Phenomenology, Culture, and Ethnomusicology in Conversation J

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Phenomenology, Culture, and Ethnomusicology in Conversation J Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Dissertations (2009 -) Dissertations, Theses, and Professional Projects Towards a Philosophy of the Musical Experience: Phenomenology, Culture, and Ethnomusicology in Conversation J. Tyler Friedman Marquette University Recommended Citation Friedman, J. Tyler, "Towards a Philosophy of the Musical Experience: Phenomenology, Culture, and Ethnomusicology in Conversation" (2019). Dissertations (2009 -). 828. https://epublications.marquette.edu/dissertations_mu/828 TOWARDS A PHILOSOPHY OF THE MUSICAL EXPERIENCE: CULTURE, PHENOMENOLOGY AND ETHNOMUSICOLOGY IN CONVERSATION by J Tyler Friedman, B.A., B.S., M.A. A Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School, Marquette University, in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Milwaukee, Wisconsin May 2019 ABSTRACT TOWARDS A PHILOSOPHY OF THE MUSICAL EXPERIENCE: CULTURE, PHENOMENOLOGY AND ETHNOMUSICOLOGY IN CONVERSATION J Tyler Friedman, B.A., B.S., M.A. Marquette University, 2018 This dissertation engages the questions and methodologies of phenomenology, the philosophy of culture, the philosophy of music and ethnomusicology in order to investigate the significance of music in human life. The systematic orientation of Ernst Cassirer’s philosophy of symbolic forms provides the overarching framework that positions the approach in chapter one. Following Cassirer, art in general and music in particular are not regarded as enjoyable yet dispensable pastimes, but rather as fundamental ways of experiencing the world as intuitive forms and sensations. Establishing the ontological significance of music entails unpacking the sui generis experience of time, space and subjectivity that characterize the musical experience. Phenomenology, in particular the thought of Alfred Schütz, provides a point of departure for thinking more concretely about the musical experience. The turn to phenomenology is motivated both by its systematic consanguinuity with Cassirer’s project as well as its insistent focus on the details of lived experience. However, bolstered by what is argued to be a more holistic description of the musical experience gleaned from the work of ethnomusicologists, Schütz’s phenomenological account of the music is challenged on a number of key issues such as music’s ontological status and the tendency to equate “music” with “musical works.” Despite the blind spots of his writings on music, Schütz’s phenomenology of the social world proves to be a useful framework for thinking about the multiplicity of ways in which music is experienced as meaningful and how the equivocality of the concept of musical meaning brings the social nature of the musical experience into view. Sociality also figures into a discussion of improvisation, an important theme that has only relatively recently begun to receive philosophical attention. Arguing that an adequate philosophical treatment of music must account for both the variety of musical cultures as well as the variety of musical practices, a consideration of improvisation helps philosophy think outside of the work-paradigm that was critiqued in chapter two. By incorporating ethnomusicological theory and ethnographies as well as downplayed musical practices like improvisation, this dissertation offers an enriched account of the ways that music shapes human life. i ACKNOWLEDGMENTS J Tyler Friedman, B.A., B.S., M.A. A great many individuals and institutions supported the writing of this dissertation on a personal and profession level. I am grateful to my Doktorvater Professor Pol Vandevelde for his guidance, patience and always-prompt feedback. Many thanks go to Professor Sebastian Luft for his unstinting professional support and friendship. Professor Timothy Rice contributed his invaluable ethnomusicological expertise and graciously served as an outside reader on my committee. I am also grateful to Professors Curtis Carter and Javier Ibáñez-Noé for serving on my committee and for seminars offered over the past few years, which enriched my understanding of aesthetics and nineteenth century German thought respectively. I would