The Transversal Thought of Gilles Deleuze: Encounters and Influences

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Transversal Thought of Gilles Deleuze: Encounters and Influences 1 The Transversal Thought of Gilles Deleuze: Encounters and Influences James Williams 2 For Heloïse, Olivia and Octie 3 Acknowledgements: This work was made possible by an AHRB Research Leave Scheme Award in 2003-4. The Carnegie Fund for the Universities Scotland funded further research in Paris libraries in 2004-5. The British Academy funded travel for presentations of versions of the chapters on Kant and on Lewis at the Experimenting with Intensities conference at Trent University, Canada, and at the Australian Society for Continental Philosophy annual conference 2005. I am very grateful for this essential and generous funding. Chapter 5 was presented as part of the “Chromatiques whiteheadiennes” series at the Sorbonne in January 2004. Chapter 7 was given at the Values and Virtues conference in Dundee, May 2004. The final chapter on resistance was presented at the Society for European Philosophy annual conference, University of Greenwich, July 2004. Chapter 4 was presented at the Gaston Bachelard: The History of Society conference at Goldsmiths College, University of London, in December 2003. Chapter 2 was presented at Carleton University, Ottawa, in May 2004. Chapter 6 was presented in part at the ‘Que prouve la science-fiction: raison, machines, corps et mondes’ conference, Université de Lille 3, 1-2 April 2005. The chapter on Deleuze and Kant was presented, in a different version, at the Experimenting with Intensities conference in May 2004. Questions, criticisms and suggestions put to me at all these occasions were invaluable in improving this work and I am grateful to all participants – but reserve all errors as mine! Many friends, postgraduate students and colleagues helped with support and ideas. I thank them all and, in particular, for remedying lack of knowledge and oversight, or for helpful suggestions: Isabella Palin, Lars Iyer, Keith Robinson, Rachel Jones, Michel Weber, Will Large, John Protevi, Nicholas Davey, John Mullarkey, Keith Ansell Pearson, Paul Barlow, Fabio Presutti, Tim Flanagan, Jenny Kermally and William Ross. Without the love of Claire, Rebecca, Nathan and Alice, this book would never have been written. 4 Contents: Chapter 1. Introduction Chapter 2. Deleuze and Kant: the transcendental without transcendence: 1. Deleuze’s debt to Kant 2. Forms and foundations 3. Immanence and the transcendental 4. Experience and experimentation 5. Political and ethical consequences 6. Transcendental Ideas, possibility and truth Chapter 3. Deleuze and Levinas: towards an ethics of expression: 1. Expressionism as ground for an ethical relation 2. Deleuze and Levinas on the face and the Other 3. Expression in speech and expression as drama 4. Movement, structure, infinity 5. Method as resistance to system Chapter 4. Deleuze and Bachelard: completeness and continuity in dialectics 1. Dialectics 2. Priorities and contexts 3. Anti-Cartesian dialectics 5 4. Continuity and discontinuity 5. Syntheses of time: Deleuze’s critique of discontinuity 6. Bachelard’s arguments against continuity 7. How radical is the new? Chapter 5. Deleuze and Whitehead: the concept of reciprocal determination 1. Dualism and immanence 2. Immortality 3. Potential and identity 4. Abstraction 5. Dramatisation 6. Stakes of a difference: Ideas and eternal objects Chapter 6. Deleuze and Lewis: the real virtual or real possible worlds? 1. Surface differences 2. Two pragmatisms 3. On common sense as conservatism 4. Justifying the possible and the virtual 5. On the reality of the virtual 6. Spatio-temporal isolation and virtual connection Chapter 7. Deleuze and Harman: distinguishing problems from questions 1. Problems and questions 6 2. Clarity, distinctness, obscurity 3. Continuity and connection 4. Truth and problems 5. A new kind of foundation: metaphysics as experimentation 6. Guiding intuitions, curbing subjectivity 7. Bad trends in philosophy Chapter 8. Deleuze, Negri, Lyotard: metaphysics and resistance Bibliography 7 Chapter 1. Introduction: the problem of openness in metaphysics ‘The construction of the most open, far-reaching and well-determined metaphysics.’ This book develops an interpretation of Gilles Deleuze’s work around the problem drawn-up by this phrase. The interpretation is but one of the multiple ways Deleuze’s work can be taken up and read. It neither aims to be comprehensive, nor faithful – in that rather sad and unreflective sense of ‘true to’ as devotedly close to the words or spirit of a master or of master-works. Instead, a series of tensions and contradictions that define the problem will guide discussions of relations between Deleuze and six other philosophers (Kant, Bachelard, Whitehead, Levinas, Lewis and Harman). The restricted terms of the discussions should not be taken as signs of irrelevance at the level of the problem. Quite the contrary: the problem reverberates throughout Deleuze’s many works and contributions. Where these impact on life, so does the