Theories of Ethical Reasoning and Your Business

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Theories of Ethical Reasoning and Your Business Theories of Ethical Reasoning and Your Business By Dana Basney 1 Dana Basney, MSBA, CPA, ABV, CIRA (retired), CVA (retired), CFF, CFE Dana Basney is a retired Managing Director of CBIZ MHM, LLC and a former Shareholder of Mayer Hoffman McCann P.C. He has practiced public accounting for more than 37 years. He is in charge of CBIZ MHM San Diego’s litigation support, due diligence, and valuation departments. Dana holds a Bachelor's Degree in Liberal Arts from Bates College in Lewiston, Maine and received a Master's Degree in Business Administration and Accounting from San Diego State University. Dana is a licensed CPA and a Certified Reorganization and Insolvency Accountant, as well as a Certified Valuation Analyst. He is a member of The American Institute of Certified Public Accountants, The California Society of Certified Public Accountants, The Institute of Managerial Accountants, The Association of Insolvency Accountants, The Institute of Business Appraisers, Inc., and the Bankruptcy Forum. He has served on the Family Law Bar's Business Valuation Subcommittee and has previously chaired the San Diego Chapter of the CPA Society’s Ethic2s Committee and the San Diego Litigation Support Interest Group of the CPA Society. Dana has extensive litigation experience and has served as an expert witness in financial and valuation matters on numerous occasions as well as a court appointed mediator and special master. Dana is also an instructor at the University of San Diego where he teaches Accounting Ethics, Fraud Examination and Forensic Accounting. He also teaches Fraud and Ethics courses for the California CPA Education Foundation. Dana may be reached at: [email protected] or 858.775.9071 2 Most People Initially Think of Ethics as Being Boring 3 What is Ethics? • Accepted standards of behavior • Practices of those in a profession • Laws • Expectations of society 4 What is Ethics? • Ethics, derived from the Greek word ethikos (character), deals with the concepts of right and wrong; standards of how people ought to act. • Morals, derived from the Latin word moralis, deals with manners, morals, character. • Ethics and morals are essentially the same. • Values are basic and fundamental beliefs that guide or motivate attitudes or actions 5 How Are Business Ethics Defined? A widely accepted definition of business ethics does not exist. 6 The best definition of ethics is also the most laconic one “Knowing what ought to be done and having the will to do it.” Source: Hall, S.S.J. (ED.) Ethics in Hospitality Management: A book of readings. East Lansing, MI: Educational Institute of the American Hotel and Motel Association; pp 12 -13. 7 Theories of Ethical Reasoning Deontology ( Duty Based Ethics) Teleology (Consequential Ethics) Justice Virtue Ethics Enlightened Ethical Judgements Egoism Egoism Utilitarianism Considers Rights of Stakeholders and Defines "right" Evaluates consequences of Emhasizes rights Only method where ethical Related Duties to Them. behavior by actions (harms and Benefits) ,fairness and Equality reasoning methods - "Vitues" Consequences Considers the well- to Stakeholders (Internal Traits of Character) - for the decision being of others within apply both to the decision Maker the scope of deciding maker and the decision on a course of action based on self interest Values Inputs not Results ACT: Evaluate Whether the Those with equal Judgements are made not by intended action provides the claims to justice applying rules, but by greatest should be treated possessing those traits that equally; those with enable the decision maker to unequal claims act for the good of others. should be treated unequally Treats People as an end and not merely Rule: Select the action that Similar to Principles of the as a means to an end conforms to the correct moral AICPA CODE and IMA rule that produces the Standards greatest net benefits Universality Perspective : Would I want others to act in a similar manner for similar reasons in this situation Associated with Immanual Kant (1724 - Associated with Jeremy Associated with John Traces origins back to the 1804) Thomas Hobbes(1588-1679) and Bentham 1748- 1832) and Rawls (1921 - 2002) ancient Greeks, Plato and John Locke (1632-1704)from the John Stuart Mills (1806 - Aristotle age of enlightenment 1873) Problems with Relies on moral absolutes - no Fails to consider Interest of others are Can be difficult to assign Can be difficult to Virtues may conflict, requiring Implementation exceptions; need to resolve conflicting interest of others subservient to self values to harms and benefits determine the criteria choices to be made. rights affected by the interest to distinguish equal decision from unequal claims 8 Religious and Philosophical Foundations of Ethics • A version of the Golden Rule appears in each of the world’s religions • Ethics can be traced back to ancient Greek philosophy . “What is the best sort of life for human beings to