Friedrich Schlegel Emergence of Romantic Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Friedrich Schlegel Emergence of Romantic Philosophy Friedrich Schlegel and the Emergence of Romantic Philosophy Elizabeth Millán-Zaibert Friedrich Schlegel and the Emergence of Romantic Philosophy SUNY series, Intersections: Philosophy and Critical Theory Rodolphe Gasché, editor Friedrich Schlegel and the Emergence of Romantic Philosophy ማሜምሞ ELIZABETH MILLÁN-ZAIBERT State University of New York Press Published by State University of New York Press, Albany © 2007 State University of New York All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior permission in writing of the publisher. For information, address State University of New York Press, 194 Washington Avenue, Suite 305, Albany, NY 12210-2384 Production by Judith Block Marketing by Michael Campochiaro Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Millán-Zaibert, Elizabeth. Friedrich Schlegel and the emergence of romantic philosophy / Elizabeth Millán-Zaibert. p. cm. — (SUNY series in intersections—philosophy and critical theory) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN-13: 978-0-7914-7083-1 (hardcover : alk. paper) 1. Schlegel, Friedrich von, 1772–1829. 2. Romanticism—Germany. I. Title. B3086.S54M55 2007 193—dc22 2006021934 10987654321 For Leo and in memory of my grandmother (1916–2005) Contents ማሜምሞ Acknowledgments ix Introduction 1 Philosophy and Early German Romanticism 1 The Literary Dimensions of Early German Romanticism 5 Defining Romanticism 10 Schlegel’s Antifoundationalism 18 Overview 20 1. Finding Room for the Romantics between Kant and Hegel 25 Idealism: From Misconceptions to Post-Kantian Variations 28 Searching for the Unity of Thought and Being: Idealist Jäger versus Romantic Spürhunde 32 Frank’s Romantic Realists versus Beiser’s Romantic Idealists 38 On Why Schlegel Is Not Hegel 44 Romantic Skepticism 48 2. Searching for the Grounds of Knowledge 53 Jacobi’s Salto Mortale 54 Schlegel’s Reaction to the Salto 57 Reinhold’s Elementarphilosophie 62 Aenesidemus and the Shift from Principle to Fact of Consciousness 65 Fichte’s Move from Fact to Act of Consciousness 68 viii Contents 3. Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre: A Tendency to Be Avoided? 71 The Foundations of Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre 72 The Clash between Schmid and Fichte 75 Fichte and Schlegel on Critical Philosophy 79 Fichte’s Mystical Errors 86 The Spirit versus the Letter of Fichte’s Philosophy 91 4. Niethammer’s Influence on the Development of Schlegel’s Skepticism 95 Niethammer’s Skepticism 97 Niethammer’s Appeal to Common Sense 101 Schlegel’s Philosophical Debut 109 Schlegel’s Critique of Niethammer’s Appeal to Common Sense 111 Schlegel’s Historical Taxonomy 114 5. Critique as Metaphilosophy: Kant as Half Critic 117 Revolution, Scientific Method, and Kant’s Critical Project 120 Critiquing the Critical Philosopher 122 Away from Kant: Schlegel’s Historical Turn 127 6. Philosophy in Media Res 133 The Wechselerweis and the Search for Truth 134 Philosophy “in the Middle”: Between Fichte and Spinoza 137 Destroying the Illusion of the Finite: Schlegel’s Critique of the Thing 141 Wilhelm Meister: Schlegel’s Model of Coherence 150 7. The Aesthetic Consequences of Antifoundationalism 159 The Modern Spirit of Romanticism 160 Understanding, Misunderstanding, and Irony 165 Irony and the Necessity of Poetry 170 Notes 175 Bibliography 231 Index 249 Acknowledgments ማሜምሞ y work on Schlegel began in 1993 when I was a graduate student Mat the State University of New York, Buffalo. The present book is a rather distant relative of my first attempts to come to terms with Schlegel’s unconventional philosophy. I am grateful to many people who have helped me to develop work in a field that has only recently appeared on the radar screens of philosophers. Manfred Frank, with whom I first