Gilles Deleuze's

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Gilles Deleuze's Gilles Deleuze’s Empiricism and Subjectivity 55194_Roffe194_Roffe andand Deleuze.inddDeleuze.indd i 115/10/165/10/16 4:574:57 PPMM Leopards break into the temple and drink all the sacrifi cial vessels dry; it keeps happening; in the end, it can be calculated in advance and is incorporated into the ritual. Franz Kafka 55194_Roffe194_Roffe andand Deleuze.inddDeleuze.indd iiii 115/10/165/10/16 4:574:57 PPMM Gilles Deleuze’s Empiricism and Subjectivity A Critical Introduction and Guide JON ROFFE 55194_Roffe194_Roffe andand Deleuze.inddDeleuze.indd iiiiii 115/10/165/10/16 4:574:57 PPMM Edinburgh University Press is one of the leading university presses in the UK. We publish academic books and journals in our selected subject areas across the humanities and social sciences, combining cutting-edge scholarship with high editorial and production values to produce academic works of lasting importance. For more information visit our website: www.edinburghuniversitypress.com © Jon Roffe, 2016 Edinburgh University Press Ltd The Tun – Holyrood Road, 12(2f) Jackson’s Entry, Edinburgh EH8 8PJ Typeset in 11.5/15 Adobe Sabon by IDSUK (DataConnection) Ltd, and printed and bound in Great Britain by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon CR0 4YY A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN 978 1 4744 0582 9 (hardback) ISBN 978 1 4744 0584 3 (webready PDF) ISBN 978 1 4744 0583 6 (paperback) ISBN 978 1 4744 0585 0 (epub) The right of Jon Roffe to be identifi ed as the author of this work has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, and the Copyright and Related Rights Regulations 2003 (SI No. 2498). 55194_Roffe194_Roffe andand Deleuze.inddDeleuze.indd iviv 115/10/165/10/16 4:574:57 PPMM Contents Acknowledgements vii Note on References ix Preface xi 1. Beyond Kant’s Hume 1 2. Belief and Theoretical Reason 19 3. The Moral World 37 4. The Madness of Thought and the Delirium of Practical Reason 81 5. Subjectivity 103 6. The Singularity of Empiricism 129 7. A Kantian Hume 149 Index 165 55194_Roffe194_Roffe andand Deleuze.inddDeleuze.indd v 115/10/165/10/16 4:574:57 PPMM 55194_Roffe194_Roffe andand Deleuze.inddDeleuze.indd vivi 115/10/165/10/16 4:574:57 PPMM Acknowledgements My thanks go to Carol Macdonald for talking me into writing this book, and for her patience during the distended period of time it took me to make good on the promise. I dedicate this book to Virginia, who kept me still and sane enough to write it. I would also like to acknowledge the support of the Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences at the University of New South Wales for supporting the publication of this work, and Haydie Gooder for preparing the excellent index. vii 55194_Roffe194_Roffe andand Deleuze.inddDeleuze.indd viivii 115/10/165/10/16 4:574:57 PPMM 55194_Roffe194_Roffe andand Deleuze.inddDeleuze.indd viiiviii 115/10/165/10/16 4:574:57 PPMM Note on References In what follows, Deleuze’s book will be referred to each time with a pair of page numbers, the French original followed by Constantin Boundas’s English translation – for example (ES 23/21). I have frequently modifi ed the translation, but whenever the change turns around a signifi cant point, a note will be appended. Whenever a single page number appears, it should be taken to refer just to the French original, with the exception of references that use lower-case Roman numer- als. These indicate the preface to the English translation that Deleuze contributed in 1991. Boundas has done a great service to readers of Empiricism and Subjectivity by tracking down the original English passages in Hume’s work that Deleuze cites in André Leroy’s translation, allowing for an easy location of these texts. Here, I will follow the now standard procedure of citing from the Clarendon Edi- tion of the Works of David Hume. References to A Treatise of Human Nature will take the form (T 1.3.1.1), indicating the book, chapter, section and paragraph respectively. References to Enquiry concerning Human Understanding will refer to sec- tion and paragraph (e.g. EHU 2.6); the Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals will invoke section, part and paragraph (EPM 3.1.4). ix 55194_Roffe194_Roffe andand Deleuze.inddDeleuze.indd ixix 115/10/165/10/16 4:574:57 PPMM 55194_Roffe194_Roffe andand Deleuze.inddDeleuze.indd x 115/10/165/10/16 4:574:57 PPMM Preface Gilles Deleuze published his fi rst book Empiricism and Sub- jectivity: An Essay on Hume’s Theory of Human Nature in 1953, the year that he turned twenty-eight.1 There is a pleasing symmetry here: David Hume was the same age when the fi rst two books of his precocious masterpiece A Treatise of Human