live?” . Greeks believed the ultimate goal of happiness was to attain some objectively good status: the life of excellence 9 Deontology Deontology – A theory of reciprocal Rights and duties 10 Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) and Deontological or Duty Based Ethics Kant's theory is an example of a deontological or duty-based ethics : it judges morality by examining the nature of actions and the will of agents rather than goals achieved. (Roughly, a deontological theory looks at inputs rather than outcomes.) One reason for the shift away from consequences to duties is that, in spite of our best efforts, we cannot control the future. We are praised or blamed for actions within our control, and that includes our willing, not our achieving. This is not to say that Kant did not care about the outcomes of our actions–we all wish for good things. Rather Kant insisted that as far as the moral evaluation of our actions was concerned, consequences did not matter. As suggested by the first version of the categorical imperative above, if the maxim or rule governing our action is not capable of being universalized, then it is unacceptable. Note that universalizability is not the same as universality. Kant's point is not that we would all agree on some rule if it is moral. Instead, we must be able to will that it be made universal; the idea is very much like the golden rule –Do unto others as you would have them do unto you. If you cannot will that everyone follow the same rule, your rule is not a moral one. The second version of the categorical imperative given above emphasizes respect for persons . Persons, unlike things, ought never to be merely used. Deontological ethics is strongest in many of the areas where utilitarianism is weakest. In an ethics of duty, the ends can never justify the means. Individual human rights are acknowledged and inviolable. We need not consider the satisfaction of harmful desires in our moral deliberations. In practice, however, Kant's ethics poses two great problems : 1. Unlike the proportionality that comes out of the utility principle, the categorical imperative yields only absolutes . Actions either pass or fail with no allowance for a "gray area." Moreover, the rigid lines are often drawn in unlikely places. For example, lying is always wrong–even the "polite lie." 2. Moral dilemmas are created when duties come in conflict, and there is no mechanism for solving them. Utilitarianism permits a ready comparison of all actions, and if a set of alternatives have the same expected utility, they are equally good. Conflicting duties, however, may require that I perform logically or physically incompatible actions, and my failure to do any one is itself a moral wrong. (Extracted from the writings of Prof. Charles D. Kay of Wofford College) 11 Thomas Hobbes – An Early Advocate of Deontological Ethics • Thomas Hobbes 1588-1679 • Philosopher • Writer • Thomas Hobbes was an English philosopher who wrote the 1651 book, Leviathan, a political treatise that described the natural life of mankind as "solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short." Hobbes was educated at Oxford and worked as a tutor to the son of William Cavendish, later the Earl of Devonshire. His connections to the royal family gave him opportunities to travel and pursue his studies, but they also put him in the middle of the English Civil War. In 1640 political turmoil forced him to leave England for France, where he continued to associate with scholars and scientists of Europe, including Galileo and Rene Descartes. In his philosophical works, Hobbes wrote that matter and motion are the only valid subjects for philosophy. In Leviathan, he argued that man's natural state is anti-social, and that moral rules are created to avoid chaos. Hobbes's notion that social authority can come from the people -- and not necessarily a monarch -- rankled his royal associates, but helped him reconcile with Oliver Cromwell and the English revolutionaries, and he returned to England shortly after Leviathan was published. After the Restoration of 1660, Hobbes was favored by King Charles II, who granted him a pension, but urged him to clear future publications with the throne. Hobbes's "nasty, brutish and short" line is still used often when students and politicians discuss human nature and the proper role of government. • Source: Who 2 Biographies on the Internet 12 John Locke • John Locke (1632-1704) • Philosopher • John Locke was a 17th-century English philosopher whose ideas formed the foundation of liberal democracy and greatly influenced both the American and French revolutions. His contributions to philosophy include the theory of knowledge known as empiricism, which addressed the limits of what we can understand about the nature of reality. Locke held that our understanding of reality ultimately derives from what we have experienced through the senses. The political implications of his theories included the notions that all people are born equal and that education can free people from the subjugation of tyranny.