began my studies not only of Friedrich Schlegel’s work, but also of the entire ro- mantic constellation, shaped my philosophical development in important ways, and I hope that in the pages of this book, he can read the debt I have to him. I am also grateful to the German Academic Exchange Ser- vice, for the generous graduate fellowship they provided so that I could begin my initial explorations of early German romantic philosophy. Rodolphe Gasché has supported my work from the beginning in many ways, and I am thankful for his support, not only in helping me to develop some of my views but also in helping me find venues to publish my work. I am also grateful to Jorge Gracia, who, while far removed philosophically from figures such as Kant and Schlegel, helped me develop my interests in German philosophy. Newton Garver read the entire manuscript in an earlier form and offered comments that much improved the current work. Barry Smith’s work has always been a source of philosophical insights for me, and despite (perhaps because of) our philosophical differences, I always learn from him. Peter Hare’s comments on an earlier version of the manuscript led me to rethink some of my claims regarding Schlegel’s epistemology. Ronald Hauser led me to my first encounter with Wilhelm Meister and many other German literary treasures, and I will be ever grateful for the path he opened for me to the literary side of German Romanticism. ix x Acknowledgments In 2001 I was fortunate to have the opportunity to participate in the NEH Summer Institute on Kant and early German Romanticism that was organized by Jane Kneller and Karl Ameriks. The discussions I had there helped me to clarify some of the points that I develop in the present volume. To Karl Ameriks I owe a special debt, for his encouragement of my work has been unflagging. At the NEH Institute I met Fred Beiser and Bob Richards, two thinkers whose work has been invaluable to the field of early German Romanticism and whose intellectual generosity is a true gift. Fred read my dissertation on Schlegel and sent me comments that led me to rethink several of my claims and to work harder to sharpen some of my points. The influence of his work is evident in the following pages, and I hope that my criticism of some aspects of his arguments does not overshadow the great admiration I have for his work. Bob Richards has been most supportive, and our discussions of Schlegel and other themes related to early German Romanticism have certainly helped me to sharpen my views. Thom Brooks read the entire manuscript, and his comments were of great value. Versions of some of the chapters were presented at conferences or talks. Given the generous support of the Alexander von Humboldt Foun- dation, I was able to spend the 2004–05 academic year in Leipzig, Ger- many. I am grateful for the kind reception I received from the Department of Philosophy at the Universität Leipzig, and for the comments I received at a talk I gave there. The arguments I develop in chapter 1 were shaped considerably by those comments. My host in Leipzig was Pirmin Stekeler- Weithofer, and I thank him for his support. Chapter 3 developed out of a talk I gave for the North American Fichte Society, and I am grateful to Dan Breazeale, Tom Rockmore, and Arnold Farr for organizing that meeting and to the participants there for their comments. My views on Schlegel’s reception of Kant came into focus as I prepared a talk for the North American Kant Association Session on Kant and Romanticism at the Ameri- can Philosophical Association’s Central Division Meeting in 2002. I thank Karl Ameriks for organizing that talk and Jane Kneller and Peter Foley for discussion that helped me to develop the material that became chapter 5 of the present book. Some of the ideas developed in chapter 7 were first developed for an article (“Romanticismo e postmoderno: variazioni incompresse sulla