POLITICAL PLATONISM in the ENGLISH RENAISSANCE Donald

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

POLITICAL PLATONISM in the ENGLISH RENAISSANCE Donald View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Carolina Digital Repository POLITICAL PLATONISM IN THE ENGLISH RENAISSANCE Donald Douglas Wells A dissertation submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of English. Chapel Hill 2007 Approved by: Reid Barbour Mary Floyd-Wilson C.D.C. Reeve Jessica L. Wolfe Larry Goldberg ABSTRACT DONALD WELLS: Political Platonism in the English Renaissance (Under the direction of Reid Barbour) I argue that the influence of Platonic thought in Renaissance England cannot be properly understood without attending to what I call “Political Platonism”—a particularly civic approach to Plato and his works. Political Platonism, which derives in part from the efforts of early humanists such as Leonardo Bruni, differs sharply from the approach favored by more well-known Platonists such as Marsilio Ficino and Pico della Mirandola. Where Pico and Ficino are drawn primarily to Plato’s metaphysical and cosmological speculations, Political Platonists tend to favor his moral, political, and rhetorical ideas. After identifying Political Platonism and distinguishing it from the Cosmological Platonism favored by Ficino and Pico in the first chapter, I trace its appearance in English writers with significant Platonic influence throughout the Renaissance in subsequent chapters. Chapter Two examines early Tudor writers such as Thomas More and Thomas Elyot, with whom the pressing needs of the new political regime combine with their own humanist ideals to produce a uniquely civic approach to Plato. Chapter Three explores how Francis Bacon uses, changes, and challenges Plato in the course of developing his own program for the advancement of science. Finally, in Chapter Four I show how John Milton continues to read Plato as a civic philosopher even as he wrestles anew with the difficulties confronting the adaptation of classical philosophy to Christian culture. ii DEDICATION With love, to my mother, without whose support this dissertation would not have been completed. iii TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter I. ENGLAND AND RENAISSANCE PLATONISM ..........................……..1 Existing Scholarship on Plato and Renaissance England ..................……..4 The Platonic Revival(s) in Italy .........................................................……..8 Political Platonism and Theological Platonism .................................……18 Political Platonism, England, and the Transmission of Texts ...........……31 II. POLITICAL PLATONISM AND THE EARLY TUDORS .............……37 The Platonic Humanism of Sir Thomas Elyot ...................................……39 Thomas Starkey and the Limitations of Plato....................................……64 Thomas More and the Political Plato.................................................……74 Political Platonism in the Elizabethan Era.........................................……95 III. FRANCIS BACON’S READING OF PLATO .................................…..103 Incidental and Minor References.......................................................…..104 Plato, Politics and Morals ..................................................................…..107 The Limitations of Platonism.............................................................…..110 Bacon and the Philosopher-King .......................................................…..120 What Knowledge is For .....................................................................…..123 Bacon and Rhetoric............................................................................…..127 Affections and Appetites....................................................................…..133 iv Plato and The New Atlantis................................................................…..137 After Bacon........................................................................................…..150 IV. RETHINKING MILTON AND PLATO...........................................…..152 Plato and Rhetoric..............................................................................…..155 Plato and Civic Thought ....................................................................…..160 Political Principles and Examples......................................................…..169 Plato and Moral Virtue.......................................................................…..177 Paradise Lost and Milton’s Reading of Plato....................................…..182 Reflections .........................................................................................…..186 General Conclusion............................................................................…..187 WORKS CITED ........................................................................................................…..190 v CHAPTER 1 ENGLAND AND RENAISSANCE PLATONISM In the last book of Paradise Regained, Milton’s Jesus offers a remarkable and dismissive account of ancient philosophy. Of particular note are his words at the outset on Socrates and Plato1: The first and wisest of them all profess’d To know this only, that he nothing knew; The next to fabling fell and smooth conceits. (ll. 293-5) At first glance the judgment seems clear enough. Socrates at least admitted his ignorance, but Plato was a liar, a poet, a maker of fables. On closer examination, however, these lines become more and more confusing. How could a Milton who elsewhere makes use of technical matters from dialogues such as Cratylus and Philebus seriously dismiss the whole of Plato as “fabling” and “smooth conceits?” Though there is certainly precedent for calling Socrates the wisest of philosophers, in what sense is he “first?” Why would he make Jesus go on to complain that the philosophers accuse God under names like Fortune and Fate