The Limits of Social Norms

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Limits of Social Norms Chicago-Kent Law Review Volume 74 Issue 4 Symposium on Law, Psychology, and Article 6 the Emotions October 1999 The Limits of Social Norms Jeffrey J. Rachlinski Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.kentlaw.iit.edu/cklawreview Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Jeffrey J. Rachlinski, The Limits of Social Norms, 74 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 1537 (2000). Available at: https://scholarship.kentlaw.iit.edu/cklawreview/vol74/iss4/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarly Commons @ IIT Chicago-Kent College of Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Chicago-Kent Law Review by an authorized editor of Scholarly Commons @ IIT Chicago-Kent College of Law. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. THE LIMITS OF SOCIAL NORMS JEFFREY J. RACHLINSKI* No society can function if it cannot constrain the self-serving behavior of its members. Societies that cannot control socially destructive behavior collapse into dysfunction; they become dangerously crime-ridden, as in some of America's inner cities, or completely anarchic, as in parts of the Balkans and central Africa.' Clear rules enforced by legal sanctions deter a great deal of socially destructive conduct, but social norms enforced by informal sanctions might create even more powerful constraints. 2 If so, then gaining control over dysfunctional societies might depend more upon using or manipulating social norms than upon enforcing the law. Decades of research conducted by social psychologists on social norms, however, suggests three important obstacles to the use of social norms: First, antisocial norms, once established, are hard to dislodge; second, even if people adhere to positive social norms, determining when they are triggered is difficult; third, subtle aspects of situations can induce antisocial conduct, seemingly even against social norms. Most legal scholarship addressing the control of antisocial behavior addresses formal sanctions rather than social norms.3 This is not surprising; formal sanctions are more familiar to lawyers and punishing undesirable antisocial conduct is the most straightforward means of maintaining social order. Formal sanctions almost certainly provide a critical degree of control over antisocial conduct, but they are costly, both to society and to the individual being punished. 4 Incarceration, in particular, can produce unintended costs to * Professor of Law, Cornell Law School. Ph.D., Psychology, Stanford University, 1994; J.D., Stanford University, 1993; B.A., The Johns Hopkins University, 1988; M.A., Psychology, The Johns Hopkins University, 1988. I thank Chris Guthrie and Emily Sherwin for their helpful comments on this paper. 1. See Tracey L. Meares & Dan M. Kahan, Law and (Norms of) Order in the Inner City, 32 L. & Soc'Y. REv. 805, 812-13 (1998). 2. See generally Dan M. Kahan, Social Meaning and the Economic Analysis of Crime, 27 J. LEGAL STUD. 609 (1998). 3. See Robert C. Ellickson, Law and Economics Discovers Social Norms, 27 J. LEGAL STUD. 537, 542-43 (1998). 4. See John J. Donohue III & Peter Siegelman, Allocating Resources Among Prisonsand Social Programs in the Battle Against Crime, 27 J. LEGAL STUD. 1,3-6 (1998). CHICAGO-KENT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 74:1537 individuals, especially in communities in which the rate of incarceration is high.5 Partly in response to the staggering costs of incarceration, some legal scholars argue that informal social norms provide a better means of controlling antisocial conduct. 6 This observation builds upon a growing body of legal scholarship concerning social norms.7 This new "law and social norms" scholarship adopts a more subtle approach to social behavior than identifying situations that should trigger formal rewards and sanctions. It accounts for the prominence of group membership and social approval as sources of rewards and punishments. 8 This new field has developed several positive and normative implications of social norms. On the positive side, the scholarship asserts that groups develop and enforce norms of conduct apart from formal legal sanctions.9 Perhaps more significantly, this scholarship might hold valuable normative lessons for policymakers interested in reducing crime as an alternative to incarceration. The law and social norms scholarship identifies two ways in which reformers can take advantage of the power of social norms. First, changes in law can influence social norms. For example, passing a law against smoking in public places had a dramatic effect on smokers, not because of the formal penalty for public smoking (which is hardly ever imposed) but because it empowered nonsmokers to levy social sanctions on smokers.1 Changes in law might also inspire changes in preferences. 1 Scholars refer to this as the "expressive" 5. See Meares & Kahan, supra note 1, at 813. 6. See generally Dan M. Kahan, Social Influence, Social Meaning, and Deterrence, 83 VA. L. REV. 349 (1997); Meares & Kahan, supra note 1, at 812. 