problem, with its tensions and difficulties, but also with its productive power. Since the problem and its conditions are bare and brute, the choice of thinkers is not so much arbitrary as tendentious. Other encounters and influences could have been selected, perhaps with more felicitous outcomes, perhaps not. These are my selections. They are made against a background of philosophical, academic and political motivations, some of which define a small world of academic training and competition, others much wider social and philosophical problems, others, the simple limitations of a brain, a body and the surroundings – near and far – that work on them over a stretch of time. Nonetheless, in charting a way through the twin pressures of how to maximally diminish the restraining and exclusive tendencies of metaphysics, whilst also creating structures that interact in an enriching and deepening manner with others, the selection seemed the one best suited to each of the main threats to a successful response to the original metaphysical problem. This focus on problems and their internal tensions explains the decisions not to include certain major influences (Nietzsche and Bergson, for example) and encounters 8 (Heidegger, Derrida and Foucault, to cite some of the major omissions). Whilst each of these will be or has been the subject of important work on Deleuze, their meetings with him seemed to take the question of metaphysics towards problems that I was not attracted to, or capable of covering in depth. In may cases, others have already done so, much better than I could or than my focus would allow1. A gesture towards the reasons for selection, or at least the ones that I am conscious of, could be that this book rests on the premises that there is a Deleuzian metaphysics, that it plays an important and irreplaceable role in his philosophy, and that it raises significant but not fatal problems2. But what do ‘open’, ‘determined’ and ‘metaphysics’ mean in the context of Deleuze’s work? Here, a metaphysics is taken to be a dynamic structure of relations between philosophical concepts and ideas. It is the productive heart of a philosophical system, not understood as the most important basic forms, but as the interaction of the most productive and original ones, with one another, but also with more distant and secondary orders. A metaphysics is therefore not a separate order or set of concepts and ideas. Nor is it a world-view, or a simplified representation of life, or a philosophical response to physical theories. It is rather the genetic core of a philosophical system in its ongoing transformative relation to the worlds it draws up and that, in return, feed into it (whether these worlds be actual, virtual, possible or real – or, as we shall see, all four). For example, were a philosophy to be constructed around two substances (mind and body, say), the idea of metaphysics used here would lead to studies of the relations between these terms and of their wider repercussions. Judgments that the world could be divided into mind and body, or that truth could be defined in terms of one but not the other, or that one was superior to the other, would be less important that the way mind and body interacted and how that relation led to series of further dynamic effects. Questions of openness would enter in terms of which relations and what kinds of relations were not allowed by the philosophy, of which relations operated in setting up the core ones, and which transformed them. 9 This is not to say that any metaphysics could exhaust or capture, represent or condense, direct or control the wider worlds or world that it interacts with. The relations are much more complex and multi-directional. Different pressures accompany different-scaled effects and affections across systems with no key or chart to finally decide on importance and on priorities. A flash of inspiration in only one body at a particular time can run through a philosophical system, just as it does through a set of literary works or a life. Equally, though, an idea, sometime a vile and terrible idea, can have strong metaphysical roots and go on to poison minds, bodies and societies, driving them to terrible destruction. Yet, one of the claims here is that metaphysics matters because, as a genetic core in process, it is to be distinguished from other structures within a system of worlds and lives. The distinguishing features of a metaphysics are its consistency, economy and reach. The elements of the metaphysical structure are very tightly related (perhaps logically, but also through many other forms of internal relations, semantically, for example). It may not even be possible to separate the elements and retain their sense. A principle of economy runs alongside this consistency. There can be no inoperative idea or redundant concept, nor unproductive or uninteresting contradiction or paradox. Finally, metaphysical structures are disproportionately powerful. They resonate through other structures to an extent and with a transformative power that is unmatched by others, both in terms of manner and of effect.