like to thank the Cyril E. Smith Trust Smith Family Fellowship for underwriting my research during the 2016-17 academic year. The Smith Fellowship allowed me to travel to the Beinecke Archives at Yale University where I had access to unpublished works by both Alfred Schütz and Ernst Cassirer, which figure importantly into chapter one. A quarter spent at UCLA also would not have come to pass without the munificence of the Smith Fellowship. It was at UCLA that much of the groundwork in ethnomusicology was laid, which I consider to be perhaps this dissertation’s chief contribution to scholarship in the philosophy of music. The Arthur J. Schmitt Leadership Fellows Program generously supported the writing of this dissertation during the 2017-2018 academic year. The ability to focus on writing and research afforded by both the Smith and Schmitt Fellowships is a great honor for which I am deeply thankful. Were it not for such support I am sure that both this dissertation and I would doubtless have suffered more than was necessary. ii Finally, I would like to thank my family and friends for their roles in the completion of this dissertation, whether by lending a sympathetic ear or helping to hold the world at bay so that I might live the privileged existence of the vita contemplativa. iii TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS…………………………………………………………………………i INTRODUCTION………………………………………………………………………………...1 CHAPTER ONE: CASSIRER’S CRITIQUE OF CULTURE AND THE POSITION OF ART.15 1. From a Critique of Reason to a Critique of Culture: the Idealistic Approach…….............16 2. A Kaleidoscopic View of the Human Being: the Philosophical-Anthropological Approach…..............................................................................................................................24 3. Art as a Symbolic Form…………………………………………………………...............30 3a. Space in (Visual) Art……………………………………………………………..38 3b. Space in Music…………………………………………………………………...53 3c. Skeptical Conceptions of Space in Music………………………………………..56 3d. Critique of Skeptical Conceptions of Space in Music…………………………...62 4. Time in Art………………………………………………………………………...............69 4a. Time in Visual Art……………………………………………………………….71 4b. Time in Music……………………………………………………………………73 5. Symbolic Forms and the Experience of Subjectivity………………………………...........78 5a. Music as a Life Form…………………………………………………………….79 6. Thinking in Music…………………………………………………………………............83 7. Conclusion…………………………………………………………………………...........89 CHAPTER TWO: THE PHENOMENOLOGY OF MUSIC: A HISTORICAL OVERVIEW AND ETHNOMUSICOLOGICAL CRITIQUE………………………………………………....91 1. Alfred Schütz’s Essays on Music…………………………………………………............93 1a. Schütz’s Ontology of Music………………………………………………….......94 1b. Schütz’s Account of the Musical Experience…………………………………..104 iv 2. Critique of the Phenomenological Ontology of Music……………………………..........115 2a. Critique of Phenomenology’s “Digital” Ontology……………………………...115 3. Critique of Work-Paradigm………………………………………………………...........124 3a. Historical Contingency of Work-Paradigm…………………………………….124 3b. Conceptualizing Music Beyond the Work-Paradigm…………………………..130 4. Consequences for the Phenomenological Account of the Musical Experience…….........138 5. Conclusion………………………………………………………………………….........145 CHAPTER THREE: MUSICAL MEANING, MUSICAL UNIVERSALS AND THE RECIPROCAL BENEFITS OF ETHNOMUSICOLOGY, PHENOMENOLOGY AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF MUSIC……………………………………………………………….........147 1. Distinctions Pertaining to Meaning………………………………………………...........148 1a. Subjective Versus Objective Meaning………………………………………….148 1b. Merely Perceptual/Phenomenological Object Versus Socio-Cultural Object….150 1c. Object Versus Activity………………………………………………………….151 2. Subjective Meaning of Music Qua Merely Perceptual Product…………………….........153 3. Objective Meaning of Music Qua Merely Perceptual Object………………………........158 4. Subjective Meaning of Music Qua Socio-Cultural Object…………………………........160 4a. Finite Province of Meaning Correlated to Socio-Cultural Music in General…..161 4b. Peter Kivy on Pure Music………………………………………………………162 4c. The Concept of Appresentation………………………………………………...168 5. Objective Meaning of Music Qua Socio-Cultural Object…………………………..........173 6. Subjective Meaning of