7. See, e.g., Lawrence Lessig, The Regulation of Social Meaning, 62 U. CHI. L. REV. 943 (1995); Richard H. McAdams, The Origin,Development, and Regulation of Norms, 96 MICH. L. REV. 338 (1997); Richard A. Posner, Social Norms and the Law: An Economic Approach, 87 AM. ECON. REV. 365 (1997); Eric A. Posner, The Regulation of Groups: The Influence of Legal and Non-Legal Sanctions on Collective Action, 63 U. CHI. L. REV. 133 (1996); Cass R. Sunstein, Social Norms and Social Roles, 96 COLUM. L. REV. 903 (1996). Owing to the number of scholars at the University of Chicago doing this work, some have referred to it as the "New Chicago School." See, e.g., Lawrence Lessig, The New Chicago School, 27 J. LEGAL STUD. 661 (1998). 8. See McAdams, supra note 7, at 341-42. 9. See generally ROBERT C. ELLICKSON, ORDER WiTHouT LAW: How NEIGHBORS SETrLE DISPuTEs (1991); Lisa Bernstein, Opting Out of the Legal System: Extralegal ContractualRelations in the Diamond Industry, 21 J. LEGAL STUD. 115 (1992); Eric A. Posner, supra note 7, at 137-44. 10. See Robert Cooter, Expressive Law and Economics, 27 J. LEGAL STUD. 585, 594-95 (1998). 11. See Cass R. Sunstein, Endogenous Preferences, EnvironmentalLaw, 22 J. LEGAL STUD. 217, 230-34 (1993). 2000] THE LIMITS OF SOCIAL NORMS function of law.12 Second, subtle and inexpensive changes in a social setting can signal different social norms. For example, fixing broken windows, cleaning up trash, erasing graffiti, and planting flowers in a neighborhood can have a dramatic effect on crime rates because tidiness can "signal" a community's intolerance for lawbreaking. 3 The interaction between law and social norms arguably identifies ways to reduce crime that are less expensive and more humane than traditional approaches. A change in law that does not need to be enforced, or is only minimally enforced, is not costly to society or to the individuals who are deterred from breaking the law by a new social taboo. Likewise, cleaning neighborhoods is much more humane than identifying and sentencing lawbreakers to lengthy periods of incarceration. Historically, those who have argued against incarceration have advocated social programs designed to fight poverty as a substitute crime control measure. 14 Such programs are expensive, and do not always succeed, or generate other unwanted consequences. The law and social norms scholarship suggests novel alternatives to the choice between expensive social programs and incarceration. Manipulating social norms to reduce antisocial conduct will only be a successful strategy if the underlying theories describing how social norms affect behavior are both accurate and reasonably complete. Although the law and social norms scholarship relies largely on observational and anecdotal support, it presents a good case that social norms influence behavior in ways that policymakers can use. The diamond industry is probably governed by the informal norms Professor Bernstein identifies, 5 sprucing up a community probably reduces crime as Professor Kahan argues,'16 and changes in the law probably affects people's perception of conduct such as dueling and wearing hockey helmets. 7 If the theories explaining these phenomena are incomplete, however, then the law and social norms scholarship is merely a post hoc effort to accommodate some anomalous phenomena. 8 The law and social norms theories might 12. See Cooter, supra note 10, at 595. See generally Cass R. Sunstein, On the Expressive Function of Law, 144 U. PA. L. REV. 2021 (1996). 13. See Kahan, supra note 6, at 352-61. 14. See, e.g., Donohue & Siegelman, supra note 4. 15. See Bernstein, supra note 9. 16. See Kahan, supra note 6, at 352-61. 17. See Lessig, supra note 7, at 968-71. 18. See Sunstein, supra note 7, at 945. CHICAGO-KENT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 74:1537 not generalize to new situations, making them useless to policy- makers. Law and social norms theory so far has relied upon rational choice theory and game theory for its intellectual foundation,19 but sociologists and social psychologists have a long history of studying social norms. Sociology even includes a school of thought known as "symbolic interactionism," which is stunningly similar to the signaling theories in the new legal scholarship on social norms.20 For their part, social psychologists have been studying social norms and social influence since the 1930s.21 Decades of social psychological research on social norms merits more than just a tip-of-the-hat from law and social norms scholars. 22 As early as 1936, a prominent social psychologist, Muzafir Sherif, published a monograph describing empirical research on the origins and implications of social norms.23 One of the founders of modern social psychology, Kurt Lewin, demonstrated how to manipulate social settings to alter social norms during World War II as part of an effort to reduce demand for scarce products needed for the war effort.2 4 Social psychologists conducted decades of research on social norms and social influence that followed these early leaders, which could enrich the law and social norms scholar's anecdotal style with rigorous empiricism.