Recommended publications
  • Hume's Objects After Deleuze
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Master's Theses Graduate School March 2021 Hume's Objects After Deleuze Michael P. Harter Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Harter, Michael P., "Hume's Objects After Deleuze" (2021). LSU Master's Theses. 5305. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses/5305 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Master's Theses by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. HUME’S OBJECTS AFTER DELEUZE A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in The Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies by Michael Patrick Harter B.A., California State University, Fresno, 2018 May 2021 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Human beings are wholly dependent creatures. In our becoming, we are affected by an incredible number of beings who aid and foster our growth. It would be impossible to devise a list of all such individuals. However, those who played imperative roles in the creation of this work deserve their due recognition. First, I would like to thank my partner, Leena, and our pets Merleau and the late Kiki. Throughout the ebbs and flows of my academic career, you have remained sources of love, joy, encouragement, and calm.
    [Show full text]
  • William James As American Plato? Scott Sinclair
    WILLIAM JAMES AS AMERICAN PLATO? ______________________________________________________________________________ SCOTT SINCLAIR ABSTRACT Alfred North Whitehead wrote a letter to Charles Hartshorne in 1936 in which he referred to William James as the American Plato. Especially given Whitehead’s admiration of Plato, this was a high compliment to James. What was the basis for this compliment and analogy? In responding to that question beyond the partial and scattered references provided by Whitehead, this article briefly explores the following aspects of the thought of James in relation to Whitehead: the one and the many, the denial of Cartesian dualism, James’s background in physiology, refutation of Zeno’s paradoxes, religious experience, and other kinships. In the end, the author agrees with Robert Neville that James had seminal ideas which could correctly result in a complimentary analogy with Plato. Therefore, a greater focus on the important thought of James is a needed challenge in contemporary philosophy. Michel Weber provided a very helpful article in two parts entitled, “Whitehead’s Reading of James and Its Context,” in the spring 2002 and fall 2003 editions of Streams of William James. Weber began his article with a reference to Bertrand Russell: “When Bertrand Russell (1872-1970) visited Harvard in 1936, ‘there were two heroes in his lectures – Plato and James.’”1 Although he goes on to affirm that Whitehead could have said the same, Weber either overlooks the fact, or is not aware, that Whitehead actually did compare James to Plato in his January 2, 1936 hand-written letter to Charles Hartshorne, as printed by Whitehead’s biographer, Victor Lowe: European philosophy has gone dry, and cannot make any worthwhile use of the results of nineteenth century scholarship.
    [Show full text]
  • Deleuze and the Simulacrum Between the Phantasm and Fantasy (A Genealogical Reading)
    Tijdschrift voor Filosofie, 81/2019, p. 131-149 DELEUZE AND THE SIMULACRUM BETWEEN THE PHANTASM AND FANTASY (A GENEALOGICAL READING) by Daniel Villegas Vélez (Leuven) What is the difference between the phantasm and the simulacrum in Deleuze’s famous reversal of Platonism? At the end of “Plato and the Simulacrum,” Deleuze argues that philosophy must extract from moder- nity “something that Nietzsche designated as the untimely.”1 The his- toricity of the untimely, Deleuze specifies, obtains differently with respect to the past, present, and future: the untimely is attained with respect to the past by the reversal of Platonism and with respect to the present, “by the simulacrum conceived as the edge of critical moder- nity.” In relation to the future, however, it is attained “by the phantasm of the eternal return as belief in the future.” At stake, is a certain dis- tinction between the simulacrum, whose power, as Deleuze tells us in this crucial paragraph, defines modernity, and the phantasm, which is Daniel Villegas Vélez (1984) holds a PhD from the Univ. of Pennsylvania and is postdoctoral researcher at the Institute of Philosophy, KU Leuven, where he forms part of the erc Research Pro- ject Homo Mimeticus (hom). Recent publications include “The Matter of Timbre: Listening, Genea- logy, Sound,” in The Oxford Handbook of Timbre, ed. Emily Dolan and Alexander Rehding (Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 2018), doi: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780190637224.013.20 and “Allegory, Noise, and History: TheArcades Project Looks Back at the Trauerspielbuch,” New Writing Special Issue: Convo- luting the Dialectical Image (2019), doi: 10.1080/14790726.2019.1567795.