Nature (1739) initially appeared.2 A book on David Hume might seem an unusual, even bizarre, choice for a young French philosopher, educated at the height of the dynastic rule of les trois H in French philosophy – Hegel, Husserl, Heidegger. Even today, you would have to extend the list of infl uential Hs in French philosophy for a very long time before Hume’s name would appear on it. The least we can say is that Deleuze’s disregard for intellectual fashion and what would today, even more than then, pass for sensible career decisions was already in full fl ower in his philosophical youth. This is not to say that the work had no precursors or patrons in Deleuze’s milieu. Deleuze occasionally refers to the infl uence of Jean Wahl, whose Preface to Vers le concret (1932) includes a brief remark about Hume’s empiricism that strikingly resembles the line of argument that will appear in Empiricism and Sub- jectivity. Despite the fact that Wahl’s doctoral thesis The Plu- ralist Philosophies of England and America (1920) explicitly marginalises Hume’s contribution,3 Deleuze will write that he xi 55194_Roffe194_Roffe andand Deleuze.inddDeleuze.indd xixi 115/10/165/10/16 4:574:57 PPMM Preface ‘had the ability to make us think, in French, things which were very new’.4 But Empiricism and Subjectivity is not dedicated to Wahl but to one of Deleuze’s teachers and a champion of the young idiosyncrat, the towering Hegelian Jean Hyppolite – ‘in sincere and respectful homage’. This dedication is something of a riddle, and one that we will later try to solve. * The translator’s introduction by Constantin Boundas is the fi rst text on Empiricism and Subjectivity that connects the book to a range of themes prominent in Deleuze’s mature work, but the truth is that there is at fi rst blush little in either Hume’s philoso- phy or Deleuze’s account of it that directly resembles his later, more well-known works. Readers of these works are likely to fi nd themselves confronted to some degree by the foreign char- acter of Deleuze’s argument. Conversely, the Hume that lives on in contemporary, predominantly analytic, Anglo-American philosophy departments is not easily recognisable in his Deleu- zian portrait either. This book hopes to present an account of Empiricism and Subjectivity that will be of interest and illu- mination to readers coming from either direction. That said, the aim here is not to set up a comparison between Deleuze’s reading and those prominent in the Anglo-American tradition from Beattie to Baier. The reader familiar with this trajectory will nevertheless fi nd it gradually appear in the discussions of naturalism and Hume’s moral thought that will emerge as we tease out Deleuze’s argument. Neither is the goal of this book the connecting up of ideas in Empiricism and Subjectiv- ity and those we fi nd later in his work. Readers interested in either or both of these approaches will fi nd them in Jeffrey Bell’s Deleuze’s Hume: Philosophy, Culture and the Scottish Enlight- enment. Again, though, and particularly in the later chapters, a few points will emerge in passing that address the way in which Deleuze’s reading of Hume might open onto his later work. Finally, the presentation that follows will not put Deleuze’s Hume in the docks of comparative scholarship. Judging the xii 55194_Roffe194_Roffe andand Deleuze.inddDeleuze.indd xiixii 115/10/165/10/16 4:574:57 PPMM Preface fi delity of his reading of Hume is not the goal. No, my aim here is more modest: to schematically present the argument of Deleuze’s little text. His writing, here as elsewhere, is remark- ably dense. Rarely does he repeat a point, and rarely does he need more than a page to present even complex arguments. At the same time, his interpretation of Hume, though brief, is remarkably wide-ranging. While the Treatise is his central refer- ence, he ranges across the whole of Hume’s writings, including the two Enquiries, the Dialogues concerning Natural Religion, and his political and economic essays.5 And while he does not dwell on the content of Hume’s history of England, he does make an important place for it in his inclusive reading of Humean thought. We can add to this the fact that, as is often the case in Deleuze’s works, the order of argumentation is unusual and, to some extent at least, misleading. The logic of this order is certainly present in Empiricism and Subjectivity, but it is woven through the book, and only appears to the reader once a certain level of comprehension is already gained. Conse- quently, to replay in full Deleuze’s reading of Hume in its richness and idiosyncrasy would require a book signifi cantly longer than the original, and the one in your possession is already (embarrassingly) longer than it should be.