when Milton himself elsewhere praises Plato and others precisely for not doing so? What at first seems an almost casual and simple dismissal upon reflection becomes a locus for serious questions. Jesus’ words on the philosophers are all the more startling in their immediate context. He is replying to a fourth temptation—one Milton has added to the three found in the biblical account of the wilderness encounter between Jesus and Satan. Further, this 1 All references to Plato are to the English translations available online at The Perseus Digital Library. new temptation sounds much like one which classical studies posed to Renaissance Christians: Be famous then By wisdom; as thy empire must extend So let extend thy mind o’er all the world In knowledge, all things in it comprehend, All knowledge is not couch’t in Moses’ law, The Pentateuch, or what the Prophets wrote, The Gentiles also know, and write, and teach To admiration, led by Nature’s light. (ll. 221-8) When Satan adds that Gentile knowledge is most useful for one who would deal with Gentiles, “ruling them by persuasion as thou mean’st” (l. 230), one is reminded of the love and hope Renaissance authors held for classical learning and rhetoric. Many humanists, for instance, hoped to find what Satan offers here—guides to knowledge, writing, and teaching; wisdom to supplement and expand that offered by the Bible, the Church, and the Fathers—in classical authorities. When Jesus replies, “He who receives / Light from above, from the fountain of light, / No other doctrine needs, though granted true” (ll. 288-90), it sounds like a repudiation of the Renaissance rehabilitation of classical learning. If divine revelation alone is necessary, what authority and value can pagan Greece and Rome hold? Milton’s words can sound harsh to ears accustomed to hearing only praises sung of the classics or of Plato. But the manner in which classical authority is subordinated and circumscribed in this passage is most useful for outlining the manner in which many English Renaissance authors read, understood, and used the classics in general—and Plato in particular. I begin with the distinction and subordination of wisdom, implied at the beginning of Satan’s speech, into natural and revealed. What the classics, and Satan, offer is bracketed by the rare use of rhyme: we may extend our minds over and 2 comprehend “the world,” that is, nature. Wisdom, expressed by the traditional metaphor of light, seems to come in two forms: we may be led by the light of Nature, and Satan offers the fruits of this, or we may receive “light from above,” or from the divine. The authority of the classics lies entirely with the light of Nature, which has decidedly the second place in honor. We must be careful, though, with this distinction. It is not absolute. Rather, the one, the light of Nature, in some way depends upon or derives from the divine light—for it is not only “from above,” it is “the fountain of light.” Matters which seem worldly or mundane are not entirely to be separated from matters eternal and divine. For instance, Jesus insists that the Prophets better teach “the solid rules of civil government” (l. 358) than any of the orators of old. No thoughtful writer in Renaissance England could fail to notice, say, how problems of politics could influence religion and vice versa. And one who believed in the incarnation of the deity, or who looked for a true resurrection of the flesh, might well find an absolute division between temporal, ever-changing matter and timeless, eternal spirit difficult to sustain. Nevertheless, a distinction can still be drawn between things known by one’s reason alone and those known only by revelation—and
Recommended publications
  • Influencia De La Nocion De Libertad De Gregorio Niiseno Sobre La Filosofía Del Siglo XV En Italia a Través De La Recepción De
    Influencia de la nocion de libertad de Gregorio Niiseno sobre la filosofía del siglo XV en Italia a través de la recepción de sus textos Bastitta Harriet, Francisco D'Amico, Claudia F. 2015 Tesis presentada con el fin de cumplimentar con los requisitos finales para la obtención del título Doctor de la Facultad de Filosofía y Letras de la Universidad de Buenos Aires en Filosofía UIVERSIDAD DE BUEOS AIRES Facultad de Filosofía y Letras TESIS DE DOCTORADO Título : “Influencia de la noción de libertad de Gregorio Niseno sobre la filosofía del siglo XV en Italia a través de la recepción de sus textos” Directora : Dra. Claudia D'Amico Co-Director : Dr. Pablo Cavallero Doctorando: Lic. Francisco Bastitta Harriet ° de Exp.: 0843448/2008 Buenos Aires, noviembre de 2015 IDICE GEERAL ITRODUCCIÓ ..................................................................................................................... 3 Sección I - La concepción de la libertad de Gregorio de isa y su suerte medieval en Occidente CAP. 1) LA TEORÍA GREGORIAA DE LA LIBERTAD PERSOAL 24 1.1. El puesto del hombre en el cosmos ....................................................................................... 25 1.2. La imagen de Dios en el hombre como libertad. Su carácter cuasi divino .......................... 41 1.3. La nueva noción de hipóstasis aplicada a Dios y a los hombres .......................................... 49 1.4. Hacia un sentido ‘personal’ y creativo de la decisión y el albedrío ..................................... 58 1.5. Autoridad y decisión más allá de la necesidad y del orden causal ....................................... 73 CAP. 2) PRESECIA DE LA TEORÍA DE LA LIBERTAD DEL ISEO E LOS AUTORES MEDIEVALES....................................................................................................... 92 2.1. Las dos primeras traducciones latinas del De opificio hominis ........................................... 93 2.2. La teoría de la libertad del iseno en los autores medievales bizantinos ...........................