    [Show full text]
  • Overturning the Paradigm of Identity with Gilles Deleuze's Differential
    A Thesis entitled Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy Dr. Ammon Allred, Committee Chair Dr. Benjamin Grazzini, Committee Member Dr. Benjamin Pryor, Committee Member Dr. Patricia R. Komuniecki, Dean College of Graduate Studies The University of Toledo May 2014 An Abstract of Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy The University of Toledo May 2014 Taking Gilles Deleuze to be a philosopher who is most concerned with articulating a ‘philosophy of difference’, Deleuze’s thought represents a fundamental shift in the history of philosophy, a shift which asserts ontological difference as independent of any prior ontological identity, even going as far as suggesting that identity is only possible when grounded by difference. Deleuze reconstructs a ‘minor’ history of philosophy, mobilizing thinkers from Spinoza and Nietzsche to Duns Scotus and Bergson, in his attempt to assert that philosophy has always been, underneath its canonical manifestations, a project concerned with ontology, and that ontological difference deserves the kind of philosophical attention, and privilege, which ontological identity has been given since Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • Gilles Deleuze's
    Gilles Deleuze’s Empiricism and Subjectivity 55194_Roffe194_Roffe andand Deleuze.inddDeleuze.indd i 115/10/165/10/16 4:574:57 PPMM Leopards break into the temple and drink all the sacrifi cial vessels dry; it keeps happening; in the end, it can be calculated in advance and is incorporated into the ritual. Franz Kafka 55194_Roffe194_Roffe andand Deleuze.inddDeleuze.indd iiii 115/10/165/10/16 4:574:57 PPMM Gilles Deleuze’s Empiricism and Subjectivity A Critical Introduction and Guide JON ROFFE 55194_Roffe194_Roffe andand Deleuze.inddDeleuze.indd iiiiii 115/10/165/10/16 4:574:57 PPMM Edinburgh University Press is one of the leading university presses in the UK. We publish academic books and journals in our selected subject areas across the humanities and social sciences, combining cutting-edge scholarship with high editorial and production values to produce academic works of lasting importance. For more information visit our website: www.edinburghuniversitypress.com © Jon Roffe, 2016 Edinburgh University Press Ltd The Tun – Holyrood Road, 12(2f) Jackson’s Entry, Edinburgh EH8 8PJ Typeset in 11.5/15 Adobe Sabon by IDSUK (DataConnection) Ltd, and printed and bound in Great Britain by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon CR0 4YY A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN 978 1 4744 0582 9 (hardback) ISBN 978 1 4744 0584 3 (webready PDF) ISBN 978 1 4744 0583 6 (paperback) ISBN 978 1 4744 0585 0 (epub) The right of Jon Roffe to be identifi ed as the author of this work has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, and the Copyright and Related Rights Regulations 2003 (SI No.
    [Show full text]
  • Deleuze's Theory of Sensation: Overcoming the Kantian Duality
    3 Deleuze's Theory of Sensation: Overcoming the Kantian Duality Daniel W Smith Aesthetics since Kant has been haunted by a seemingly irretractable dualism. On the one hand. aesthetics designates the theory of sensib­ ility as the form of possible experience; on the other hand, it desig­ nates the theory of art as a rdl ection on real experience. The first is the objective element of sensation. which is conditioned by the a priori Conns of space and time (the 'T ranscendental Aesthetic ' aCthe en"rique of Pure Reason); the second is the subjective element of sensation, which is expressed in the feeling of pleasure and pain (the 'Critiqu e of Aesthetic Judgment' in the Critique of Judgment) , Gilles Deleuze ar­ gues that these two aspects of the theory of sensation (aesthetics) can � reunited only at the pric e of a radic al recasting of the transcenden­ tal project as form!Jlated by Kant, pushing it in the direction of what Schelling once called a 'superior empiricism': it is only when the conditions of experience in general become the genetic conditions of experience that they can be reunited with the structures of works real of an. In this case, the principles of sensation would at the same time Constitute the principles of composition of the work of art, and conver­ sely it would be the structure of the work of that reveals these conditions. I In what follows, I would like to examinean the means by �'hich Deleuze anempts to overcome this duality in aesthetics. follow­ this single thread through the network of his thought, even if in tramgcin g this line we sacrifice a cenain amount of detail in favor of a nain perspicuity.