Recommended publications
  • The Strength of Social Norms Across Human Groups
    PPSXXX10.1177/1745691617708631Gelfand et al.Strength of Social Norms 708631research-article2017 Perspectives on Psychological Science 2017, Vol. 12(5) 800 –809 The Strength of Social Norms Across © The Author(s) 2017 Reprints and permissions: Human Groups sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav DOI:https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691617708631 10.1177/1745691617708631 www.psychologicalscience.org/PPS Michele J. Gelfand1, Jesse R. Harrington1, and Joshua Conrad Jackson2 1University of Maryland and 2University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Abstract Social norms are a defining feature of human psychology, yet our understanding of them is still underdeveloped. In this article, we present our own cross-cultural research program on tightness-looseness (TL)—which draws on field, experimental, computational, and neuroscience methods—to illustrate how going beyond Western borders is critical for understanding social norms’ functions and their multilevel consequences. Cross-cultural research enables us to account for the universal features of norm psychology but also explains the great cultural diversity we see in social norms around the globe. Keywords culture, diversity, neuroscience, individual differences, environment Imagine a world where everyone drives on both sides around town, to having conversations, to running an of the road. There are stoplights but no one pays atten- organization turn into an uncoordinated mess. tion to them. Trains, buses, and airplanes don’t operate Perhaps because of their important role in human with any fixed schedule. In conversations, people don’t behavior, social norms have been a central topic of greet each other, interrupt each other frequently, and study in psychology. The earliest studies of normative invade each other’s space.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Norms and Social Influence Mcdonald and Crandall 149
    Available online at www.sciencedirect.com ScienceDirect Social norms and social influence Rachel I McDonald and Christian S Crandall Psychology has a long history of demonstrating the power and and their imitation is not enough to implicate social reach of social norms; they can hardly be overestimated. To norms. Imitation is common enough in many forms of demonstrate their enduring influence on a broad range of social life — what creates the foundation for culture and society phenomena, we describe two fields where research continues is not the imitation, but the expectation of others for when to highlight the power of social norms: prejudice and energy imitation is appropriate, and when it is not. use. The prejudices that people report map almost perfectly onto what is socially appropriate, likewise, people adjust their A social norm is an expectation about appropriate behav- energy use to be more in line with their neighbors. We review ior that occurs in a group context. Sherif and Sherif [8] say new approaches examining the effects of norms stemming that social norms are ‘formed in group situations and from multiple groups, and utilizing normative referents to shift subsequently serve as standards for the individual’s per- behaviors in social networks. Though the focus of less research ception and judgment when he [sic] is not in the group in recent years, our review highlights the fundamental influence situation. The individual’s major social attitudes are of social norms on social behavior. formed in relation to group norms (pp. 202–203).’ Social norms, or group norms, are ‘regularities in attitudes and Address behavior that characterize a social group and differentiate Department of Psychology, University of Kansas, Lawrence, KS 66045, it from other social groups’ [9 ] (p.
    [Show full text]
  • What Normative Terms Mean and Why It Matters for Ethical Eory
    What Normative Terms Mean and Why It Matters for Ethical eory* Alex Silk University of Birmingham [email protected] Forthcoming in M. Timmons (Ed.), Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics, Vol. Abstract is paper investigates how inquiry into normative language can improve substantive normative theorizing. First I examine two dimensions along which normative language differs: “strength” and “subjectivity.” Next I show how greater sensitivity to these features of the meaning and use of normative lan- guage can illuminate debates about three issues in ethics: the coherence of moral dilemmas, the possibility of supererogatory acts, and the connection between making a normative judgment and being motivated to act accord- ingly. e paper concludes with several brief reections on the theoretical utility of the distinction — at least so-called — between “normative” and “non- normative” language and judgment. e discussions of these specic linguistic and normative issues can be seen as case studies illustrating the fruitfulness of utilizing resources from philosophy of language for normative theory. Get- ting clearer on the language we use in normative conversation and theorizing can help us diagnose problems with bad arguments and formulate better mo- tivated questions. is can lead to clearer answers and bring into relief new theoretical possibilities and avenues to explore. *anks to Eric Swanson and the audience at the Fih Annual Arizona Normative Ethics Work- shop for discussion, and to two anonymous referees for comments. Contents Introduction Weak and strong necessity Endorsing and non-endorsing uses Dilemmas Supererogation Judgment internalism and “the normative” Conclusion Introduction e strategy of clarifying philosophical questions by investigating the language we use to express them is familiar.