Recommended publications
  • Is Business Ethics Possible and Necessary?, Economics & Sociology, Vol
    Lech Keller-Krawczyk 133 ISSN 2071-789X INTERDISCIPLINARY APPROACH TO ECONOMICS AND SOCIOLOGY Lech Keller-Krawczyk, Is Business Ethics Possible and Necessary?, Economics & Sociology, Vol. 3, No 1, 2010, pp. 133-142. Lech Keller-Krawczyk IS BUSINESS ETHICS POSSIBLE AND CETRAD-UTAD Universidade de Trás-os-Montes e NECESSARY? Alto Douro, Portugal ABSTRACT. In this paper I try to define business ethics, the need for it and discuss if it is possible and necessary. I understand business ethics as a subset of applied ethics relating to business activity of human beings. I also explain Received: February, 2010 the differences between ethics and law, especially business 1st Revision: March, 2010 ethics and business law, as well as differences between Accepted: April, 2010 business etiquette, and business ethics. I also argue that the rising challenge from China and India, strong independence movements in Latin America and prolonged socio-economic crisis in Western Europe, as well as the recent events in the US, made it no longer possible to ignore the ethical dimension of business activities. Finally, I signal the fundamental questions of business ethics, such as. 1. What is ownership, and is it moral? 2. Are relationships between labour and capital based on sound moral principles? 3. Where is the border between ethical and unethical methods in fighting the competition? 4. What is the definition of “fair profit”? The conclusion is that as the “invisible hand of the market” rarely solves the ethical problems in business, so business ethics is really a necessity. JEL Classification: A14, L29 Keywords: business ethics, business law.
    [Show full text]
  • The Law and Ethics of Trade Secrets: a Case Study
    California Western Law Review Volume 42 Number 2 Article 3 2006 The Law and Ethics of Trade Secrets: A Case Study Kurt M. Saunders California State University, Northridge Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.cwsl.edu/cwlr Recommended Citation Saunders, Kurt M. (2006) "The Law and Ethics of Trade Secrets: A Case Study," California Western Law Review: Vol. 42 : No. 2 , Article 3. Available at: https://scholarlycommons.law.cwsl.edu/cwlr/vol42/iss2/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by CWSL Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in California Western Law Review by an authorized editor of CWSL Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Saunders: The Law and Ethics of Trade Secrets: A Case Study THE LAW AND ETHICS OF TRADE SECRETS: A CASE STUDY KURT M. SAUNDERS* "[Niothing is secret, that shall not be made manifest...., ABSTRACT Almost every business owns proprietary information that adds value and provides a competitive advantage because the information is not known to the business's competitors. Trade secret law protects such information from theft or unauthorized disclosure. Because one of the principal policies underlying trade secret law is the maintenance of standards of commercial ethics, trade secrets are a rich source of material for exploring questions of business ethics alongside the law. This pedagogical case study offers a means to examine the legal and ethical issues involving the protection and misappropriation of trade secrets within the business environment. I. INTRODUCTION Decisions made by business managers are never made in an ethi- cal vacuum; usually such decisions have a wide-reaching impact on shareholders, employees, consumers, communities, and other busi- nesses.