critica della modernità”) that Nectarios Limantis and Luigi Pastore invited me to write for their collection Prospettive sul Postmoderno (Milano: Mimesis, 2006). I would also like to offer thanks to Bärbel Frischmann, a fellow Schlegel scholar. Her work and friendship have shaped my work. I would also like to thank the students in the graduate seminars I have taught at the Universidad Simón Bolívar, in Caracas, Venezuela and at DePaul Univer- Acknowledgments xi sity in Chicago, for the many stimulating discussions which have helped me look in new directions and develop my ideas. Though distance separates us, I am deeply thankful for the friendship and support of my work from Rafael Tomás Caldera, Victor Krebs, Fabio Morales, and the late Luis Castro Leiva. My gratitude also extends to the editorial staff at SUNY Press, in particular to the production editor, Judith Block, and to Marilyn Semerad, director of production, for their expertise in guiding the manuscript to its final form. I also wish to acknowledge David Prout, who prepared a thorough and detailed index, which contributes greatly to the usefulness of the book. I am also grateful for a grant from the University Research Council of DePaul University which helped cover the costs associated with the final preparation of the manuscript My first philosophical investigations began by my grandmother’s side, and they continue with the most supportive partner in all of my Symphilosophie, my husband and fellow philosopher, Leo, who has con- tributed to this book in more ways than I can properly acknowledge. Introduction ማሜምሞ Philosophy and Early German Romanticism he value of early German Romanticism as a literary movement has Tbeen generally accepted.1 The growing interest in the movement by philosophers is a more recent phenomenon; it is no overstatement to claim that there is currently a renaissance of interest in the philosophical dimensions of early German Romanticism.2 Stanley Cavell, Frederick Beiser, and Andrew Bowie were among the first brave souls in the Anglophone world to dare ascribe philosophi- cal importance to early German Romanticism.
Recommended publications
  • Fichte's Controversy with Reinhold
    Gunter Zoller 51 PIi 10 (2000), 50-76. lO'l"plion of his work in Jena in general and to his work from the last Yl';\IS in Jena in particular. I. Aut aut or transcendental philosophy and popUlar philosophy The Unpopularity of Transcendental Philosophy: Fichte's Controversy With Reinhold (1799-1801) Thc type of systematic philosophy which Kant and Fichte developed and prcsented under the titles "transcendental philosophy" and "Wissenschaftslehre" at the close of the eighteenth century marks a sharp GUNTER ZOLLER cacsura in the philosophical discourse of modernity. To be sure, the Kantian-Fichtean philosophical revolution shares in the general critical spirit of the Enlightenment. Yet the scientific rigor of Kant' sand Fichte' s philosophical work contrasts sharply with the essayistic manner of These days common sense thinking and writing to be found in European philosophy in the second is like the peasant who swallows half of the eighteenth century and especially in its German variant, that the prescription instead of the medicine.' eclecticism in which Leibnizian heritage mixes comfortably with English, Scottish and French inspirations. In this regard, the German philosophy of the Enlightenment, chiefly represented by Moses Mendelssohn and The following essay examines the account of the relation between Christian Garve, with its aim of a widely comprehensible treatment of philosophy and life which Fichte developed at the end of his years in Jena philosophical issues, can rightly be considered to remain more faithful to and at the beginning of his time in Berlin in response to contemporary the spirit of the age than the Kantian-Fichtean movement with its criticisms and attacks of his earlier work.