    [Show full text]
  • The Apocryphal Whitehead Michel Weberi
    Contact Made Vision: The Apocryphal Whitehead Michel Weberi Religion is what the individual does with his own solitariness. It runs through three stages, if it evolves to its final satisfaction. It is the transition from God the void to God the enemy, and from God the enemy to God the companion. (RM 16)1 Introduction The present Whiteheadian dialogue between natural process theology and Whiteheadian scholarship exploits a tangential approach that will provide new ways of contrasting Whitehead’s worldview by adding a third unexpected speaker: Thomas, the Gnostic Jew who wrote his Gospel perhaps as early as 60 years after Jesus’ death and could thus have constituted an earlier corpus than the canonical gospels—and their hypothetical Q.2 Some readers might consider that the price to pay is too high to venture oneself on such a cross-interpretative path: there is no need to impose an unfashionable syncretic burden either on Whitehead or on Thomas; the inflexion required on each of them to bring them together is simply too demanding and totally unscientific anyway. At least four answers immediately come to mind: first, there is no such thing as a totally objective interpretation in these matters (even the “hard-core” scientific enterprise does not completely escape from the social construction of its issues); second, this hermeneutical wager carries important consequences for each party; third, the rapprochement is operational only at the level of the fundamental intuition—of course not at the level of the technicalities (for the most part absent in Thomas anyway); fourth, what matters above all is to highlight new ways of understanding the human condition, not to stick sclerotically to dead abstractions.
    [Show full text]
  • Reason and Affect in a Shipboard Conversion Narrative
    journal of jesuit studies 2 (2015) 641-658 brill.com/jjs Father of My Soul: Reason and Affect in a Shipboard Conversion Narrative J. Michelle Molina Northwestern University [email protected] Abstract In 1768, a young Swedish Lutheran, inspired by Voltaire, took up life as a merchant to learn more about the world and to find “true religion” based upon reason. When he boarded a ship to Corsica, his travelling companions were two hundred Mexican Jesuits recently expelled from the Americas. In close confines with these members of the Society of Jesus for the duration of his five-week journey, Thjülen chose to convert to Catholicism and, shortly after arriving in Italy, he became a Jesuit. This essay explores the nature of his conversion, utilizing affect theory to argue that he converted less to Catholicism than to the Society of Jesus, or—more precisely—Thjülen converted to remain in proximity to a particular Mexican Jesuit named Manuel Mariano (Emmanuele) de Iturriaga. Keywords Lorenzo Ignazio Thjülen – Manuel Mariano (Emmanuele) de Iturriaga – ex-Jesuit – expulsion – conversion – affect – conatus – religious friendship – homo-sociability – Enlightenment Catholicism In 1768, a young Lutheran Swedish merchant named Lars Birger Thjülen (1746– 1833) left the Spanish port of Cádiz on a boat destined for the French island of Corsica. He found himself among two hundred Jesuits who, recently expelled from Mexico, were en route to their exile in Bologna, Italy. The possibilities for Jesuit spiritual and intellectual engagement with the world had changed dra- matically at the end of the eighteenth century. The Jesuits Thjülen encoun- tered on the ship from Cádiz to Corsica were among two thousand members © Molina, 2015 | doi 10.1163/22141332-00204006 This is an open access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution- Noncommercial 4.0 Unported (CC-BY-NC 4.0) License.
    [Show full text]
  • In a Thousand Plateaus: Agency Without Subject
    Ethics to Politics in A Thousand Plateaus: Agency without Subject Title: Ethics to Politics in A Thousand Plateaus: Agency without Subject Abstract: In A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari offer a cosmology that denies an opposition between the one and the many. Their cosmology, which is ethical in nature and which appears to radically revise key Kantian paradigms, identifies being with the action of becoming, rather than with the intention of an autonomous will. While we find concepts of autonomy and agency within this cosmology, the modern connotations of those concepts have been altered. In this new context, agency and autonomy function without need of the modern concept of subject, especially insofar as that concept connotes negativity (or lack), both metaphysically and politically. Deleuze and Guattari offer an alternative to many tenets of Kantian moral philosophy and Aristotelian metaphysics, but in locating the possibility of a political model suited to Deleuze and Guattari’s cosmology, here I will suggest a conjunction of their rendering of existence with ethical, social, and political aspects of Aristotle’s and Kant’s philosophies. In short, Deleuze and Guattari’s apparently radical anti-Kantian cosmology—a cosmology also apparently anti-Aristotelian—turns out to be much less so upon close examination. 