Music Qua ‘Merely Perceptual’ (Formal) Activity………..........174 6a. Schütz on the Concept of Action……………………………………………….175 6b. “Problems” Pertaining to the Relation of Schütz’s Concept of Action and Meaning……………………………………………………….................................180 v 7. Objective Meaning of Music Qua ‘Merely Perceptual’ (Formal) Activity………...........182 8. Subjective Meaning of Music Qua Socio-Cultural Activity………………………..........183 8a. Finite Province of Meaning Correlated to the Activity of Music………………183 8b. Functions of Music……………………………………………………………..184 9. Objective Meaning of Music Qua Socio-Cultural Activity………………………...........187 10. Ethnomusicology and the Reciprocal Advantages of Philosophizing About Music.......188 11. Conclusion………………………………………………………………………….......201 CHAPTER FOUR: TOWARDS A PHENOMENOLOGY OF IMPROVISATION………………………..................................................................................203 1. What is Improvisation?......................................................................................................204 2. The Pedagogy of Improvisation…………………………………………………….........210 3. Improvisation and Composition…………………………………………………….........216
Recommended publications
  • Philosophy of Music Education
    University of New Hampshire University of New Hampshire Scholars' Repository Honors Theses and Capstones Student Scholarship Spring 2017 Philosophy of Music Education Mary Elizabeth Barba Follow this and additional works at: https://scholars.unh.edu/honors Part of the Music Education Commons, and the Music Pedagogy Commons Recommended Citation Barba, Mary Elizabeth, "Philosophy of Music Education" (2017). Honors Theses and Capstones. 322. https://scholars.unh.edu/honors/322 This Senior Honors Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Scholarship at University of New Hampshire Scholars' Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Theses and Capstones by an authorized administrator of University of New Hampshire Scholars' Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Philosophy of Music Education Mary Barba Dr. David Upham December 9, 2016 Barba 1 Philosophy of Music Education A philosophy of music education refers to the value of music, the value of teaching music, and how to practically utilize those values in the music classroom. Bennet Reimer, a renowned music education philosopher, wrote the following, regarding the value of studying the philosophy of music education: “To the degree we can present a convincing explanation of the nature of the art of music and the value of music in the lives of people, to that degree we can present a convincing picture of the nature of music education and its value for human life.”1 In this thesis, I will explore the philosophies of Emile Jacques-Dalcroze, Carl Orff, Zoltán Kodály, Bennett Reimer, and David Elliott, and suggest practical applications of their philosophies in the orchestral classroom, especially in the context of ear training and improvisation.
    [Show full text]
  • Contesting Regimes of Variation: Critical Groundwork for Pedagogies of Mobile Experience and Restorative Justice
    Robert W. Train Sonoma State University, California CONTESTING REGIMES OF VARIATION: CRITICAL GROUNDWORK FOR PEDAGOGIES OF MOBILE EXPERIENCE AND RESTORATIVE JUSTICE Abstract: This paper examines from a critical transdisciplinary perspective the concept of variation and its fraught binary association with standard language as part of the conceptual toolbox and vocabulary for language educators and researchers. “Variation” is shown to be imbricated a historically-contingent metadiscursive regime in language study as scientific description and education supporting problematic speaker identities (e.g., “non/native”, “heritage”, “foreign”) around an ideology of reduction through which complex sociolinguistic and sociocultural spaces of diversity and variability have been reduced to the “problem” of governing people and spaces legitimated and embodied in idealized teachers and learners of languages invented as the “zero degree of observation” (Castro-Gómez 2005; Mignolo 2011) in ongoing contexts of Western modernity and coloniality. This paper explores how regimes of variation have been constructed in a “sociolinguistics of distribution” (Blommaert 