    [Show full text]
  • JG Fichte and the Atheism Dispute
    J.G. FICHTE AND THE ATHEISM DISPUTE (1798–1800) This page has been left blank intentionally J.G. Fichte and the Atheism Dispute (1798–1800) Translated by CURTIS BOWMAN Independent Scholar, USA Commentary by YOLANDA ESTES Mississippi State University, USA First published 2010 by Ashgate Publishing Published 2016 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN 711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017, USA Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business Copyright © 2010 Yolanda Estes and Curtis Bowman Yolanda Estes and Curtis Bowman have asserted their right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as the editors of this work. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. Notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data J.G. Fichte and the Atheism Dispute (1798–1800). 1. Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 1762–1814. 2. Atheism – History – 18th century. 3. Atheism – History -- 18th century – Sources. I. Estes, Yolanda. II. Bowman, Curtis. 211.8’092–dc22 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Estes, Yolanda. [Selections. English. 2010] J.G. Fichte and the Atheism Dispute, 1798–1800 / Yolanda Estes and Curtis Bowman. p. cm. Includes index. 1. Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 1762–1814.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel on Indian Philosophy: Spinozism, Romanticism, Eurocentrism Gino Signoracci University of New Mexico
    University of New Mexico UNM Digital Repository Philosophy ETDs Electronic Theses and Dissertations Spring 5-4-2017 Hegel on Indian Philosophy: Spinozism, Romanticism, Eurocentrism Gino Signoracci University of New Mexico Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalrepository.unm.edu/phil_etds Part of the Comparative Philosophy Commons, Continental Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Signoracci, Gino. "Hegel on Indian Philosophy: Spinozism, Romanticism, Eurocentrism." (2017). https://digitalrepository.unm.edu/ phil_etds/24 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Electronic Theses and Dissertations at UNM Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy ETDs by an authorized administrator of UNM Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Gino Signoracci Candidate Philosophy Department This dissertation is approved, and it is acceptable in quality and form for publication: Approved by the Dissertation Committee: Adrian Johnston, Chairperson John Taber Brent Kalar Iain Thomson Shannon Mussett i HEGEL ON INDIAN PHILOSOPHY: SPINOZISM, ROMANTICISM, EUROCENTRISM by GINO SIGNORACCI B.A., Philosophy, English, University of Notre Dame, 2004 M.A., Philosophy, Brock University, 2009 DISSERTATION Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Philosophy The University of New Mexico Albuquerque, New Mexico July, 2017 ii DEDICATION For Ally, for turning up, keeping up, putting up, picking (me) up, and never letting up: with love, good humor, and wonder iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS There are seven people whose abiding support, encouragement, sensitivity, patience, and understanding are the reason I completed this dissertation at all: Adrian, Ally, Jane, Jon, Judy, Kaity, and Krupa.
    [Show full text]
  • Religious Skepticism, Atheism, Humanism, Naturalism, Secularism, Rationalism, Irreligion, Agnosticism, and Related Perspectives)
    Unbelief (Religious Skepticism, Atheism, Humanism, Naturalism, Secularism, Rationalism, Irreligion, Agnosticism, and Related Perspectives) A Historical Bibliography Compiled by J. Gordon Melton ~ San Diego ~ San Diego State University ~ 2011 This bibliography presents primary and secondary sources in the history of unbelief in Western Europe and the United States, from the Enlightenment to the present. It is a living document which will grow and develop as more sources are located. If you see errors, or notice that important items are missing, please notify the author, Dr. J. Gordon Melton at [email protected]. Please credit San Diego State University, Department of Religious Studies in publications. Copyright San Diego State University. ****************************************************************************** Table of Contents Introduction General Sources European Beginnings A. The Sixteenth-Century Challenges to Trinitarianism a. Michael Servetus b. Socinianism and the Polish Brethren B. The Unitarian Tradition a. Ferenc (Francis) David C. The Enlightenment and Rise of Deism in Modern Europe France A. French Enlightenment a. Pierre Bayle (1647-1706) b. Jean Meslier (1664-1729) c. Paul-Henri Thiry, Baron d'Holbach (1723-1789) d. Voltaire (Francois-Marie d'Arouet) (1694-1778) e. Jacques-André Naigeon (1738-1810) f. Denis Diderot (1713-1784) g. Marquis de Montesquieu (1689-1755) h. Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778) B. France and Unbelief in the Nineteenth Century a. August Comte (1798-1857) and the Religion of Positivism C. France and Unbelief in the Twentieth Century a. French Existentialism b. Albert Camus (1913 -1960) c. Franz Kafka (1883-1924) United Kingdom A. Deist Beginnings, Flowering, and Beyond a. Edward Herbert, Baron of Cherbury (1583-1648) b.