    [Show full text]
  • War Rights and Military Virtues: a Philosophical Re-Appraisal of Just War Theory
    The University of Notre Dame Australia ResearchOnline@ND Theses 2014 War rights and military virtues: A philosophical re-appraisal of Just War Theory Matthew T. Beard University of Notre Dame Australia Follow this and additional works at: https://researchonline.nd.edu.au/theses Part of the Philosophy Commons COMMONWEALTH OF AUSTRALIA Copyright Regulations 1969 WARNING The material in this communication may be subject to copyright under the Act. Any further copying or communication of this material by you may be the subject of copyright protection under the Act. Do not remove this notice. Publication Details Beard, M. T. (2014). War rights and military virtues: A philosophical re-appraisal of Just War Theory (Doctor of Philosophy (PhD)). University of Notre Dame Australia. https://researchonline.nd.edu.au/theses/96 This dissertation/thesis is brought to you by ResearchOnline@ND. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses by an authorized administrator of ResearchOnline@ND. For more information, please contact [email protected]. War Rights and Military Virtues A Philosophical Re-appraisal of Just War Theory Doctoral Thesis Prepared by Matthew T. Beard School of Philosophy and Theology University of Notre Dame, Australia Supervised by Christian Enemark and Hayden Ramsay Supported by The Morris Research Scholarship Declaration I, Matthew Thomas Beard, declare that this PhD thesis, entitled War Rights and Military Virtues: A Philosophical Re-appraisal of Just War Theory is no more than 100,000 words exclusive of title pages, table of contents, acknowledgements, list of figures, reference list, and footnotes. The thesis is my own original work, prepared for the specific and unique purposes of this academic degree and has not been submitted in whole or part for the awarding of any other academic degree at any institution.
    [Show full text]
  • Examining the Philosophical Inconsistencies of Libertarian Paternalism
    Munich Personal RePEc Archive The Curious Case of Choice Architect: Examining the Philosophical Inconsistencies of Libertarian Paternalism Kuriakose, Francis and Kylasam Iyer, Deepa Erasmus University Rotterdam, University of Cambridge 24 April 2017 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/84842/ MPRA Paper No. 84842, posted 06 Nov 2019 16:37 UTC The Curious Case of Choice Architect: Examining the Philosophical Inconsistencies of Libertarian Paternalism Francis Kuriakose and Deepa Kylasam Iyer April 2017 Abstract Classical economics works on the principle that individuals are rational and make decisions to maximize their self interest. However in real situations, individuals face a conflict between rational and irrational selves leading to decision making that does not leave them better off. Libertarian paternalism proposes a solution to this rationality problem in an individual by conceiving a choice architect. Choice architect is a third party capable of arriving at what a perfectly rational choice would be and ‘nudges’ an individual towards making that choice. Libertarian paternalists claim that choice architect does not interfere with the freedom of an individual because the choices he offers are easily reversible, i.e, an individual can reject it at any given point in time. Libertarian Paternalism seems to offer the third way between absolute autonomy of individual choice (libertarianism) and third party intervention (paternalism). This paper argues that the conception of a choice architect comes out of a hasty commitment to reconciling libertarianism and paternalism by placing perfect rationality and autonomy in two separate individuals in the case of a single decision making process. The paper proposes alternatives to confront the rationality problem.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Unit 4 Ethics in the History of Western Philosophy
    1 UNIT 4 ETHICS IN THE HISTORY OF WESTERN PHILOSOPHY Contents 4.0 Objectives 4.1 Introduction 4.2 Epicurus 4.3 Aristotle 4.4 Thomas Aquinas 4.5 William of Ockham 4.6 Thomas Hobbes 4.7 Jeremy Bentham 4.8 Immanuel Kant 4.9 John Stuart Mill 4.10 Emile Durkheim 4.11 Let Us Sum Up 4.12 Key Words 4.13 Further Readings and References 4.0 OBJECTIVES As Sir David Ross points out, in a classical work Foundations of Ethics, written over sixty years ago, there are, broadly speaking, two approaches to ethics. This is better known as the distinction between deontological and teleological ethics. The Greek word for an ‘end’, in the sense of a goal to be achieved, is telos. Hence, ‘teleological’ ethics comprises all those kinds of ethics which see the criterion of morality in terms of whether an action fulfills the overall total end of human life in general and of moral activity in particular. The word ‘deontological’ was coined by the British moralist, Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832), from the Greek word, deon, literally, that which is binding. Deontological ethics views the morally good in terms of doing ones duty. Deontology would be the science of moral duties. We shall see that these two approaches differ more in emphasis than anything else; they are not mutually exclusive water- tight compartments. 4.1 INTRODUCTION Let us start with teleological approach. Ever since Aristotle, practically the entire Western tradition of philosophizing has accepted his contention that the ultimate human end is “happiness.” Now this could be understood as either exclusively, or with a strong stress on, individual or private happiness.