2010) constituted around the delimitation of borders—linguistic, temporal, social and territorial—rather than a “sociolinguistics of mobility” focused on interrogating and problematizing the validity and relevance of those borders in a world characterized by diverse transcultural and translingual experiences of human flow and migration. This paper reframes “variation” as mobile modes-of-experiencing- the-world in order to expand the critical, historical, and ethical vocabularies and knowledge base of language educators and lay the groundwork for pedagogies of experience that impact human lives in the service of restorative social justice. Keywords: metadiscursive regimes w sociolinguistic variation w standard language w sociolinguistics of mobility w pedagogies of experience Train, Robert W.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Linguistic Movements: Neogrammarianism, Structuralism, Transformationalism
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 041 282 AL 002 492 AUTHOR Katranides, Aristotle TITLE Three Linguistic Movements: Neogrammarianism, Structuralism, Transformationalism. PUB DATE Mar 70 NOTE 14p.; Paper given at the fourth annual TESOL Convention, San Francisco, California, March 18-21, 1970 EDRS PRICE EDRS Price MF-$0.25 HC-$0.80 DESCRIPTORS *English (Second Language) , *Language Instruction, *Linguistics, Linguistic Theory, Structural Linguistics, *Teaching Methods, Transformation Generative Grammar IDENTIFIERS *Neogrammarianism ABSTRACT The relevance, the application, and the importance of linguistics to teaching English as a foreign language is discussed. The author's assumption is that linguistics is "irrelevant to the aims, and inapraicable to the tasks of such teaching," and agrees with linguists such as Rosenbaum that the goal of linguistic science is "to determine inductively the laws governing the behavior of observable data." Developments in linguistics during thepast 100 years can be grouped into three main movements: (1) Neogrammarianism, which introduced rigorous requirements ofan exact science into historLcal linguistics by concentratingon the observation of phonetic phenomena; (2) Structuralism, which forcefully promoted the anthropological view that all human languagesare equal in complexity of structure, and was responsible for the widely accepted view that linguistics is a panacea for all problems inevery type of language-teaching activity; and(3) Transformationalism, which has not yet contributed anything new to an understanding of natural languages but has put linguistics in some theoretical perspective and freed it from the excessive preoccupation of the structuralists with taxonomic procedure. Some time ago, language teachingwas freed from philology; quite recently language teachingwas freed from literary studies; it should now be freed from linguistics.
    [Show full text]
  • From Linguistic Events and Restricted Languages to Registers. Firthian Legacy and Corpus Linguistics Jacqueline Léon
    From Linguistic Events and Restricted Languages to Registers. Firthian legacy and Corpus Linguistics Jacqueline Léon To cite this version: Jacqueline Léon. From Linguistic Events and Restricted Languages to Registers. Firthian legacy and Corpus Linguistics. The Henry Sweet Society Bulletin, 2007, 49, pp.5-26. halshs-00220455 HAL Id: halshs-00220455 https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-00220455 Submitted on 26 Mar 2008 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Léon J., 2007, « From Linguistic Events and Restricted Languages to Registers. Firthian legacy and Corpus Linguistics » Bulletin of the Henry Sweet Society for the History of Linguistic Ideas, n°49 :5-26 From Linguistic Events and Restricted Languages to Registers. Firthian legacy and Corpus Linguistics1 Jacqueline Léon Laboratoire d’Histoire des théories linguistiques, CNRS, Université Paris Denis Diderot It is generally acknowledged, among present-day corpus linguists working on registers and genres, that the notion of register has Firthian sources and more generally that it originates from British contextualism regarded as « the only tradition that suggests this kind of direct correlation between the functional organization of meaning in language and the organization of context. » (Eggins et Martin 1997 :239).