    [Show full text]
  • Reflections on Social Norms and Human Rights
    The Psychology of Social Norms and the Promotion of Human Rights Deborah A. Prentice Princeton University Chapter to appear in R. Goodman, D. Jinks, & A. K. Woods (Eds.), Understanding social action, promoting human rights. New York: Oxford University Press. This chapter was written while I was Visiting Faculty in the School of Social Sciences at the Institute for Advanced Study, Princeton, NJ. I would like to thank Jeremy Adelman, JoAnne Gowa, Bob Keohane, Eric Maskin, Dale Miller, Catherine Ross, Teemu Ruskola, Rick Shweder, and Eric Weitz for helpful discussions and comments on earlier drafts of the chapter. Please direct correspondence to: Deborah Prentice Department of Psychology Princeton University Green Hall Princeton, NJ 08540 [email protected] 1 Promoting human rights means changing behavior: Changing the behavior of governments that mistreat suspected criminals, opponents of their policies, supporters of their political rivals, and members of particular gender, ethnic, or religious groups; changing the behavior of corporations that mistreat their workers, damage the environment, and produce unsafe products; and changing the behavior of citizens who mistreat their spouses, children, and neighbors. In this chapter, I consider what an understanding of how social norms function psychologically has to contribute to this very worthy project. Social norms have proven to be an effective mechanism for changing health-related and environmental behaviors, so there is good reason to think that they might be helpful in the human-rights domain as well. In the social sciences, social norms are defined as socially shared and enforced attitudes specifying what to do and what not to do in a given situation (see Elster, 1990; Sunstein, 1997).
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on Pragmatism and Scientific Realism Author(S): Cleo H
    Notes on Pragmatism and Scientific Realism Author(s): Cleo H. Cherryholmes Source: Educational Researcher, Vol. 21, No. 6, (Aug. - Sep., 1992), pp. 13-17 Published by: American Educational Research Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1176502 Accessed: 02/05/2008 14:02 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=aera. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We enable the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Notes on Pragmatismand Scientific Realism CLEOH. CHERRYHOLMES Ernest R. House's article "Realism in plicit declarationof pragmatism. Here is his 1905 statement ProfessorResearch" (1991) is informative for the overview it of it: of scientificrealism.
    [Show full text]
  • 'The Magic That Can Set You Free': the Ideology of Folk and the Myth of the Rock Community
    The magic that can set you free': the ideology of folk and the myth of the rock community by SIMON FRITH Rock, the saying goes, is 'the folk music of our time'. Not from a sociological point of view. If 'folk' describes pre-capitalist modes of music production, rock is, without a doubt, a mass-produced, mass- consumed, commodity. The rock-folk argument, indeed, is not about how music is made, but about how it works: rock is taken to express (or reflect) a way of life; rock is used by its listeners as a folk music - it articulates communal values, comments on shared social problems. The argument, in other words, is about subcultures rather than music- making; the question of how music comes to represent its listeners is begged. (I develop these arguments further in Frith 1978, pp. 191-202, and, with particular reference to punk rock, in Frith 1980.) In this article I am not going to answer this question either. My concern is not whether rock is or is not a folk music, but is with the effects of a particular account of popular culture - the ideology of folk - on rock's interpretation of itself. For the rock ideologues of the 1960s - musicians, critics and fans alike - rock 'n' roll's status as a folk music was what differentiated it from routine pop; it was as a folk music that rock could claim a distinctive political and artistic edge. The argument was made, for example, by Jon Landau in his influential role as reviews editor and house theorist of Rolling Stone.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemic Justification, Normative Guidance, and Knowledge
