The Critique of Instrumental Reason: Horkheimer, Marcuse And

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Critique of Instrumental Reason: Horkheimer, Marcuse And Reason after Its Eclipse Jay, Martin Published by University of Wisconsin Press Jay, M.. Reason after Its Eclipse: On Late Critical Theory. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 2016. Project MUSE., https://muse.jhu.edu/. For additional information about this book https://muse.jhu.edu/book/44706 Access provided by University of California @ Berkeley (30 Jan 2017 19:16 GMT) UWP: Jay: Reason after Its Eclipse page97 5 The Critique of Instrumental Reason Horkheimer, Marcuse, and Adorno In 1941, arguably one of the bleakest years in all of modern history, the Frankfurt School reluctantly acknowledged for the first time the crisis of the emphatic concept of reason that had been a mainstay of its work for much of the previous decade.1 The disillusionment was abrupt. Although in his earliest days Max Horkheimer had in good historical materialist fashion denounced the dualism and idealism he saw in Cartesian rationalist metaphysics, he had come staunchly to defend a dialectical notion of reason against the irrationalist alterna- tive he identified with the threat of fascism.2 While acknowledging that ratio- nality in its liberal, bourgeois form was tied to egoistic self-preservation rather than the general good, he had resisted the conclusion that reason tout court inevi- tably led in this direction. As a result, one commentator has gone so far as to posit a “rationalist turn” in Critical Theory around 1937 in which concrete political hopes were replaced by more philosophical concerns.3 In an essay of that year, “The Latest Attack on Metaphysics,” Horkheimer could still insist, as noted at the end of the previous chapter, that “rationalism uses existing objects as well as the active inner strivings and ideas of man to construct standards for the future. In this regard it is not so closely associated with the present order as is empiricism.”4 In the same year, Herbert Marcuse could add in the pages of the Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung: Reason is the fundamental category of philosophical thought, the only one by means of which it has bound itself to human destiny. Philosophy wanted to discover the ultimate and most general grounds of Being. Under 97 UWP: Jay: Reason after Its Eclipse page98 98 Part II. Reason’s Eclipse and Return the name of reason it conceived the idea of authentic Being in which all significant antitheses (of subject and object, essence and appearance, thought and being) were reconciled.5 Four years later, Marcuse’s spirited defense of Hegel against his alleged support for statist authoritarianism, Reason and Revolution, could even more vigorously celebrate the critical energy of universal reason. In its dialectical guise, which emphasized the power of negation, reason had resisted the affirma- tive implications of positivism in all of its forms. Going beyond the limits of the analytic understanding (Verstand ) that Kant had posited for cognition, reason (Vernunft ) was a synthetic faculty able to incorporate the moral norms Kant had relegated to practical reason alone. According to Marcuse, Hegel’s idea of reason, with which he clearly identified, “has retained, though in an idealistic form, the material strivings for a free and rational order of life. The core of Hegel’s philosophy is a structure the concepts of which—freedom, subject, mind, notion—are derived from the idea of reason.”6 Capitalist rationalization, tied to commodity fetishism, the domination of exchange value, and what Lukács had called reification, was a pathological distortion of this ideal. As Marx had famously said in 1843, “reason has always existed, but not always in rational form.”7 Despite sub rosa tensions between Marcuse and some of his colleagues at the time, the book was proudly dedicated to “Max Horkheimer and the Institute of Social Research,”8 whose theoretical stance he thought he shared. But in a new essay of 1941 by Horkheimer, “Reason and Self-Preservation,” which first appeared in a private volume to mourn the recently perished Walter Benjamin, a very different note was struck. When it appeared in the final issue of the Institute’s journal, which coincided with Horkheimer’s move from New York to California and the growing importance of his partnership with Adorno, it was retitled in more apocalyptic fashion “The End of Reason.”9 “The funda- mental concepts of civilization are in a process of rapid decay,” Horkheimer began ominously. “The decisive concept among them was that of reason, and philosophy knew no higher principle.”10 The decay of reason, Horkheimer then suggested, was due not only to the failure to realize itself in the world but also to a fatal characteristic of the concept itself. Ironically, the inherent connec- tion between reason and critique could ultimately be carried to the point that reason might undermine its