    [Show full text]
  • Stony Brook University
    SSStttooonnnyyy BBBrrrooooookkk UUUnnniiivvveeerrrsssiiitttyyy The official electronic file of this thesis or dissertation is maintained by the University Libraries on behalf of The Graduate School at Stony Brook University. ©©© AAAllllll RRRiiiggghhhtttsss RRReeessseeerrrvvveeeddd bbbyyy AAAuuuttthhhooorrr... The Specter of Spinoza: The Legacy of the Pantheism Controversy in Hegel’s Thought Dissertation Presented by Harrison Fluss to The Graduate School in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy Stony Brook University December 2016 Copyright by Harrison Fluss 2016 Stony Brook University The Graduate School Harrison Fluss We, the dissertation committee for the above candidate for the Doctor of Philosophy degree, hereby recommend acceptance of this dissertation. Allegra de Laurentiis – Dissertation Advisor Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy Jeffrey Edwards - Chairperson of Defense Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy Andrew Platt - Internal Reader Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy Stephen Houlgate – External Reader Department of Philosophy, University of Warwick This dissertation is accepted by the Graduate School Nancy Goroff Interim Dean of the Graduate School ii Abstract of the Dissertation The Specter of Spinoza: The Legacy of the Pantheism Controversy in Hegel’s Thought by Harrison Fluss Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy Stony Brook University 2016 This dissertation seeks to trace Hegel’s shifting attitudes towards Spinoza, and its significance for later interpretations of the Hegel-Spinoza relationship. In contrast to virtually all other approaches, it will be argued that Hegel’s earlier defense of Spinoza in Faith and Knowledge (1802) was superior to Hegel’s interpretation of Spinoza shaped after his break with Schelling. There is precious little in the Anglophone literature that compares and contrasts the approaches of the young and “mature” Hegel regarding Spinoza’s metaphysics.
    [Show full text]
  • Immanuel Kant (Born in 1724 and Died in 1804)
    What Does it Mean to Orient Oneself in Thinking? Was heißt: sich im Denken orientieren? October 1786 Königsberg in Prussia, Germany. By Immanuel Kant (Born in 1724 and died in 1804) Translation into English by Daniel Fidel Ferrer (March, 2014) What Does it Mean to Orient Oneself in Thinking? / By Immanuel Kant (1724-1804). [Was heißt: sich im Denken orientieren? English]. Translation of text, notes, essays, chronology, etc by Copyright ©2014 Daniel Fidel Ferrer. All rights reserved. Free unlimited distribution. Creative Commons General Public License "Attribution, Non-Commercial", version 3.0 (CCPL BY-NC). Table of Contents Translator’s Short Preface for Historical Context (pages 3-4). Immanuel Kant’s Text translated into English (pages 5-22). Translator’s Remarks (pages 23-24). Notes and Background for Kant’s essay and translation (page 25). Earlier translations from German into English of Kant’s essay (page 26). Pantheism Controversy (Quarrel) (Pantheismusstreit) (pages 27-28). Chronology of the Pantheism Controversy (Quarrel) (pages 29-37). Main Philosophers and authors. Ranked by birth year. Lessing first quarrel. Fragments Controversy. Pantheism Controversy or Pantheism Quarrel starts. Atheism Controversy. What is the Purpose of Kant’s Orientation Essay? (pages 38-42). Selected Bibliography related to Pantheism Controversy (pages 42-43). Related Online Resources (pages 43-44). Kant’s Note on his Overall Philosophical Position (pages 45-47). Dedication and Acknowledgements (pages 48-49). Appendix A. Image of first page of Kant Essay (1786) (pages 49-51). Keyword index (pages 51-83). Starts with a green page. 2 Translator’s Short Preface for the Historical Context By Daniel Fidel Ferrer From 1774 to about 1800, there were three intense philosophical and theological controversies underway in Germany, namely: Fragments Controversy, the Pantheism Controversy, and the Atheism Controversy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Provocations of Nihilism: Practical Philosophy and Aesthetics in Jacobi, Kant, and Schelling