    13 Epistemic Justication, Normative Guidance, and Knowledge ∗ ARTURS LOGINS Abstract. Recently, Pascal Engel has defended a version of a compatibilist view in epistemology that combines both an element of externalism and an element of internalism (Engel 2007, 2012). According to this position exter- nalism has to be adopted about knowledge, whereas internalism has to be endorsed concerning epistemic justification. In this paper I argue that consi- derations that, allegedly, motivates Engel’s internalism about epistemic justi- fication, can be explained equally well, or, indeed, even better by a knowledge based externalist account of epistemic justification. ∗This paper is dedicated to Pascal Engel. I would like to express my gratefulness to Pascal for his teaching and support. His work has made an important impact on me. In particular his Engel 2000, and his Engel 2007 contributed largely to my initiation to analytic philosophy and contem- porary epistemology, respectively. The research work that lead to this article was supported by the Swiss National Science Foundation (SNSF) grant number 100015_131794 (project Knowledge, Evidence, and Practice). 169 170 ARTURS LOGINS 1. Introduction Recently, Pascal Engel has defended a version of a compatibilist view in epis- temology that combines both an element of externalism and an element of internalism (Engel 2007, 2012). In short, according to this view, knowledge has to be characterized in externalist terms, whereas epistemic justification and ra- tionality has to be characterized in internalist terms. The externalist view about knowledge that Engel favours integrates a ver- sion of safety account of knowledge that requires that knowledge is safe belief and does not require that a subject has a reflective access top in order for the subject to know thatp (see Engel 2012 : 8).
    [Show full text]
  • Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II
    UCLA UCLA Public Law & Legal Theory Series Title Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/81q9p7hk Author Greenberg, Mark Publication Date 2006-03-03 Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II Mark Greenberg UCLA School of Law and Department of Philosophy I. Introduction In How Facts Make Law and other recent papers,1 I argue that a full constitutive account of the content of the law – of legal facts – must appeal to normative facts. The project of HFML is to defend this position without assuming that legal facts are themselves normative facts. The argument’s engine is a requirement that a constitutive account of legal facts must meet. According to this rational-relation requirement,2 it is not enough for a constitutive account of legal facts to specify non-legal facts that modally determine the legal facts. The constitutive determinants of legal facts must provide reasons for the obtaining of the legal facts (in a sense of “reason” that I develop). In HFML,3 I argue that non-normative, contingent facts – descriptive facts, for short – do not provide such reasons without normative facts.4 In the present paper, I focus on the rational-relation requirement. I deploy it in three related projects. First, I respond to a family of objections that challenge me to explain why normative facts and descriptive facts together are better placed to provide 1 Mark Greenberg, How Facts Make Law, <INSERT CITE FOR HFML IN THIS VOLUME HERE 2006> [hereinafter HFML].
    [Show full text]
  • Deviance from Social Norms: Who Are the Deviants?
    Running Head: DEVIANCE FROM SOCIAL NORMS: WHO ARE THE DEVIANTS? This article was published in the Journal of Social and Political Psychology doi: https://doi.org/10.5964/jspp.v8i1.1134 The Social and Psychological Characteristics of Norm Deviants: A Field Study in a Small Cohesive University Campus Robin Gomila and Elizabeth Levy Paluck Princeton University Word count: 10,342 DEVIANCE FROM SOCIAL NORMS: WHO ARE THE DEVIANTS? Abstract People who deviate from the established norms of their social group can clarify group boundaries, strengthen group cohesion, and catalyze group and broader social change. Yet social psychologists have recently neglected the study of deviants. We conducted in-depth interviews of Princeton University upperclassmen who deviated from a historical and widely known Princeton norm: joining an “eating club,” a social group that undergraduates join at the end of their sophomore year. We explored the themes of these interviews with two rounds of surveys during the semester when students decide whether to join an eating club (pilot survey, N=408; and a random subsample of the pilot survey with 90% takeup, N=212). The surveys asked: what are the social and psychological antecedents of deviance from norms? The data suggest that deviance is a pattern: compared to those who conform, students who deviate by not joining clubs report a history of deviance and of feeling different from the typical member of their social group. They also feel less social belonging and identification with Princeton and its social environment. Students who deviate are lower in social monitoring, but otherwise are comparable to students who conform in terms of personality traits measured by the Big Five, and of their perception of the self as socially awkward, independent, or rebellious.