own legitimacy. “Rationalism itself had established the criteria of rigidity, clarity and distinctness as the criteria of rational cognition. Skeptical and empirical doctrines opposed rationalism with these selfsame standards. Skepticism purged the idea of reason of so much of its content that scarcely anything is left of it. Reason, in destroying conceptual fetishes, ulti- mately destroyed itself. None of the categories of rationalism has survived.”11 UWP: Jay: Reason after Its Eclipse page99 The Critique of Instrumental Reason 99 There is a withered residue of reason still left in human behavior, Hork- heimer conceded, but only in its instrumental guise: “its features can be summa- rized as the optimum adaptation of means to ends, thinking as an energy-saving operation. It is a pragmatic instrument oriented to expediency, cold and sober.”12 Was this an aberration or the working out of a sinister potential always lurking in reason? Marcuse had been inclined to blame it on the increased power of technological rationality in the modern world.13 But Horkheimer, at his most pessimistic, asserted that “as close as the bond between reason and efficiency is here revealed to be, in reality so has it always been.”14 To the extent that reason claimed universal, ahistorical validity, it was based, moreover, on a lie, because all previous societies were divided along class lines. As the universality of reason became more frankly formalistic, it resigned itself to the separation of thought and object, the ideal of universality betrayed by the reality of class division. The increasing influence of nominalism, which meant the loss of any hope for a substantive concept of reason as inhering in the actual world, also ratified the separation of facts from values and the hegemony of calculation. “The triumph of nominalism goes hand in hand with the triumph of formalism. In limiting itself to seeing objects as a strange multiplicity, as a chaos, reason becomes a kind of adding machine that manipulates analytical judgments.”15 Along with this decline of reason into the instrumentality that was always lurking under the surface of the substantive concept went a concomitant ero- sion of the individual subject who was supposed to be its bearer. Although in the past a dialectic of self-preservation and self-sacrifice meant that there was some rough balance between individual and community, now the former was in total disarray: The destruction of rationalistic dogmatism through the self-critique of reason, carried out by the ever renewed nominalistic tendencies in philoso- phy, has now been ratified by historical reality. The substance of individual- ity itself, to which the idea of autonomy was bound, did not survive the process of industrialization. Reason has degenerated because it was the ideological projection of a false universality which now shows the autonomy of the subject to have been an illusion. The collapse of reason and the collapse of individuality are one and the same.16 The result is the political horror that was now sweeping over Europe, which must be understood as more than an expression of atavistic irrationalism: “the new order of fascism is reason revealing itself as unreason.”17 Holding on to a faint hope that fascism might not have the last word, Horkheimer concluded his jeremiad with a modified evocation of the famous alternative Rosa Luxemburg UWP: Jay: Reason after Its Eclipse page100 100 Part II. Reason’s Eclipse and Return had posed in her World War I Junius Pamphlet: “the progress of reason that leads to its self-destruction has come to an end; there is nothing left but barbarism or freedom.”18 Throughout the 1940s, Horkheimer still desperately attempted to salvage something from the wreckage of reason. But even the end of the war and defeat of fascism did not lessen his dire conclusion in 1946 that reason itself “today seems to suffer from a kind of disease,” the cure of which is uncertain.19 Only digging deep into its past might provide some potential relief: “reason must reconstruct the history of its vicissitudes—try, as it were to recollect its origins and understand its own inherent self-destructive trends and mechanisms. Reason’s ability to render an account of its transformation from the power by which all things are perceived, to a mere instrumentality of self-preservation, is a condition of its recovery.”20 Only by facing the sources of the “self-liquidation of reason” can the process of enlightenment continue, a process, despite its paradoxical implications, needing to be encouraged: “the hope of Reason lies in the emancipation from its own fear of despair.”21 Struggling against that fear while at the same time not flinching from the despair were the motivations behind Horkheimer’s two subsequent works, Eclipse of Reason (1947) and Dialectic of Enlightenment, the latter of which he wrote jointly with Adorno (1947). Together, they represented the summa of the Frankfurt School’s thesis of the self-liquidation of reason.