Recommended publications
  • Hume's Objects After Deleuze
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Master's Theses Graduate School March 2021 Hume's Objects After Deleuze Michael P. Harter Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Harter, Michael P., "Hume's Objects After Deleuze" (2021). LSU Master's Theses. 5305. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses/5305 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Master's Theses by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. HUME’S OBJECTS AFTER DELEUZE A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in The Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies by Michael Patrick Harter B.A., California State University, Fresno, 2018 May 2021 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Human beings are wholly dependent creatures. In our becoming, we are affected by an incredible number of beings who aid and foster our growth. It would be impossible to devise a list of all such individuals. However, those who played imperative roles in the creation of this work deserve their due recognition. First, I would like to thank my partner, Leena, and our pets Merleau and the late Kiki. Throughout the ebbs and flows of my academic career, you have remained sources of love, joy, encouragement, and calm.
    [Show full text]
  • Deleuze and the Simulacrum Between the Phantasm and Fantasy (A Genealogical Reading)
    Tijdschrift voor Filosofie, 81/2019, p. 131-149 DELEUZE AND THE SIMULACRUM BETWEEN THE PHANTASM AND FANTASY (A GENEALOGICAL READING) by Daniel Villegas Vélez (Leuven) What is the difference between the phantasm and the simulacrum in Deleuze’s famous reversal of Platonism? At the end of “Plato and the Simulacrum,” Deleuze argues that philosophy must extract from moder- nity “something that Nietzsche designated as the untimely.”1 The his- toricity of the untimely, Deleuze specifies, obtains differently with respect to the past, present, and future: the untimely is attained with respect to the past by the reversal of Platonism and with respect to the present, “by the simulacrum conceived as the edge of critical moder- nity.” In relation to the future, however, it is attained “by the phantasm of the eternal return as belief in the future.” At stake, is a certain dis- tinction between the simulacrum, whose power, as Deleuze tells us in this crucial paragraph, defines modernity, and the phantasm, which is Daniel Villegas Vélez (1984) holds a PhD from the Univ. of Pennsylvania and is postdoctoral researcher at the Institute of Philosophy, KU Leuven, where he forms part of the erc Research Pro- ject Homo Mimeticus (hom). Recent publications include “The Matter of Timbre: Listening, Genea- logy, Sound,” in The Oxford Handbook of Timbre, ed. Emily Dolan and Alexander Rehding (Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 2018), doi: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780190637224.013.20 and “Allegory, Noise, and History: TheArcades Project Looks Back at the Trauerspielbuch,” New Writing Special Issue: Convo- luting the Dialectical Image (2019), doi: 10.1080/14790726.2019.1567795.