    [Show full text]
  • Normative Surrender
    Michigan Journal of International Law Volume 9 Issue 1 1988 Normative Surrender Jerome B. Elkind University of Wyoming, College of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mjil Part of the Human Rights Law Commons, International Law Commons, and the Public Law and Legal Theory Commons Recommended Citation Jerome B. Elkind, Normative Surrender, 9 MICH. J. INT'L L. 263 (1988). Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mjil/vol9/iss1/9 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Michigan Journal of International Law at University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Michigan Journal of International Law by an authorized editor of University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Normative Surrender Jerome B. Elkind* INTRODUCTION In the published papers of a recent colloquium on the life and works of Hugo Grotius, the observation was made that Grotius attempted to steer a path between "Utopian idealism which had no chance of exercising any influence on the actual behavior of States, and Machiavellian realism which would have amounted to total surrender to their will and whim."' Concern for the distinction between idealism and realism, an issue even at the dawn of the era of power politics, is very much a current issue. In the world of modem international law doctrine there is no greater scorn than that reserved by self-professed "realists" for those whom they choose to regard as "idealists." In the cynical atmosphere of the late twentieth century, it is fashionable to be a realist.
    [Show full text]
  • Normative and Descriptive Aspects of Management Education: Differentiation and Integration
    Journal of Educational Issues ISSN 2377-2263 2015, Vol. 1, No. 1 Normative and Descriptive Aspects of Management Education: Differentiation and Integration Gavriel Meirovich (Corresponding author) Department of Management, Bertolon School of Business, Salem State University 352 Lafayette Street, Salem, MA 01930, United States Tel: 978-543-6948 Fax: 978-542-6027 E-mail: [email protected] Received: April 7, 2015 Accepted: May 27, 2015 Published: June 3, 2015 doi:10.5296/jei.v1i1.7395 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.5296/jei.v1i1.7395 Abstract This study advocates strongly for clear differentiation and synthesis of descriptive and normative approaches in management education. There is a certain isolation of normative and descriptive theoretical frameworks presented in management courses. Normative frameworks in management explain how organizations should be managed, while descriptive frameworks show how they actually are managed. Significant portions of what we teach in the business curriculum are predominantly descriptive; other parts are mostly normative, or prescriptive. If these domains are not sufficiently connected, the relevance of both approaches diminishes. When one piece of material explains only the current reality without providing tools to improve it, while another piece prescribes steps for improvement that are not grounded in a particular context, students lose interest in both. The paper presents various modes of differentiation and integration between two realms and pertinent ways to recalibrate management courses. Keywords: Normative and descriptive framework, Differentiation, Integration 1. Introduction The purpose of business education is preparing future business professionals for successful careers and meaningful lives. The continued rise of its cost poses difficult questions about the relevance of contemporary business education in general and management education in particular.
    [Show full text]
  • Ideology: the Challenge for Civic Literacy Educators by James A
    Volume 1, Issue 1 http://journals.iupui.edu/index.php/civiclit/index July 2014 Ideology: The Challenge for Civic Literacy Educators By James A. Duplass ABSTRACT: Commitment to open-mindedness, critical thinking, liberty, and social justice are proposed as four pillars of a democratic ideology. The highly charged and polarized discourse between left and right po- litical ideology among the media, politicians, educators, and public has intensified the challenge placed on social studies educators to transmit these goals to their students. A rendition of the philosophical trajectory of the ideas of liberty, social justice, and justice are provided and married with concepts from the philosophical foundations of American education, social studies education goals and strategies, and contemporary human- istic philosophy so as to articulate a new case that transmission of a democratic ideology is at the core of social studies education. The proposition is made that teaching social studies is unique because the development of an ideology requires teachers’ attention to values, virtues formation, and the liberation of the individual. Keywords: Ideology, critical thinking, liberty, social justice, justice The purpose of this essay is to explore the largely unexamined idea of a democratic ideology as an inherent goal of social studies education. The traditional meaning of competency and literacy established by many disciplines including social studies education (Duplass, 2006) do not fully convey the unique mission of social studies education to pass on an ideology - belief system - to successive generations. The formation of values (Apple, 2004; Duplass, 2008; McCarthy, 1994), the use of critical thinking (Dewey, 1890/1969), and July 2014 Ideology: The Challenge for Civic Literacy Educators 1 the goal of passing on democratic traditions (Dewey, 1939/1976; National Council for Social Studies, 2008) serve as an intersection for the formation of a democratic ideology, although such a term is seldom found in the social studies literature.
    [Show full text]