Recommended publications
  • The Concept of the Global Subject in Adorno
    University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Major Papers Theses, Dissertations, and Major Papers November 2019 The Concept of The Global Subject In Adorno Sebastian Kanally [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/major-papers Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, and the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Kanally, Sebastian, "The Concept of The Global Subject In Adorno" (2019). Major Papers. 99. https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/major-papers/99 This Major Research Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses, Dissertations, and Major Papers at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in Major Papers by an authorized administrator of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Concept of The Global Subject in Adorno By Sebastian Kanally A Major Research Paper Submitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies through the Department of Philosophy in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts at the University of Windsor Windsor, Ontario, Canada 2019 © 2019 Sebastian Kanally The Concept of the Global Subject in Adorno by Sebastian Kanally APPROVED BY: ______________________________________________ J. Noonan Department of Philosophy ______________________________________________ D. Cook, Advisor Department of Philosophy August 30, 2019 DECLARATION OF ORIGINALITY I hereby certify that I am the sole author of this thesis and that no part of this thesis has been published or submitted for publication. I certify that, to the best of my knowledge, my thesis does not infringe upon anyone’s copyright nor violate any proprietary rights and that any ideas, techniques, quotations, or any other material from the work of other people included in my thesis, published or otherwise, are fully acknowledged in accordance with the standard referencing practices.
    [Show full text]
  • Critical Theory of Herbert Marcuse: an Inquiry Into the Possibility of Human Happiness
    University of Montana ScholarWorks at University of Montana Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers Graduate School 1986 Critical theory of Herbert Marcuse: An inquiry into the possibility of human happiness Michael W. Dahlem The University of Montana Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Dahlem, Michael W., "Critical theory of Herbert Marcuse: An inquiry into the possibility of human happiness" (1986). Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers. 5620. https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd/5620 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at ScholarWorks at University of Montana. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks at University of Montana. For more information, please contact [email protected]. COPYRIGHT ACT OF 1976 This is an unpublished manuscript in which copyright sub­ s is t s, Any further reprinting of its contents must be approved BY THE AUTHOR, Mansfield Library U n iv e rs ity o f Montana Date :_____1. 9 g jS.__ THE CRITICAL THEORY OF HERBERT MARCUSE: AN INQUIRY INTO THE POSSIBILITY OF HUMAN HAPPINESS By Michael W. Dahlem B.A. Iowa State University, 1975 Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts University of Montana 1986 Approved by Chairman, Board of Examiners Date UMI Number: EP41084 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted.
    [Show full text]
  • POL 478Y (POL2019Y5Y L0101) (Autumn 2016) MORAL REASON
    POL 478Y (POL2019Y5Y L0101) (Autumn 2016) MORAL REASON AND ECONOMIC HISTORY Professor R.B. Day 229 Kaneff Centre (905) 828-5203 Office Hours: Thursday 3-5 email: [email protected] Course website: www.richardbday.com SECTION I: POLITICAL ECONOMY AND ETHICAL LIFE 1) 6 September – Course Outline and Grading 2) 7 September – Plato and Aristotle: Justice and Economy, the Ethical Whole and the Parts *K. Polanyi, “Aristotle Discovers the Economy” in G. Dalton (ed), Primitive, Archaic and Modern Economies: Essays of Karl Polanyi, ch. 5; also in Polanyi, Arensberg & Pearson (eds), Trade and Market in the Early Empires, pp. 64-94 Aristotle, The Politics Plato, The Republic J.J. Spengler, Origins of Economic Thought and Justice, ch. 5 E. Barker, Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle, chs. 3-4, 6-9 J. Barnes (ed), Cambridge Companion to Aristotle, chs. 7-8 S. Meikle, Aristotle’s Economic