    [Show full text]
  • Overturning the Paradigm of Identity with Gilles Deleuze's Differential
    A Thesis entitled Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy Dr. Ammon Allred, Committee Chair Dr. Benjamin Grazzini, Committee Member Dr. Benjamin Pryor, Committee Member Dr. Patricia R. Komuniecki, Dean College of Graduate Studies The University of Toledo May 2014 An Abstract of Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy The University of Toledo May 2014 Taking Gilles Deleuze to be a philosopher who is most concerned with articulating a ‘philosophy of difference’, Deleuze’s thought represents a fundamental shift in the history of philosophy, a shift which asserts ontological difference as independent of any prior ontological identity, even going as far as suggesting that identity is only possible when grounded by difference. Deleuze reconstructs a ‘minor’ history of philosophy, mobilizing thinkers from Spinoza and Nietzsche to Duns Scotus and Bergson, in his attempt to assert that philosophy has always been, underneath its canonical manifestations, a project concerned with ontology, and that ontological difference deserves the kind of philosophical attention, and privilege, which ontological identity has been given since Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • Deleuze's Theory of Sensation: Overcoming the Kantian Duality
    3 Deleuze's Theory of Sensation: Overcoming the Kantian Duality Daniel W Smith Aesthetics since Kant has been haunted by a seemingly irretractable dualism. On the one hand. aesthetics designates the theory of sensib­ ility as the form of possible experience; on the other hand, it desig­ nates the theory of art as a rdl ection on real experience. The first is the objective element of sensation. which is conditioned by the a priori Conns of space and time (the 'T ranscendental Aesthetic ' aCthe en"rique of Pure Reason); the second is the subjective element of sensation, which is expressed in the feeling of pleasure and pain (the 'Critiqu e of Aesthetic Judgment' in the Critique of Judgment) , Gilles Deleuze ar­ gues that these two aspects of the theory of sensation (aesthetics) can � reunited only at the pric e of a radic al recasting of the transcenden­ tal project as form!Jlated by Kant, pushing it in the direction of what Schelling once called a 'superior empiricism': it is only when the conditions of experience in general become the genetic conditions of experience that they can be reunited with the structures of works real of an. In this case, the principles of sensation would at the same time Constitute the principles of composition of the work of art, and conver­ sely it would be the structure of the work of that reveals these conditions. I In what follows, I would like to examinean the means by �'hich Deleuze anempts to overcome this duality in aesthetics. follow­ this single thread through the network of his thought, even if in tramgcin g this line we sacrifice a cenain amount of detail in favor of a nain perspicuity.
    [Show full text]
  • Reason and Affect in a Shipboard Conversion Narrative
    journal of jesuit studies 2 (2015) 641-658 brill.com/jjs Father of My Soul: Reason and Affect in a Shipboard Conversion Narrative J. Michelle Molina Northwestern University [email protected] Abstract In 1768, a young Swedish Lutheran, inspired by Voltaire, took up life as a merchant to learn more about the world and to find “true religion” based upon reason. When he boarded a ship to Corsica, his travelling companions were two hundred Mexican Jesuits recently expelled from the Americas. In close confines with these members of the Society of Jesus for the duration of his five-week journey, Thjülen chose to convert to Catholicism and, shortly after arriving in Italy, he became a Jesuit. This essay explores the nature of his conversion, utilizing affect theory to argue that he converted less to Catholicism than to the Society of Jesus, or—more precisely—Thjülen converted to remain in proximity to a particular Mexican Jesuit named Manuel Mariano (Emmanuele) de Iturriaga. Keywords Lorenzo Ignazio Thjülen – Manuel Mariano (Emmanuele) de Iturriaga – ex-Jesuit – expulsion – conversion – affect – conatus – religious friendship – homo-sociability – Enlightenment Catholicism In 1768, a young Lutheran Swedish merchant named Lars Birger Thjülen (1746– 1833) left the Spanish port of Cádiz on a boat destined for the French island of Corsica. He found himself among two hundred Jesuits who, recently expelled from Mexico, were en route to their exile in Bologna, Italy. The possibilities for Jesuit spiritual and intellectual engagement with the world had changed dra- matically at the end of the eighteenth century. The Jesuits Thjülen encoun- tered on the ship from Cádiz to Corsica were among two thousand members © Molina, 2015 | doi 10.1163/22141332-00204006 This is an open access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution- Noncommercial 4.0 Unported (CC-BY-NC 4.0) License.