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemological Tensions Between Linguistic Description and Ordinary Speakers’ Intuitive Knowledge: Examples from French Verb Morphology
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Serveur académique lausannois Epistemological tensions between linguistic description and ordinary speakers’ intuitive knowledge: examples from French verb morphology Christian SURCOUF École de français langue étrangère, Faculté des lettres, Université de Lausanne Abstract In this article, I address epistemological questions regarding the status of linguistic rules and the pervasive––though seldom discussed––tension that arises between theory-driven object perception by linguists on the one hand, and ordinary speakers’ possible intuitive knowledge on the other hand. Several issues will be discussed using examples from French verb morphology, based on the 6500 verbs from Le Petit Robert dictionary (2013). 1. Introduction A journalist commenting on French actress Juliette Binoche’s performance declared on the radio “elle est insupportable, elle ne joue pas elle binoche” (she is unbearable, she does not act, she “binoches”). Undoubtedly, any French native speaker can spontaneously produce the whole morphological paradigm of this brand new verb, and for instance add /ʁa/ to this Pr31 /binɔʃ/ in order to form Fut3 /binɔʃʁa/. But what is the status of this “rule”? In this article, I will mainly raise epistemological questions regarding the tension between scientific expectations while analyzing French verb inflectional morphological rules on the one hand and ordinary speakers’ possible inflectional production rules on the other. 1 Tenses are abbreviated as Pr(esent), Imp(erfect), Fut(ure), Inf(initive), P(assé) S(imple), P(ast) P(articiple). Persons follow the conventional I to they order from 1 to 6. Thus, Pr1-3 indicates Present singular.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 7 Linguistics As a Science of Structure Ryan M
    Chapter 7 Linguistics as a science of structure Ryan M. Nefdt University of the Western Cape Generative linguistics has rapidly changed during the course of a relatively short period. This has caused many to question its scientific status as a realist scientific theory (Stokhof & van Lambalgen 2011; Lappin et al. 2000). In this chapter, I argue against this conclusion. Specifically, I claim that the mathematical foundations of the science present a different story below the surface. I agree with critics that due to the major shifts in theory over the past 80 years, linguistics is indeed opened up to the problem of pessimistic meta-induction or radical theory change. However, I further argue that a structural realist approach (Ladyman 1998; French 2006) can save the field from this problem and at the same time capture its structural nature. I discuss particular historical instances of theory change in generative grammar as evidence for this interpretation and finally attempt to extend it beyond the gener- ative tradition to encompass previous frameworks in linguistics. 1 Introduction The generativist revolution in linguistics started in the mid-1950s, inspired in large part by insights from mathematical logic and in particular proof theory. Since then, generative linguistics has become a dominant paradigm, with many connections to both the formal and natural sciences. At the centre of the newly established discipline was the syntactic or formal engine, the structures of which were revealed through modelling grammatical form. The generativist paradigm in linguistics initially relied heavily upon the proof-theoretic techniques intro- duced by Emil Post and other formal logicians to model the form language takes (Tomalin 2006; Pullum 2011; 2013).1 Yet despite these aforementioned formal be- ginnings, the generative theory of linguistics has changed its commitments quite 1Here my focus will largely be on the formal history of generative syntax but I will make some comments on other aspects of linguistics along the way.
    [Show full text]
  • UK Linguistic Ethnography Discussion Paper
    UK linguistic ethnography: A discussion paper UK LINGUISTIC ETHNOGRAPHY: A DISCUSSION PAPER Coordinating Committee UK Linguistic Ethnography Forum 1 December 2004 Contents: 0. Preface 1. Linguistics & ethnography 1.1 Ethnography 1.2 Linguistics 1.3 Ethnography in tension with linguistics 1.4 The limits of ethnographic description 1.5 Ethnographies of discourse 2. Linguistic ethnography in the UK 2.1 Academic connections, influences and antecedents in the UK 2.2 Research trajectories and academic & political demeanours 2.3 Comparison with North American linguistic anthropology 3. Issues for the future 3.1 Generalisation & theory development 3.2 Building community and extending dialogue 0. PREFACE In recent years in the UK, a number of researchers have started to identify their work as ‘linguistic ethnography’, and 4 ½ years ago, a UK Linguistic Ethnography Forum (LEF) was established.. This work has strong links to Hymes’ ‘ethnography of communication’ (1972), but ‘the ethnography of communication’ isn’t really adequate as an umbrella characterisation because of substantial developments both in linguistic anthropology and elsewhere that have impacted on British work since the 1980s. More than that, the phrase ‘ethnography of communication’ blurs an important tension between linguistics and ethnography that contributes much to the methodological identity of linguistic ethnographic work. So what does the construct ‘linguistic ethnography’ actually imply, and what kind of cultural construction is the UK LEF? What are the links to other kinds of work, and what principles, practices, alignments and differentiations are involved UK LE’s self-constitution? These are very much genuine questions, and not just the rhetorical prelude to a proclamation of sub-disciplinary autonomy, and this paper tries to start formulating some of the answers.