1 Ethics to Politics in A Thousand Plateaus: Agency without Subject Ethics to Politics in A Thousand Plateaus: Agency without Subject Although he is not the first to insist upon the necessity of agency for morality, the manner in which Immanuel Kant renders individual autonomy raises it to its modern metaphysical peak, which arguably necessitates a subject—the specific individual in whom an autonomous will inheres.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem: the Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations 2013 The rP oblem: The Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze Ryan J. Johnson Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Johnson, R. (2013). The rP oblem: The Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/706 This Immediate Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College & Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Ryan J. Johnson May 2014 Copyright by Ryan J. Johnson 2014 ii THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE By Ryan J. Johnson Approved December 6, 2013 _______________________________ ______________________________ Daniel Selcer, Ph.D Kelly Arenson, Ph.D Associate Professor of Philosophy Assistant Professor of Philosophy (Committee Chair) (Committee Member) ______________________________ John Protevi, Ph.D Professor of Philosophy (Committee Member) ______________________________ ______________________________ James Swindal, Ph.D. Ronald Polansky, Ph.D. Dean, McAnulty College & Graduate Chair, Department of Philosophy School of Liberal Arts Professor of Philosophy Professor of Philosophy iii ABSTRACT THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE By Ryan J. Johnson May 2014 Dissertation supervised by Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Gilles Deleuze
    CHAPTER 6 GILLES DELEUZE Learning from the Unconscious For the philosopher Gilles Deleuze, rational Cartesian consciousness as the sole constituent of thought is insufficient because what is yet “unthought” is equally capable of producing practical effects at the level of human experiences. Deleuze considers “an unconscious of thought [to be] just as profound as the unknown of the body” (Deleuze, 1988a, p. 19; italics Deleuze’s). The quality of profundity is signi- ficant and relates Deleuze’s particular mode of production of human subjectivity, that he together with social psychologist Felix Guattari called “schizoanalysis”, to Jung’s depth psychology. Kerslake (2007) notices that Deleuze’s conception of the unconscious is closer to the Jungian rather than the Freudian. Jung’s dynamic process of the individuation of the Self as the goal of analysis is akin to Deleuze’s concept of becoming, and specifically becoming-other as a process of learning from the un- conscious embedded in experience. The Jungian collective unconscious is by definition transpersonal, thus exceeding the scope of traditional Freudian psychoanalytic conception as narrowly personal and simply repressed. Contrary to behaviorist psychology positing an individual as born in the state of a blank slate, tabula rasa, the Jungian unconscious is always already inhabited by archetypes. Analogously Deleuze is adamant that “one never has a tabula rasa; one slips in, enters in the middle” (Deleuze, 1988a, p. 123, italics Deleuze’s). According to Deleuze, the world consists not of substantial “things” but of relational entities, or multiplicities, and the production of subjectivity is necessarily embedded amidst the relational, experimental and experiential, dynamics.
    [Show full text]
  • Deleuze and Anarchism and Anarchism Deleuze Edited by Chantelle Gray Van Heerden and Aragorn Eloff
    Deleuze Connections Deleuze Deleuze Connections Series Editor: Ian Buchanan and Deleuze and Anarchism Anarchism Deleuze Edited by Chantelle Gray van Heerden and Aragorn Eloff ’With pleasing rigour and sly provocation, this essential volume frees the child from Oedipal jail. The child now boldly, and no less beautifully, lucidly sits in and Anarchism radical hands.’ Kathryn Bond Stockton, University of Utah ‘This timely new book frees the affective play of childhood from the conceptual persona of the child, reminding readers that the age of childhood never passes. Herein lies a strategy, reiterated on every page, for the invention of new social and political worlds grounded in the praxis of the becoming-child.’ Cameron Duff, RMIT University The first collection of essays to focus on Deleuze’s writing on children and childhood This collection gives an accessible account of the key characterisations of children and childhood made in Deleuze and Guattari‘s work. These concepts are then van Heerden and Eloff applied to concerns that have shaped the child in various disciplines and in interdisciplinary scholarship. Bringing together established and new voices, the essays take up concepts from Deleuze and Guattari’s work to question the popular idea that children are innocent adults-in-the-making caught in an Oedipal grid. Authors working in philosophy, literature, education, sociology, gender and sexuality, music and film studies consider aspects of children‘s lives such as time, language, affect, atmosphere, gender, sexuality and schooling, offering critical approaches to the pervasive interest in the teleology of upward growth of the child. Markus P. J. Bohlmann is Professor of English at Seneca College, Toronto, Canada.
    [Show full text]