    [Show full text]
  • In a Thousand Plateaus: Agency Without Subject
    Ethics to Politics in A Thousand Plateaus: Agency without Subject Title: Ethics to Politics in A Thousand Plateaus: Agency without Subject Abstract: In A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari offer a cosmology that denies an opposition between the one and the many. Their cosmology, which is ethical in nature and which appears to radically revise key Kantian paradigms, identifies being with the action of becoming, rather than with the intention of an autonomous will. While we find concepts of autonomy and agency within this cosmology, the modern connotations of those concepts have been altered. In this new context, agency and autonomy function without need of the modern concept of subject, especially insofar as that concept connotes negativity (or lack), both metaphysically and politically. Deleuze and Guattari offer an alternative to many tenets of Kantian moral philosophy and Aristotelian metaphysics, but in locating the possibility of a political model suited to Deleuze and Guattari’s cosmology, here I will suggest a conjunction of their rendering of existence with ethical, social, and political aspects of Aristotle’s and Kant’s philosophies. In short, Deleuze and Guattari’s apparently radical anti-Kantian cosmology—a cosmology also apparently anti-Aristotelian—turns out to be much less so upon close examination. 1 Ethics to Politics in A Thousand Plateaus: Agency without Subject Ethics to Politics in A Thousand Plateaus: Agency without Subject Although he is not the first to insist upon the necessity of agency for morality, the manner in which Immanuel Kant renders individual autonomy raises it to its modern metaphysical peak, which arguably necessitates a subject—the specific individual in whom an autonomous will inheres.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem: the Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations 2013 The rP oblem: The Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze Ryan J. Johnson Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Johnson, R. (2013). The rP oblem: The Theory of Ideas in Ancient Atomism and Gilles Deleuze (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/706 This Immediate Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College & Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Ryan J. Johnson May 2014 Copyright by Ryan J. Johnson 2014 ii THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE By Ryan J. Johnson Approved December 6, 2013 _______________________________ ______________________________ Daniel Selcer, Ph.D Kelly Arenson, Ph.D Associate Professor of Philosophy Assistant Professor of Philosophy (Committee Chair) (Committee Member) ______________________________ John Protevi, Ph.D Professor of Philosophy (Committee Member) ______________________________ ______________________________ James Swindal, Ph.D. Ronald Polansky, Ph.D. Dean, McAnulty College & Graduate Chair, Department of Philosophy School of Liberal Arts Professor of Philosophy Professor of Philosophy iii ABSTRACT THE PROBLEM: THE THEORY OF IDEAS IN ANCIENT ATOMISM AND GILLES DELEUZE By Ryan J. Johnson May 2014 Dissertation supervised by Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Gilles Deleuze
    CHAPTER 6 GILLES DELEUZE Learning from the Unconscious For the philosopher Gilles Deleuze, rational Cartesian consciousness as the sole constituent of thought is insufficient because what is yet “unthought” is equally capable of producing practical effects at the level of human experiences. Deleuze considers “an unconscious of thought [to be] just as profound as the unknown of the body” (Deleuze, 1988a, p. 19; italics Deleuze’s). The quality of profundity is signi- ficant and relates Deleuze’s particular mode of production of human subjectivity, that he together with social psychologist Felix Guattari called “schizoanalysis”, to Jung’s depth psychology. Kerslake (2007) notices that Deleuze’s conception of the unconscious is closer to the Jungian rather than the Freudian. Jung’s dynamic process of the individuation of the Self as the goal of analysis is akin to Deleuze’s concept of becoming, and specifically becoming-other as a process of learning from the un- conscious embedded in experience. The Jungian collective unconscious is by definition transpersonal, thus exceeding the scope of traditional Freudian psychoanalytic conception as narrowly personal and simply repressed. Contrary to behaviorist psychology positing an individual as born in the state of a blank slate, tabula rasa, the Jungian unconscious is always already inhabited by archetypes. Analogously Deleuze is adamant that “one never has a tabula rasa; one slips in, enters in the middle” (Deleuze, 1988a, p. 123, italics Deleuze’s). According to Deleuze, the world consists not of substantial “things” but of relational entities, or multiplicities, and the production of subjectivity is necessarily embedded amidst the relational, experimental and experiential, dynamics.