    THE PROVOCATIONS OF NIHILISM THE PROVOCATIONS OF NIHILISM: PRACTICAL PHILOSOPHY AND AESTHETICS IN JACOBI, KANT, AND SCHELLING Jeremy Proulx, H.B.A., M.A. A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy McMaster University ©Copyright by Jeremy Proulx, October 2010 DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY (2010) McMaster University (Philosophy) Hamilton, Ontario TITLE: The Provocations ofNihilism: Practical Philosophy and Aesthetics in Jacobi, Kant, and Schelling AUTHOR: Jeremy Proulx, H.B.A. (Trent), M.A. (Western) SUPERVISOR: Professor Brigitte Sassen NUMBER OF PAGES: viii; 195. 11 Abstract The purpose of the dissertation is to describe how Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi's diagnosis of nihilism at the heart of the rationalist metaphysics of the Enlightenment provokes a tum to practical philosophy and aesthetics as alternative areas of philosophical scrutiny. I divide my analysis into two basic parts, treating practical philosophy and aesthetics respectively. The first part argues that Jacobi's debate with Moses Mendelssohn provokes the development of two unique approaches to practical philosophy, Jacobi's and Kant's. I interpret Jacobi's famous salto mortale as a balance between passively accepting feeling as a legitimate revelation of truth and actively creating the practical context in which feeling can appear as meaningful in the first place. I also argue that in his practical response to the Jacobi-Mendelssohn debate, Kant is still susceptible to Jacobi's critique of Enlightenment rationalism. In the second part, I tum my attention to how Kant and the early Schelling both develop their aesthetic theories as a response to Jacobi's diagnosis of nihilism.
    [Show full text]
  • F.H. Jacobi's "On Divine Things and Their Revelation." a Study And
    F.H. Jacobi's "On Divine Things and their Revelation." A Study and Translation. Paolo Livieri, School of Religious Studies, McGill University, Montreal April 2019 A thesis submitted to McGill University in partial fulfillment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Religious Studies. ©PaoloLivieri2019 - 1 - Table of Contents Abstract 3 Acknowledgments 6 Contribution to Knowledge 7 Chapter 1. Introduction 10 F.H. Jacobi and the Divine Things 10 History of the manuscript 15 Bibliographical overview and theoretical perspectives 22 Conclusion 32 Chapter 2 Divine Things. The significance of the book within the development of Jacobi's 34 philosophy. Intro 34 Atheismusstreit 36 Jacobi's Letter to Fichte: the rise of nihilism 39 The faculty of reason 45 On death and dying 52 Chapter 3. Conceptual Analysis of the Divine Things. A View from Within. Lexical and 56 Theoretical Structure of the Text. Prophecy 56 Measure 67 Reason 72 Jacobi's realism 83 The last threat 87 Chapter 4. The Problem of Existence. 91 The distinctiveness of metaphysics: methodology 91 The certainty of existence 102 The problem of freedom 104 Concluding remarks 111 Conclusion 115 Bibliographical Appendix 121 F. H. JACOBI - On Divine Things and their Revelation 142 (the translation follows its own pagination) - 2 - Abstract English Version This dissertation presents the first English translation, together with commentary, of F.H. Jacobi´s On Divine Things and their Revelation (1811; henceforth, Divine Things). This work marked for Jacobi the emancipation of rational thinking from the bounds set to it by the Enlightenment in matters of religion. Jacobi’s goal was to develop a new definition of rationality.