    [Show full text]
  • Calculus of Possibilities As a Technique in Linguistic Typology
    Calculus of possibilities as a technique in linguistic typology Igor Mel’uk 1. The problem stated: A unified conceptual system in linguistics A central problem in the relationship between typology and the writing of individual grammars is that of developing a cross-linguistically viable con- ceptual system and a corresponding terminological framework. I will deal with this problem in three consecutive steps: First, I state the problem and sketch a conceptual system that I have put forward for typological explora- tions in morphology (Sections 1 and 2). Second, I propose a detailed illus- tration of this system: a calculus of grammatical voices in natural languages (Section 3). And third, I apply this calculus (that is, the corresponding con- cepts) in two particular case studies: an inflectional category known as an- tipassive and the grammatical voice in French (Sections 4 and 5). In the latter case, the investigation shows that even for a language as well de- scribed as French a rigorously standardized typological framework can force us to answer questions that previous descriptions have failed to re- solve. I start with the following three assumptions: 1) One of the most pressing tasks of today’s linguistics is description of particular languages, the essential core of this work being the writing of grammars and lexicons. A linguist sets out to describe a language as pre- cisely and exhaustively as possible; this includes its semantics, syntax, morphology and phonology plus (within the limits of time and funds avail- able) its lexicon. 2) Such a description is necessarily carried out in terms of some prede- fined concepts – such as lexical unit, semantic actant, syntactic role, voice, case, phoneme, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • Descriptive Theories, Explanatory Theories, and Basic Linguistic Theory1
    Descriptive theories, explanatory theories, and Basic Linguistic Theory1 Matthew S. Dryer 1. Introduction Linguists often distinguish work they characterize as descriptive from work they characterize as theoretical. Similarly, linguists often characterize certain work as atheoretical. This label is sometimes applied, not only to descriptive work on particular languages, but also occasionally to crosslinguistic typological work. I argue in this chapter that this way of talking represents a fundamental confusion about the relationship between theory and description. First, there is no such thing as atheoretical description. Second, although it is confused to talk about theory and description as contrastive notions, it does make sense to talk about a contrast between description and explanation. I further argue that there is a need for both descriptive theories and explanatory theories. Descriptive theories (or theoretical frameworks) are theories about what languages are 2 like . They are theories about what tools we need in order to provide adequate descriptions of individual languages. Explanatory theories (or theoretical frameworks), in contrast, are theories about why languages are the way they are. The distinction between descriptive theories and explanatory theories is not widely recognized in linguistics, although it is not hard to identify the historical explanation for this. First, pregenerative theories, such as American structuralism, explicitly disavowed the goal of constructing an explanatory theory. As such they were examples of descriptive theories, but the underlying assumption was that that was the only type of theory needed. Generative grammar, in contrast, has aimed at being an explanatory theory. Furthermore, a central tenet of generative grammar, especially clear in the work of Chomsky since the mid-1970s (e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Music Philosophy 365 Syllabus
    Philosophy of Music Philosophy 365 Syllabus John Douard Texts: New Jersey Books will have the texts. The Imaginary Museum of Musical Works, by Lydia Goehr, Oxford University Press., ISBN: 9780195324785 Listening to Popular Music, or How I learned to stop worrying and love Led Zeppelin by Theodore Gracyk, U. of Michigan Press, ISBN: 978-0-472-06983-5 Improvisation: It’s Nature and Practice in Music, by Derek Bailey, Da Capo Press, ISBN: 978-0306805288 Derek Bailey: On the Edge: Video based on Improvisation: http://ubu.com/film/bailey.html I will also email a packet of papers on specific issues. ______________________________________________________________________________________________ In this course, we begin with a consideration of the concept of the musical work. We will then examine improvisational music: jazz, rock and hip hop; but also music generated as improvisations in the classical canon, Indian raga, and African indigenous music. Most courses on the philosophy of music focus on “classical” or “art” music. These terms usually are used in an ethnocentric way to refer to formal Western music, and it is in that context in which the concept of the musical work evolved in the early 19th century. A focus on improvisation will permit an interrogation of the concept of a musical work, by setting it against the essentially imperfect productions of improvisations. We will conclude with a conversation about the politics of music and the role of the audience in musical production. The purpose of this course is to deepen your understanding of music by reflecting on fundamental philosophical questions, but also to deepen your philosophical understanding by examining questions about an ubiquitous human practice.