Thought 3) 13 September – Augustine, Aquinas, Calvin: “Embedded Consciousness,” Spiritual Community & the “Spirit of Capitalism” *Polanyi, “Obsolete Market Mentality,” in Dalton (ed), Primitive, Archaic and Modern Economies *Weber, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism K. Samuelsson, Religion and Economic Action P.E. Sigmund (ed), St. Thomas Aquinas on Politics and Ethics R.H. Tawney, Religion and the Rise of Capitalism E.L. Fortin, "St. Thomas Aquinas" and “St. Augustine” in L. Strauss & J. Cropsey (eds), History of Political Philosophy A, Kuyper, Lectures on Calvinism: The Stone Foundation Lectures Andre Bieler, Calvin’s Economic and Social Thought 4) 14 September – Adam Smith: Individual Moral Judgment and Macro-Economic Growth *J. Cropsey, “Adam Smith,” in L.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Collected Papers of Herbert Marcuse, Volume 3: the New Left
    Collected Papers of Herbert Marcuse, Volume 3: The New Left and the 1960s Edited by Douglas Kellner Introduction by Douglas Kellner Preface by Angela Davis I. Interventions: “The Inner Logic of American Policy in Vietnam," 1967; “Reflections on the French Revolution,” 1968; “Student Protest is Nonviolent Next to the Society Itself”; “Charles Reich as Revolutionary Ostrich,” 1970; “Dear Angela,” 1971; “Reflections on Calley,” 1971; and “Marcuse: Israel strong enough to concede,” 1971 II. “The Problem of Violence and the Radical Opposition” III. "Liberation from the Affluent Society" IV. "Democracy Has/Hasn't a Future...A present" V. "Marcuse Defines His New Left Line" VI. Testimonies: Herbert Marcuse on Czechoslovakia and Vietnam; the University of California at San Diego Department of Philosophy on Herbert Marcuse; T.W. Adorno on Herbert Marcuse. VII. "On the New Left" VIII. “Mr. Harold Keen: Interview with Dr. Herbert Marcuse” IX. "USA: Questions of Organization and Revolutionary Subject: A Conversation with Hans-Magnus Enzensberger" X. "The Movement in an Era of Repression" XI. "A Conversation with Herbert Marcuse: Bill Moyers" XII. “Marxism and Feminism” XIII. 1970s Interventions: "Ecology and Revolution”; “Murder is Not a Political Weapon”; “Thoughts on Judaism, Israel, etc…” XIV. "Failure of the New Left?" Afterword by George Katsiaficas, “Marcuse as an Activist: Reminiscences of his Theory and Practice“ 1 Radical Politics, Marcuse, and the New Left Douglas Kellner In the 1960s Herbert Marcuse was promoted to the unlikely role of
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel: Three Studies I Theodor W
    Hegel Three Studies · I Hegel Three Studies Theodor W. Adorno. translated by Shierry Weber Nicholsen with an introduction by Shierry Weber Nicholsen and Jeremy]. Shapiro \\Imi\�\\�\i\il\"t�m .� . 39001101483082 The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, and London, England ·" '.�. This edition © 1993 Massachusetts Institute of Technology This work originally appeared in German under the title Drei Studien zu Hegel, © 1963, 1971 Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt am Main, Germany. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any fo rm or by any electronic or mechanical means (including photocopying, recording, or information storage and retrieval) without permission in writing from the publisher. This book was set in Baskerville by The Maple-Vail Book Manufacturing Group and was printed and bound in the United States of America. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Adorno, Theodor W., 1903-1969. [Drei Studien zu Hegel. English] Hegel: three studies I Theodor W. Adorno ; translated by Shierry Weber Nicholsen ; with an introduction by Shierry Weber Nicholsen and Jeremy J. Shapiro. p. cm.-(Studies in contemporary German social thought) Translation of: Drei Studien zu Hegel. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-262-01131-X 1. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 1770- 1831. 1. Title. 11. Series. B2948.A3213 1993 193----dc20 92-23161 CIP ..�. •. , ......... ..,..·...",...,..'''_''e ... • 11�. I },i . :-::" 7.�� <,f,' · '�: · : :-:- ;;· �:<" For Karl Heinz Haag 337389 Contents Introduction by Shierry Weber Nicholsen and IX Jeremy J. Shapiro Preface XXXv A Note on the Text xxxvii Editorial Remarks from the German Edition XXXIX Aspects of Hegel's Philosophy 1 The Experiential Content of Hegel's Philosophy 53 Skoteinos, or How to Read Hegel 89 Notes 149 Name Index 159 Introduction Shierry Weber Nicholsen Jeremy J.