    [Show full text]
  • The End of Economics, Or, Is
    THE END OF ECONOMICS, OR, IS UTILITARIANISM FINISHED? By John D. Mueller James Madison Program Fellow Fellow of The Lehrman Institute President, LBMC LLC Princeton University, 127 Corwin Hall, 15 April 2002 Summary. According to Lionel Robbins’ classic definition, “Economics is the science which studies human behavior as a relationship between ends and scarce means that have alternate uses.” Yet most modern economists assume that economic choice involves only the means and not to the ends of human action. The reason seems to be that most modern economists are ignorant of the history of their own discipline before Adam Smith or Jeremy Bentham. Leading economists like Gary Becker attempt to explain all human behavior, including love and hate, as a maximization of “utility.” But historically and logically, an adequate description of economic choice has always required both a ranking of persons as ends and a ranking of scarce goods as means. What is missing from modern economics is an adequate description of the ranking of persons as ends. This is reflected in the absence of a satisfactory microeconomic explanation (for example, within the household) as to how goods are distributed to their final users, and in an overemphasis at the political level on an “individualistic social welfare function,” by which policymakers are purported to add up the preferences of a society of selfish individuals and determine all distribution from the government downwards, as if the nation or the world were one large household. As this “hole” in economic theory is recognized, an army of “neo-scholastic” economists will find full employment for the first few decades of the 21st Century, busily rewriting the Utilitarian “economic approach to human behavior” that dominated the last three decades of the 20th Century.
    [Show full text]
  • Immanuel Kant Was Born in 1724, and Published “Religion Within The
    CHAPTER FIVE THE PHENOMENOLOGY AND ‘FORMATIONS OF CONSCIOUSNESS’ It is this self-construing method alone which enables philosophy to be an objective, demonstrated science. (Hegel 1812) Immanuel Kant was born in 1724, and published “Religion within the limits of Reason” at the age of 70, at about the same time as the young Hegel was writing his speculations on building a folk religion at the seminary in Tübingen and Robespierre was engaged in his ultimately fatal practical experiment in a religion of Reason. Kant was a huge figure. Hegel and all his young philosopher friends were Kantians. But Kant’s system posed as many problems as it solved; to be a Kantian at that time was to be a participant in the project which Kant had initiated, the development of a philosophical system to fulfill the aims of the Enlightenment; and that generally meant critique of Kant. We need to look at just a couple of aspects of Kant’s philosophy which will help us understand Hegel’s approach. “I freely admit,” said Kant , “it was David Hume ’s remark [that Reason could not prove necessity or causality in Nature] that first, many years ago, interrupted my dogmatic slumber and gave a completely differ- ent direction to my enquiries in the field of speculative philosophy” (Kant 1997). Hume’s “Treatise on Human Nature” had been published while Kant was still very young, continuing a line of empiricists and their rationalist critics, whose concern was how knowledge and ideas originate from sensation. Hume was a skeptic; he demonstrated that causality could not be deduced from experience.