    [Show full text]
  • The Renaissance, and the Rediscovery of Plato and the Greeks
    Click here for Full Issue of Fidelio Volume 12, Number 3, Fall 2003 The Renaissance, and The Rediscovery of Plato And the G by Torbjörn Jerlerup t was in the Midland between the ‘ famous rivers Po and Ticino and IAdda and others, whence some say our Milan derives its name, on the ninth day of October, in the year of this last age of the world the 1360th.”1 For the people who lived in the Italian city of Milan or in one of its surrounding villages, it might have looked like an ordinary, but cold, autumn morning. It was Friday. The city council and the bishop of Milan were probably quarrelling about the construction of a new cathedral in the city. The construction would not start for another 25 years. The university professors and the barbers (the doctors Alinari/Art Resource, NY of the time), were probably worried Domenico di Michelino, “Dante Alighieri Reading His Poem,” 1465 about rumors of a new plague, the (detail). The Cathedral of Florence, topped by Brunelleschi’s Dome, third since the Great Plague in 1348, appears to Dante’s left. and the townspeople were probably complaining about taxes, as usual. The Great minds of ancient Greece farmers, who led their cattle to pas- (clockwise from top): Homer, Plato, ture, were surely complaining about Solon, Aeschylus, Sophocles. the weather, as it had been unusually unstable. 36 © 2003 Schiller Institute, Inc. All Rights Reserved. Reproduction in whole or in part without permission strictly prohibited. The Granger Collection of Plato EIRNS/Philip Ulanowsky Greeks The Granger Collection If they were not too busy with their cows, they perhaps caught a glimpse of a monk riding along the grassy, mud-ridden path that was part of the main road between the cities of Florence and The Granger Collection Milan.
    [Show full text]
  • GALILEO CREATION and COSMOGONY a Study on the Interplay Between Galileo’S Science of Motion and the Creation Theme [M-STO/05, M-FIL/06]
    DOCTORAL DISSERTATION GALILEO CREATION AND COSMOGONY A Study on the Interplay between Galileo’s Science of Motion and the Creation Theme [M-STO/05, M-FIL/06] Ph.D. Candidate Ph.D. Coordinator IVAN MALARA Prof. ANDREA PINOTTI Registration number: R11933 JOINT PH.D. SUPERVISORS Università degli Studi di Milano Prof. LUCA BIANCHI Doctoral course in Philosophy and Human Sciences – XXXIII Cycle Prof. ELIO NENCI (Dipartimento di Filosofia “Piero Martinetti”) Gent Universiteit Prof. MAARTEN VAN DYCK Academic Year 2019/2020 È chiaro che il pensiero dà fastidio anche se chi pensa è muto come un pesce anzi è un pesce e come pesce è difficile da bloccare perché lo protegge il mare Com’è profondo il mare LUCIO DALLA, Com’è profondo il mare (1977) Non ’mbrischiare a calia ca ’nzudda (Calabrian saying) Table of contents Abstract English .........................................................................................................VII Italian ..........................................................................................................VIII Dutch.............................................................................................................IX Introduction .............................................................................................................XI PART ONE: CREATION I. Anno 1607: Galileo and Castelli 1. Galileo in 1607..............................................................................................3 2. Castelli in 1607. The epistulae Cavenses.......................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Forgetful Platonism: Misrepresenting Proclus and Twentieth-Century
    Misrepresenting Neoplatonism in Contemporary Christian Dionysian Polemic: Eriugena and Nicholas of Cusa versus Vladimir Lossky and Jean-Luc Marion American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 82:4 (2008): 683–703. Wayne Hankey Part I: From Eriugena to Nicholas of Cusa The Corpus Areopagiticum in Greek—or at least a part of it—circulated in Rome, probably from the time of Gregory the Great‘s Homily XXIV (592 or 593), but certainly from the middle of the seventh up to the second half of the ninth century.1 Nonetheless, there was no profound encounter by the Latins with the philosophical and mystical content of the corpus, until the translations by Hilduin and Eriugena consequent on its arrival at the Frankish court in 827.2 John the Scot‘s grasp and development of what the Areopagite passed on from his sources has only rarely been equalled. After Boethius, he was the first to draw together the Greek and Latin Platonists. Among the Latins, Augustine and Boethius, together with Ambrose, because, as Eriugena wrote, he so often followed the Greeks, were pre-eminent .3 He learned most from the Greek texts he translated—the Dionysian corpus, the Ambigua and Scoliae of Maximus the Confessor, and the De hominis opificio of Gregory of Nyssa—; what he took from the Latins was generally assimilated to their logic.4 His sources were so nearly exclusively Christian, and the texts so predominantly theological and mystical—despite such ―secular‖ and pagan authorities as the De nuptiis Philologiae et Mercurii of Martianus Capella from his Irish education5—that no real confrontation between Hellenic and Christian Neoplatonisms occurs for him.
