reny’s better-reply security and Simon and Zame’s endogenous sharing rule approach. This allows us to explore a link between these two distinct meth- ods. Although regularity implies that the limits of -equilibria are equilibria, it is in general too weak for implying equilibrium existence. However, we are able to identify extra conditions that, together with regularity, are suffi- cient for equilibrium existence. In particular, we show how regularity allows the technique of approximating games both by payoff functions and space of strategies. Keywords: Discontinuous games; weak payoff security; better-reply security; regularity; regular games; epsilon-equilibria; approximating se- quence; approximating games. JEL classification numbers: C72; C73. ∗I am grateful to Guilherme Carmona and Philip Reny for their helpful comments. yDepartment of Managerial Economics and Decisions Sciences, Kellogg School of Manage- ment, Northwestern University, Evanston, IL 60201, USA. E-mail: [email protected] 1 1 Introduction Many classical problems in economics are modeled as games with a continuum of actions, but discontinuous payoffs.
    [Show full text]
  • Two-Sided Strategy-Proofness in Many-To-Many Matching Markets
    UC3M Working papers Departamento de Economía Economics Universidad Carlos III de Madrid 17-17 Calle Madrid, 126 December, 2017 28903 Getafe (Spain) ISSN 2340-5031 Fax (34) 916249875 Two-sided strategy-proofness in many-to-many matching markets Antonio Romero-Medina, Matteo Triossi†‡ December 18, 2017 Abstract We study the existence of group strategy-proof stable rules in many to-many matching markets. We show that when firms have acyclical preferences over workers the set of stable matchings is a singleton, and the worker-optimal stable mechanism is a stable and group strategy-proof rule for firms and workers. Furthermore, acyclicity is the minimal condition guaranteeing the existence of stable and strategy-proof mechanisms in many-to-many matching markets. JEL Classification Numbers: C71; C78; D71; D78. Keywords: Many-to-many markets, Acyclicity, Stability, Two-sided Group Strategy-proofness, Singleton core. Departamento de Economía, Universidad Carlos III de Madrid. † Centro de Economía Aplicada, Departamento de Ingeniería Industrial, Universidad de Chile. Beaucheff 851, Santiago, Chile. ‡ Corresponding Author 1 Introduction Many relevant real-world markets are many-to-many. The canonical example of a many-to-many market is the specialty training followed by junior doctors in the UK (Roth, 1991). Other examples of many-to-many markets are markets where workers are allowed to work part-time and the non-exclusive dealings between down-stream firms and up-stream providers. Many-to-many markets are also useful to model multi-unit assignment problems such as course allocations (see Budish 2011, S¨onmezand Unver,¨ 2010, Kojima, 2013) or the assignment of landing slots (see Schummer and Abizada, 2017, Schummer and Vohra, 2013).
    [Show full text]