    [Show full text]
  • Reason-And-Revolution.Pdf
    Reason and Revolution HEGEL AND THE RISE OF SOCIAL THEORY HERBERT MARCUSE 2nd Edition with Supplementary Chapter LONDON ROUTLEDGE & KEGAN PAUL LTD BROADWAY HOUSE: te-74 CARTER LANE, E.C.4 Preface > ) ceo c- THE content of a truly philosophical work does not remain unchanged with time. If its concepts have an essential bearing upon the aims and interests of men, a fundamental change in the historical situation will make them see its teachings in a new light. In our time, the rise of Fascism calls for a reinterpretation of Hegel's philosophy. We hope that the analysis offered here will demonstrate that Hegel's basic concepts are hostile to the tendencies that have led into Fascist theory and practice. We have devoted the first part of the book to a survey of the structure of Hegel's system. At the same time, we have tried to go beyond mere restatement and to elucidate those implications of Hegel's ideas that identify them closely with the later developments in European thought, particularly with the Marxian theory. Hegel's critical and rational standards, and especially his dialectics, had to come into conflict with the prevailing social reality. For this reason, his system could well be called a negative philosophy, the name given to it by its contemporary opponents. To counteract its destructive tendencies, there arose, in the decade following Hegel's death, a positive philosophy which undertook to subordi- nate reason to the authority of established fact. The strug- gle that developed between the negative and positive philosophy offers, as we haVe attempted to show in the second part of this book, many clues for understanding the rise of modern social theory in Europe.
    [Show full text]
  • Jürgen Habermas and Carl Schmitt in the Paradigm of Modernity for a Critique of the Modern Law
    UNIVERSIDADE DE BRASÍLIA – FACULDADE DE DIREITO PROGRAMA DE PÓS-GRADUAÇÃO EM DIREITO – DOUTORADO ÁREA DE CONCENTRAÇÃO: CONSTITUIÇÃO E DEMOCRACIA Jürgen Habermas and Carl Schmitt in the paradigm of modernity For a critique of the modern law Orientador: Prof. Dr. Miroslav Milović Vanja Grujić Brasília, Setembro 2017 Dedicatória Gostaria de expressar a minha sincera gratidão à Universidade Nacional de Brasília e à Faculdade de Direito por me dar a honra e a oportunidade para defender a minha tese aqui. Também queria expressar minha apreciação ao meu professor Prof. Dr. Miroslav Milović. Você tem sido um inspirador mentor para mim. Gostaria de agradecer-lhe por encorajar minha pesquisa e por me permitir crescer na esfera acadêmica. Gostaria também de agradecer aos meus membros da comissão, a professora Rochelle Cysne Frota D'Abreu, ao professor Marcelo da Costa Pinto Neves, ao professor Paulo César Nascimento, e ao professor Juliano Zaiden Benvindo por servir como membros do meu comitê, mesmo em dificuldades. Além disso, gostaria de expressar o agradecimento aos funcionários da secretaria de pós-graduação da Faculdade de Direito por me ajudar sempre que necessário. Também, gostaria de agradecer a CAPES (Coordenação de Aperfeiçoamento de Pessoal de Nível Superior) para o financiamento do meu doutorado no Brasil, e para a oportunidade de fazer parte do programa doutorado sanduíche no exterior. Sem essas bolsas, meus estudos de doutorado não seriam possíveis. Sincera gratidão a todos os colegas e professores da Faculdade de Direito em Brasília. Ouvir suas ideias e comentários foi uma experiência incrível e aprendi muito com vocês. Por último, mas não menos importante, agradeço aos professores e colegas da ZERP (Zentrum für Europäische Rechtspolitik der Universität Bremen) por seus frutíferos comentários, palavras de encorajamento e amizade que certamente deixaram uma marca importante no meu trabalho.