    [Show full text]
  • Deleuze and Anarchism and Anarchism Deleuze Edited by Chantelle Gray Van Heerden and Aragorn Eloff
    Deleuze Connections Deleuze Deleuze Connections Series Editor: Ian Buchanan and Deleuze and Anarchism Anarchism Deleuze Edited by Chantelle Gray van Heerden and Aragorn Eloff ’With pleasing rigour and sly provocation, this essential volume frees the child from Oedipal jail. The child now boldly, and no less beautifully, lucidly sits in and Anarchism radical hands.’ Kathryn Bond Stockton, University of Utah ‘This timely new book frees the affective play of childhood from the conceptual persona of the child, reminding readers that the age of childhood never passes. Herein lies a strategy, reiterated on every page, for the invention of new social and political worlds grounded in the praxis of the becoming-child.’ Cameron Duff, RMIT University The first collection of essays to focus on Deleuze’s writing on children and childhood This collection gives an accessible account of the key characterisations of children and childhood made in Deleuze and Guattari‘s work. These concepts are then van Heerden and Eloff applied to concerns that have shaped the child in various disciplines and in interdisciplinary scholarship. Bringing together established and new voices, the essays take up concepts from Deleuze and Guattari’s work to question the popular idea that children are innocent adults-in-the-making caught in an Oedipal grid. Authors working in philosophy, literature, education, sociology, gender and sexuality, music and film studies consider aspects of children‘s lives such as time, language, affect, atmosphere, gender, sexuality and schooling, offering critical approaches to the pervasive interest in the teleology of upward growth of the child. Markus P. J. Bohlmann is Professor of English at Seneca College, Toronto, Canada.
    [Show full text]
  • The Lick of the Mother Tongue: Derrida's Fantasies Of
    The Lick of the Mother Tongue: Derrida’s Fantasies of “the Touch of Language” with 1 Augustine and Marx Rachel Aumiller Introduction Augustine’s Confessions makes the impossible attempt to return to a time before language. Augustine claims that before we are aware of language, we learn our mother tongue through the touch of the mother. This lesson in language that we often first learn through a gentle touch—the nipple of the mother in the mouth of the infant—is later reinforced by a violent touch—the switch of the schoolmaster. Augustine suggests that any memory of a time before “the touch of language” is purely imaginary. And yet his autobiography is driven (by a death drive) to return to a time before the touch of the mother (tongue). While Augustine confesses the personal fantasy of returning to an imaginary time before the touch of the mother (tongue), Karl Marx articulates the communal fantasy of a time to come when we will forget our mother tongue. The fantasy of forgetting the mother tongue is the fantasy of rearticulating ourselves as individuals or a society: the fantasy of self-expression in the creation of a new shared tongue. And yet, as Marx confesses, this fantasy of forgetting the mother tongue that predetermines us is a failed fantasy. We find ourselves bound by the mother tongue, trapped between two imaginary temporalities: the time before and after the touch of language. Jacques Derrida turns to both Augustine and Marx to repeat the fantasy of escaping the mother (tongue). His lectures on Spectres de Marx and his personal autobiography “Circonfession” (or in English, “Circumfession”), both published in the early 1990s, do not explicitly speak to each other (cf.