    [Show full text]
  • One Thousand Years of Proclus an Introduction to His Reception Stephen Gersh
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-19849-3 - Interpreting Proclus: From Antiquity to the Renaissance Edited by Stephen Gersh Excerpt More information One thousand years of Proclus An introduction to his reception Stephen Gersh To describe the reception of Proclus in European thought in either a nar- rative or an analytical form is undoubtedly a complicated task. It is well known that a substantial part of the history of Platonism – and indeed, the entirety of that history down to the seventeenth century – is the his- tory of what we nowadays term “Neoplatonism” (together with that of the closely related phenomenon of “Middle Platonism”). It is less well known, although it is a demonstrable historical fact rather than a histor- ian’s subjective view, that the influence of Proclus far outweighs that of any other Neoplatonist. That the name of Proclus’ predecessor Plotinus tends to come to mind when people who are not among the ranks of academic specialists think of the term “Neoplatonism” results from cer- tain features of the current “hermeneutical situation.” These include the respective chronological positions of Plotinus and Proclus that bring the former into the purview of classicists and leave the latter outside it, the fact that – methodologically speaking – the essentials of Plotinus’ philosoph- ical position need to be grasped before proceeding to the explanation of Proclus’ doctrine, and the two philosophers’ respective degrees of potential consistency with the monotheistic Christian worldview, which is greater in the case of Plotinus than it is in that of Proclus. However, there are also good reasons for re-evaluating or “rehabilitating” Proclus at the present time, not the least of which is the enormous extent of his influence in the medieval Latin and Byzantine worlds and in the Renaissance.1 In order to avoid the danger of losing sight of the wood for the trees, I will frame a narrative of Proclus’ influence within European thought between approximately 500 and 1600 of the Common Era by working along two trajectories.
    [Show full text]
  • Concetta BIANCA NICCOLÒ CUSANO E
    CoNCETTA BIANCA NICCOLÒ CUSANO E LA SUA BIBLIOTECA: NOTE, 'NOTABILIA', GLOSSE Nella dedica a Paolo II dell'edizione di Lucii Apuleii Opera, stampata a 1 Roma da Sweynheym e Pannartz il 28 febbraio 1469 , Giovanni Andrea Bus­ si, vescovo di Aleria, tracciava un profilo di Niccolò Cusano, cardinale di San Pietro in Vincoli, di cui era stato segretario per quasi sei anni, dal 1458 alla morte di quest'ultimo nel 1464 2• Il profilo è intessuto di ricordi personali, ma, di là dall'affetto dichiarato e dal riconoscimento della funzione culturale che il Cusano ebbe nella formazione intellettuale del Bussi, ne scaturisce un giudizio lucido e ponderato: le doti morali («vitiorum omnium hostis acerri­ mus») si intrecciano con quelle intellettuali («studiosissimus», «eloquens et latinus») 3, gli interessi filosofici - di cui il Bussi, proprio negli anni in cui scoppiava violenta la polemica tra platonici ed aristolelici con la pubblicazio­ ne, tra l'altro, dell'In calumniatorem Platonis del Bessarione4, sottolineava giusta­ mente le direttive principali («philosophiae aristotelicae acerrimus disputa­ tor»)5 - si accompagnano con le preoccupazioni di riforma ecclesiale e con 1 L. HAIN, Repertorium bibliographiCiim [ ...], I, 1, Milano 1948, n. 1314; Indice Generale degli Incunaboli [... ], I, Roma 1943, n. 769; Gesamtkatalog der Wiegendmcke [... ],II, Stuttgart-New York 19682, n. 2301; Indice delle edizioni romane a stampa[ ...], Città del Vaticano 1980, n. 27. Cfr. M. D. FELD, Sweynheym and Pannartz, Cardinal Bessarion, Neoplatonism: Renaissance Humanism and Two Ear!J Printers' Choise oJ Texts, «Harvard Library Bulletin», XXX (1982), pp. 282-335. 2 La dedica a Paolo II è pubblicata in G.