    [Show full text]
  • Theodor W. Adorno: with Hegel Against Capitalism
    Theodor W. Adorno: With Hegel Against Capitalism Anders Bartonek How and why does Theodor W. Adorno use the philosophy of Hegel in order to strengthen his Marxist theory and its perspective? This is the ques- tion that this essay will try to answer. Against the background of an outline of Adorno’s thinking, as far as it is Marxist, the purpose is to reconstruct in what way he is using essential aspects and concepts of Hegel’s thinking in order to develop his own philosophical contribution to Marxism. The main thesis, which will be constructed around Adorno’s ambivalence towards Hegel, is that Adorno uses his own critique against Hegel’s system of iden- tity in his critique of the principle of capitalism, and that, when doing this, Adorno harnesses his adapted version of Hegel’s notion of non-identity as a critical tool against both Hegel’s identity system and the system of capi- talism. This means that, with help from Hegel, Adorno secures a possibility of criticizing Hegel and capitalism (as well as Marx’s own tendency toward closure), doing so from a Marxist and system-critical perspective. In quite different ways, the philosophies of Hegel and Marx play a crucial role for the Western Marxism of the Frankfurt School, of which Adorno is one of the most prominent members.1 Marx’s thinking was a cornerstone already when the institute was founded by Felix Weil,2 that is, at an earlier stage than when the now most famous members joined. For Max Hork- heimer, who became the head of the institute in 1930, Marx played a sig- nificant role in the formation of a critical theory that avoided becoming a scientific theory adequate to and the preserve of modern capitalist society.
    [Show full text]
  • “Life”: Max Horkheimer and Herbert Marcuse's Reception Of
    Enrahonar. An International Journal of Theoretical and Practical Reason 62, 2019 39-58 The vicissitudes of the politics of “life”: Max Horkheimer and Herbert Marcuse’s reception of phenomenology and vitalism in Weimar Germany John Abromeit State University of New York, Buffalo State [email protected] Reception date: 23-5-2018 Acceptance date: 13-12-2018 Abstract The following article attempts to clarify the ambivalent relationship that Max Horkheimer and Herbert Marcuse developed with the vitalist and phenomenological tendencies that permeated philosophy and the social sciences during the Weimar Republic. More precise- ly, it traces how both thinkers, in spite of acknowledging the “truth moment” contained in the criticism that the philosophical exponents of both movements (Husserl, Bergson, Dilthey) developed of 19th century positivism, also recognized in its shallow populari- zation the advancement of a dangerous philosophical irrationalism, suspicious of science and Enlightenment values, that would soon become an accomplice to the rise of fascism. Keywords: Frankfurt school; critical theory; irrationalism; conservative revolution Resum. Les vicissituds de la política de la «vida»: la recepció de Max Horkheimer i Herbert Marcuse de la fenomenologia i el vitalisme en l’Alemanya de Weimar L’article següent s’ocupa d’aclarir la relació ambivalent que Max Horkheimer i Herbert Marcuse van desenvolupar amb les tendències vitalista i fenomenològica que van permear la filosofia i les ciències socials durant la república de Weimar. Més precisament, documenta com ambdós pensadors, alhora que van reconèixer el «moment de veritat» latent en la crítica al positivisme del segle xix, expressat pels referents genuïnament filosòfics dels dos moviments (Husserl, Bersong, Dilthey), van detectar el desenvolupament popularitzant d’un perillós irracionalisme filosòfic, suspicaç davant la ciència i els valors il·lustrats, que aviat va esdevenir còmplice de l’auge del totalitarisme.