    [Show full text]
  • Typology of Signed Languages: Differentiation Through Kinship Terminology Erin Wilkinson
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of New Mexico University of New Mexico UNM Digital Repository Linguistics ETDs Electronic Theses and Dissertations 7-1-2009 Typology of Signed Languages: Differentiation through Kinship Terminology Erin Wilkinson Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalrepository.unm.edu/ling_etds Recommended Citation Wilkinson, Erin. "Typology of Signed Languages: Differentiation through Kinship Terminology." (2009). https://digitalrepository.unm.edu/ling_etds/40 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Electronic Theses and Dissertations at UNM Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Linguistics ETDs by an authorized administrator of UNM Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. TYPOLOGY OF SIGNED LANGUAGES: DIFFERENTIATION THROUGH KINSHIP TERMINOLOGY BY ERIN LAINE WILKINSON B.A., Language Studies, Wellesley College, 1999 M.A., Linguistics, Gallaudet University, 2001 DISSERTATION Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Linguistics The University of New Mexico Albuquerque, New Mexico August, 2009 ©2009, Erin Laine Wilkinson ALL RIGHTS RESERVED iii DEDICATION To my mother iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Many thanks to Barbara Pennacchi for kick starting me on my dissertation by giving me a room at her house, cooking me dinner, and making Italian coffee in Rome during November 2007. Your endless support, patience, and thoughtful discussions are gratefully taken into my heart, and I truly appreciate what you have done for me. I heartily acknowledge Dr. William Croft, my advisor, for continuing to encourage me through the long number of months writing and rewriting these chapters.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant Expressive Theory Music
    Kant’s Expressive Theory of Music Samantha Matherne Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism (2014, pre-print) Abstract: Several prominent philosophers of art (e.g., Kivy, Dahlhaus, Schueller) have worried whether Kant has a coherent theory of music on account of two perceived tensions in his view. First, there appears to be a conflict between his formalist and expressive commitments. Second (and even worse), Kant defends seemingly contradictory claims about music being beautiful and merely agreeable, i.e., not beautiful. Against these critics, I show that Kant has a consistent view of music that reconciles these tensions. I argue that, for Kant, music can be experienced as either agreeable or beautiful depending upon the attitude we take towards it. Though we might be tempted to think he argues that we experience music as agreeable when we attend to its expressive qualities and as beautiful when we attend to its formal properties, I demonstrate that he actually claims that we are able to judge music as beautiful only if we are sensitive to the expression of emotion through musical form. With this revised understanding of Kant’s theory of music in place, I conclude by sketching a Kantian solution to a central problem in the philosophy of music: given that music is not sentient, how can it express emotion? §1. Introduction As philosophers like Peter Kivy and Stephen Davies have emphasized, one of the central issues in the philosophy of music is the problem of expression.1 Frequently when we hear a piece of instrumental music, we describe it as expressing an emotion, e.g., Beethoven’s ‘Eroica’ symphony sounds triumphant or Chopin’s Étude in E Major (Op.
    [Show full text]