    [Show full text]
  • Deleuze's Neo-Leibnizianism, Events and <Italic>The Logic of Sense
    This is the published version Bowden, Sean 2010, Deleuze's neo-leibnizianism, events and the logic of sense's 'static ontological genesis', Deleuze studies, vol. 4, no. 3, pp. 301- 328. Available from Deakin Research Online http://hdl.handle.net/10536/DRO/DU:30064858 Reproduced with the kind permission of the copyright owner Copyright: 2010, Edinburgh University Press Deleuze’s Neo-Leibnizianism, Events and The Logic of Sense’s ‘Static Ontological Genesis’ Sean Bowden University of Melbourne and La Trobe University Abstract In The Logic of Sense, Deleuze effectively argues that two types of relation between events govern their ‘evental’ or ‘ideal play’, and ultimately underlie determined substances, that is, worldly individ- uals and persons. Leibniz calls these relations ‘compossibility’ and ‘incompossibility’. Deleuze calls them ‘convergence’ and ‘divergence’. This paper explores how Deleuze appropriates and extends a number of Leibnizian concepts in order to ground the idea that events have ontological priority over substances ‘all the way down’. Keywords: Deleuze, Leibniz, events, ontology, possible worlds, intersubjectivity Deleuze’s philosophical relation to Leibniz has in general been downplayed in the secondary literature.1 Deleuze’s major, pre- Difference and Repetition influences are frequently cited as Nietzsche, Bergson and Spinoza, and that these figures are constant touchstones for Deleuze is undeniable.2 Nevertheless, in his 1968 Spinoza book it is clear that, in certain respects, Deleuze reads Spinoza through Leibniz.3 It is also clear that Leibniz is a major reference in ‘The Method of Dramatization’ (Deleuze 2004), which is effectively a summary of the major themes of Difference and Repetition. In the text of The Logic of Sense, which was published one year after Difference and Repetition, Spinoza is not mentioned at all, and Bergson is cited only once.
    [Show full text]
  • Deleuze's Nietzschean Revaluation: the Image of Thoughtl Thought Without Image
    r Deleuze's Nietzschean Revaluation: The Image of Thoughtl Thought Without Image JEFFREY w. BROWN, University of Waterloo The importance of Nietzsche for the work of Gilles Deleuze is no secret. 1 This importance goes far beyond mere influence or inspiration, however. In Nietzsche, Deleuze finds the provocation to engage in a nomadic, an­ archic mode of discourse that runs counter to the sedentary mode of discourse characteristic of the Western philosophical tradition. Deleuze considers himself a member of a generation "that was more or less blud­ geoned to death with the history of philosophy" (N, 6). Trapped within the cognitive confines of the tradition's repressive framework, Deleuze was "extricated" by Nietzsche (N, 6). Thus extricated, Deleuze-rather than merely parroting the insights of this philosophical provocateur-puts Nietzsche to work, engaging in a series of experiments and explorations that employ various Nietzschean devices (such as the will to power, the eternal return, the ubermensch, and the genealogical method) as their launching pads. 2 Deleuze's dealings with Nietzsche range from relatively conventional (by Deleuze's standards) expositions of Nietzsche's thought (in Nietzsche and PhtYosophy) to radical experimentations which are more characteris­ tically "Deleuzian" than "Nietzschean." In a sense, Nietzsche owes as much to Deleuze as Deleuze does to Nietzsche, maybe more so; for with his experimentations Deleuze extracts from these Nietzschean notions their full effect, telegraphing them on lines of flight that animate them and reveal the range of their power and fecundity. Rescued from the naive, hyperbolic, and ill-conceived introductions they often receive from Nietzsche, these revitalized notions are the leitmotifs in Deleuze's exposi­ tion of the "chaosmos" in which thought is active, productive, and prob­ lematic rather than passive, sedentary, and repressive.
    [Show full text]