    [Show full text]
  • Bessarion's Life 9
    Open Research Online The Open University’s repository of research publications and other research outputs Culture, humanism and intellect: Cardinal Bessarion as patron of the arts Thesis How to cite: Bolick, Laura (2014). Culture, humanism and intellect: Cardinal Bessarion as patron of the arts. PhD thesis The Open University. For guidance on citations see FAQs. c 2014 The Author https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ Version: Version of Record Link(s) to article on publisher’s website: http://dx.doi.org/doi:10.21954/ou.ro.0000eeef Copyright and Moral Rights for the articles on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. For more information on Open Research Online’s data policy on reuse of materials please consult the policies page. oro.open.ac.uk UNRESTRIC1ED - Culture, Humanism and Intellect: Cardinal Bessarion as Patron of the Arts Laura Bolick Volume I Text Dissertation Submitted for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Open University 13 May 2013 Date.. 01 SU.b~5Sl0v\ ~ q M~ 2Dl3 Date 0d fv.No.xo.; 51'rVVll lollf IMAGING SERVICES NORTH Boston Spa, Wetherby West Yorkshire, LS23 7BQ www.bl.uk PAGE/PAGES EXCLU DED UNDER INSTRUCTION FROM THE UNIVERSITY Culture, Humanism and Intellect: Cardinal Bessarion as Patron of the Arts Abstract To date many scholars seem to have agreed that Cardinal Bessarion was a physical and spiritual exile from Constantinople who sought to preserve his national culture in the alien environment of fifteenth-century Rome. In this thesis I am seeking to re-open the debate about Bessarion's role and aspirations in western Europe as expressed through the mechanism of his cultural projects.
    [Show full text]
  • The Prolegomenon to Proclus' Platonic Theology. an Introduction
    The Prolegomenon to Proclus’ Platonic Theology An Introduction, Translation, and Commentary of Chapters 1-7 of Book I of the Platonic Theology Thèse Simon Fortier Doctorat en Philosophie Philosophiae Doctor (Ph.D.) Québec, Canada © Simon Fortier, 2014 Résumé Bien qu‘elle représente son opus magnum, la Théologie platonicienne de Proclus a souvent été négligée par les études néoplatoniciennes récentes. Hormis l‘importante édition et traduction de cette œuvre dans la Collection des Universités de France (Proclus, Théologie platonicienne, 6 vol., éd. H. D. Saffrey et L. G. Westerink, Paris, 1968-1997), et le Festschrift qui l‘a célébrée par la suite (Proclus et la théologie platonicienne, Actes du Colloque International de Louvain [13-16 mai 1998], en l'honneur de H. D. Saffrey et L. G. Westerink (†), éd. A. Ph. Segonds (†) et C. Steel,, Leuven/Paris, 2000), peu de travaux ont été consacrés à la Théologie platonicienne. Le signe le plus révélateur de ce manque criant est sans aucun doute l‘absence d‘une traduction anglaise digne de foi et d‘un commentaire détaillé de cette œuvre, pourtant capitale, de la tradition philosophique occidentale. La présente traduction anglaise des premiers chapitres des prolégomènes de la Théologie platonicienne (chap. 1-7), accompagnée d‘une introduction, d‘un essai interprétatif et d‘un commentaire détaillé, cherche en partie à combler cette lacune, espérant aussi stimuler par-là l‘intérêt pour ce dernier grand monument de la philosophie antique tardive. iii Abstract Despite being his magnum opus, Proclus‘ Platonic Theology has been largely overlooked by the contemporary revival of Neoplatonic scholarship. Aside the publication of H.
    [Show full text]