    [Show full text]
  • Code of Business Ethics and Conflict of Interest Policy for Directors, Officers and Employees ______
    [INSERT COMPANY NAME] Code Of Business Ethics And Conflict Of Interest Policy For Directors, Officers And Employees _________________________________ This Code of Ethics and Conflict of Interest Policy (the “Code”) for Directors, Officers and Employees as defined below (collectively, “Covered Persons”) is designed to maintain the standards of business conduct of [Insert Company Name], its subsidiaries and affiliates and their successors and assigns (collectively and severally, the “Company”), and to assure compliance with applicable law. The Company is committed to conducting its business in accordance with the highest ethical standards. It is the policy of the Company to conduct its business fairly, ethically and in compliance with applicable law. Accordingly, all conduct inconsistent with this Code is prohibited. This Code requires not only the avoidance of misconduct, but also the avoidance of acts or omissions that give the appearance of misconduct as well as reporting of misconduct. Covered Persons shall not enter into any activity or incur any expense or liability which would compromise the Company’s commitment to these high standards. Covered Persons are expected to read and understand this Code and uphold its standards day to day. This Code is designed to deter wrong-doing and to promote: 1. honest and ethical conduct, including the ethical handling of actual or apparent conflicts of interest between personal and professional relationships; 2. fair, full, accurate, timely and understandable disclosure in reports and documents that the Company files with the government and in other public communications made by the Company; 3. compliance with applicable law; 4. prompt internal reporting of violations of this Code; and 5.
    [Show full text]
  • (AAM) Code of Business Ethics
    ASSOCIATION FOR ACCESSIBLE MEDICINES Code of Business Ethics March 2018 Introduction Improving patient access to affordable medicines is a core value of companies that develop and manufacture generic and biosimilar medicines. Our companies produce and distribute the medicines that make up approximately 90% of all prescriptions filled in the United States – but at just 26% of total prescription drug spending. We serve as a key pillar in our national healthcare system. Our work includes promoting marketplace competition and supporting strategic enhancements to the Food and Drug Administration’s (FDA) generic drug and biosimilar approval process. We do this for one purpose: to put affordable medicines within the reach of patients who need them. Every dollar saved at the pharmacy counter is a dollar that patients can spend on life’s essentials and other pursuits — or put away for future use. We help patients live better lives, and we do so in a way that saves precious resources for patients, taxpayers, and our economy. Today we introduce the Association for Accessible Medicines (AAM) Code of Business Ethics. The practices discussed in this Code represent behaviors that our companies have been demonstrating for many years. And yet, it is incumbent on us to declare to our patients and customers the values upon which our industry is based, and the ethical and business standards upon which we are committed to operating with other members of the healthcare ecosystem. AAM endorses international principles of business ethics as set forth in this Code, including the Asia Pacific Economic Cooperation (APEC) Mexico City Principles on Voluntary Codes of Business Ethics in the Biopharmaceutical Sector.
    [Show full text]
  • Mohist Theoretic System: the Rivalry Theory of Confucianism and Interconnections with the Universal Values and Global Sustainability
    Cultural and Religious Studies, March 2020, Vol. 8, No. 3, 178-186 doi: 10.17265/2328-2177/2020.03.006 D DAVID PUBLISHING Mohist Theoretic System: The Rivalry Theory of Confucianism and Interconnections With the Universal Values and Global Sustainability SONG Jinzhou East China Normal University, Shanghai, China Mohism was established in the Warring State period for two centuries and half. It is the third biggest schools following Confucianism and Daoism. Mozi (468 B.C.-376 B.C.) was the first major intellectual rivalry to Confucianism and he was taken as the second biggest philosophy in his times. However, Mohism is seldom studied during more than 2,000 years from Han dynasty to the middle Qing dynasty due to his opposition claims to the dominant Confucian ideology. In this article, the author tries to illustrate the three potential functions of Mohism: First, the critical/revision function of dominant Confucianism ethics which has DNA functions of Chinese culture even in current China; second, the interconnections with the universal values of the world; third, the biological constructive function for global sustainability. Mohist had the fame of one of two well-known philosophers of his times, Confucian and Mohist. His ideas had a decisive influence upon the early Chinese thinkers while his visions of meritocracy and the public good helps shape the political philosophies and policy decisions till Qin and Han (202 B.C.-220 C.E.) dynasties. Sun Yet-sen (1902) adopted Mohist concepts “to take the world as one community” (tian xia wei gong) as the rationale of his democratic theory and he highly appraised Mohist concepts of equity and “impartial love” (jian ai).