    [Show full text]
  • Danilo S. Alterado, Philosophia
    110 BOOK REVIEW Φιλοσοφια Volume 16, 1:2015 BOOK REVIEW Kevin B. Anderson and Russell Rockwell, eds. Dunayevskaya-Marcuse-Fromm correspondence, 1954-1978: Dialogues on Hegel, Marx and Critical Theory New York: Lexington Books, 2012, 269 pages Critical Theory as a philosophical orientation has provided a radical stimulus to a contemporary generation of thinkers by combining the Hegelian and Marxian dialectical methods with Marx’s critique of ideology. This has given rise to a distinctively powerful lens of social analysis for the project of emancipation in the multifarious issues of power struggle, ideology, language, discourse, technology, instrumental reason, aesthetic industry, etc. in social, economic, political, and cultural spheres of contemporary society. The revolutionary insights of Hegel and Marx in Critical Theory, however, do not imply a closed system of thought among its practitioners; in fact, at times, it has been discordant, however vibrant. In this collection of correspondence, for instance, Marcuse disagrees with Dunayevskaya on the latter’s interpretation and application of Hegel’s dialectics and absolute idea/mind, while Fromm accused Marcuse of callousness towards moral qualities in political figures similar to that of Lenin (xviii), and Marcuse likewise attacked Fromm on his Freudian revisionism and liberalism regarding interpretations on Freudian psychoanalysis vis-à-vis Marxist social analysis. References to the disagreements between the Frankfurt School’s intellectual leaders Max Horkheimer and Theodor Adorno with Herbert Marcuse (xvii), on the one hand, and with Erich Fromm (xix), on the other hand, were also alluded to. Nonetheless, by and through persistent critical dialogue and exchange—truly a real practice of dialectics—the critical theorists in different perspectives of the Marxist-Humanist, Hegelian-Marxist, and Socialist Humanist standpoints, have preserved and has brought to greater heights.
    [Show full text]
  • Karl Marx's Political Epistemology James Martin Mclvor
    Karl Marx’s Political Epistemology Subjectivity, abstraction and the state in the writings o f the early 1840s James Martin Mclvor Government Department London School of Economics and Political Science University of London Submitted for Examination for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy, University of London. March 2004 1 UMI Number: U615251 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Dissertation Publishing UMI U615251 Published by ProQuest LLC 2014. Copyright in the Dissertation held by the Author. Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code. ProQuest LLC 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346 Th£S £S F Abstract This study of Karl Marx’s pre-1844 writings argues that the crucial link between his ‘mature’ social theory and preceding philosophical traditions lies in the elaboration in these early texts of what is here termed a ‘political epistemology’. This can be summarised as a critique of laws and social institutions which treats them as human beings’ operative conceptualisations of their practical interdependence. It is on the basis of this implicit equation that Marx transposes the terms of German Idealist investigations of consciousness and knowledge into an original analysis of political power and social conflict The historical and philosophical background to this idea of a ‘political epistemology’ is sketched through a consideration of the neo-Scholastic rationalism of the eighteenth century, the critical idealism of Kant, and the post-Kantian idealism of Fichte, Schelling and Hegel.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy of Praxis: Marx, Lukács and the Frankfurt School
    The Philosophy of Praxis: Marx, Lukács and the Frankfurt School Andrew Feenberg In 1844, Marx wrote that “Philosophy can only be realized by the abolition of the proletariat, and the proletariat can only be abolished by the realization of philosophy” (Marx, 1963: 59). Adorno later commented, “Philosophy, which once seemed obsolete, lives on because the moment to realize it was missed” (Adorno, 1973: 3). What is the meaning of this strange concept of a “realization” of philosophy? The purpose of this talk is to sketch an answer to this question which is more fully developed in my forthcoming book, entitled The Philosophy of Praxis: Marx, Lukács, and the Frankfurt School. Gramsci used the phrase “philosophy of praxis” as a code word for Marxism in his Prison Notebooks. It has come to signify interpretations of Marxism that follow his lead in situating all knowledge in a cultural context, itself based on a class specific worldview. Gramsci called this “absolute historicism.” It characterizes the Hegelian Marxism of Marx’s early work, Lukács, Korsch, Bloch, and the Frankfurt School. I will refer to this trend as philosophy of praxis to distinguish it from other interpretations of Marxism. The philosophy of praxis holds that fundamental philosophical problems are in reality social contradictions abstractly conceived. These contradictions appear as practical problems without solutions, reflected in cultural dilemmas. Philosophy treats them as theoretical antinomies, insoluble conundrums over which the thinkers struggle without reaching a convincing solution or consensus. They include the antinomies of value and fact, freedom and necessity, individual and society and, ultimately, subject and object.
    [Show full text]