    [Show full text]
  • 5. What Matters Is the Motive / Immanuel Kant
    This excerpt is from Michael J. Sandel, Justice: What's the Right Thing to Do?, pp. 103-116, by permission of the publisher. 5. WHAT MATTERS IS THE MOTIVE / IMMANUEL KANT If you believe in universal human rights, you are probably not a utili- tarian. If all human beings are worthy of respect, regardless of who they are or where they live, then it’s wrong to treat them as mere in- struments of the collective happiness. (Recall the story of the mal- nourished child languishing in the cellar for the sake of the “city of happiness.”) You might defend human rights on the grounds that respecting them will maximize utility in the long run. In that case, however, your reason for respecting rights is not to respect the person who holds them but to make things better for everyone. It is one thing to con- demn the scenario of the su! ering child because it reduces overall util- ity, and something else to condemn it as an intrinsic moral wrong, an injustice to the child. If rights don’t rest on utility, what is their moral basis? Libertarians o! er a possible answer: Persons should not be used merely as means to the welfare of others, because doing so violates the fundamental right of self-ownership. My life, labor, and person belong to me and me alone. They are not at the disposal of the society as a whole. As we have seen, however, the idea of self-ownership, consistently applied, has implications that only an ardent libertarian can love—an unfettered market without a safety net for those who fall behind; a 104 JUSTICE minimal state that rules out most mea sures to ease inequality and pro- mote the common good; and a celebration of consent so complete that it permits self-in" icted a! ronts to human dignity such as consensual cannibalism or selling oneself into slav ery.
    [Show full text]
  • Art of Judging
    NEW YORK UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW VOLUME 71 JUNE 1996 NUMBER 3 THE ART OF JUDGING STEWART G. POLLOCK* In the second annual William J. Brennan, Jr. Lectur4 New Jersey Supreme Court Justice Stewart G. Pollock explores the relationship between art and adjudication. The separationof powers, the federalist system, and the inherent constraints of the common law confine state courts. Notwithstanding those constraints,state courts have demonstrated creativity when interpretingstate statutes and constitutionsand when adapting the common law to changing conditions. Thus, Justice Pollock fnds artistry in the work of state courts. He begins by exploring creativity in statu- tory interpretation. Then, Justice Pollock examines two areasof substantive law of greatpublic concern: public-school-financelitigation under state constitutions and the common-law redefinition of the modem family. Justice Pollock demonstrates how state appellate courts, through public-school-finance litigation, have shaped the constitutionalright to a public-school education. Justice Pollock then discusses how state courts have reacted to the changing composition of the American family. By recognizing these changes, state courts have redefined the family in areas as diverse as zoning ordinances, surrogacy agreements, and same-sex marriages. Common to all these endeavors is protection of the inherent dignity of the individ- ual Justice Pollock concludes that an appreciationof the similarities between art and judging may lead to a better understandingof the judicial process. Delivering the Brennan Lecture in Vanderbilt Hall is for me deeply moving. Justice Brennan graced the New Jersey Supreme Court for four years before starting his remarkable service on the United States Supreme Court. Also, this building is named for the former dean of this law school and the Chief Justice of the New Jersey Supreme Court with whom Justice Brennan served, Arthur T.
    [Show full text]