    [Show full text]
  • FH Jacobi's Novel Allwill and the Aufkldrung's Self
    Between Rationalism and Romanticism: F.H. Jacobi's novel Allwill and the Aufkldrung's Self-conception By RICHARD LUDWIG ESCHELMULLER B.A., The University of British Columbia, 1996 A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS In THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES (Department of History) We accept this thesis as coriforrning tojhe required standard THE UNIVERSITY OF BRITKiH COLUMBI^ December 1999 © Richard Ludwig Eschelmuller, 1999 In presenting this thesis in partial fulfilment of the requirements for an advanced degree at the University of British Columbia, I agree that the Library shall make it freely available for reference and study. I further agree that permission for extensive copying of this thesis for scholarly purposes may be granted by the head of my department or by his or her representatives. It is understood that copying or publication of this thesis for financial gain shall not be allowed without my written permission. Department The University of British Columbia Vancouver, Canada DE-6 (2/88) Abstract This paper addresses a problem in the history of philosophy concerning the issue of moral autonomy within the context of the German Enlightenment. More specifically, it explores the way in which Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi addressed this problem in his 1793 philosophical novel Allwill. The first chapter analyzes the three phases of an ongoing philosophical debate between pietists and rationalists over the definition of Enlightenment By contrasting the rationalism of the first phase with the romantic reaction that characterized the second phase, the first chapter outlines the general historical and philosophical background of the third phase during which thinkers of the Aujklarung explicitly addressed the question of true and false Enlightenment.
    [Show full text]
  • THE NEW SPINOZISM ‘Our World Is the Material of Our Duty Made Sensible’
    THE NEW SPINOZISM ‘Our world is the material of our duty made sensible’. Fichte, On the Basis of Our Belief in a Divine Governance of the World 1 ‘The objective world is simply the original, as yet unconscious, poetry of the spirit; the universal organon of philosophy . is the philosophy of art’. Schelling, System of Transcendental Idealism (1800) 2 1. It was in 1935 that Paul Hazard famously spoke of a ‘crisis of the European mind’3 to describe the transition from the earlier confessional era – when reason was still taken to be subservient to faith, and political power to the rule of God and the Church – to the Enlightenment, when reason reversed that relation by asserting its autonomy with respect to religious belief and philosophers began to look at reason’s rule for the authentication of political power. Hazard himself dated that transition to around 1680. 4 Recent scholarship has pushed this date back to 1650, and has also refined the layout of the crisis. The tendency now is to consider it as a global European phenomenon, rather than to break it down into to the various lands and linguistic groups that made up seventeenth century Europe. 5 There is also a greater sensitivity now to the variety of the strands of thought that caused it. Some of these strands were especially reluctant to forge compromises with the tradition of the past, and, among these, the one of which Spinoza was both the spiritual father and the continuing inspirational force – the so called ‘radical 1J. G. Fichte – Gesamtausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften , eds.
    [Show full text]
  • The Divine Marquis' Ethical Project: Sade and the “Turn to Religion” in Postmodernist Philosophy
    School of Media, Culture and Creative Arts The Divine Marquis’ Ethical Project: Sade and the “Turn to Religion” in Postmodernist Philosophy Melissa Michele Russell This thesis is presented for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy of Curtin University April 2014 To the best of my knowledge and belief, this thesis contains no material previously published by any other person except where due acknowledgement has been made. This thesis contains no material which has been accepted for the award of any other degree or diploma in any university. - Melissa M. Russell 29/04/14 Abstract This thesis argues that Sade’s work constitutes a transgressive ethical project which, in spite of its grounding in a materialist atheism, cannot escape from Christian ethical categories. In accordance with the nature of transgression Sade must invoke and reinstate those very limits and categories--such as good and evil, vice and virtue, the sacred and profane--that he attempts, with enormous relish, to destroy. This thesis does not argue that Sade explicitly employed a theory of transgression. However, following Georges Bataille and Michel Foucault, who both base their concept of transgression on a reading of Sade’s work, I use transgression to provide a philosophical lens through which to reread him and to determine the precise nature of his transgressiveness. Sade’s pornographic writings can still generate outrage in the popular imagination even if they are now largely unread. However, this thesis aims to show that it is not primarily the offensive sexual content of his writing which makes Sade’s work deserving of the label ‘transgressive.’ Sex is the vehicle for transgression because sexual taboos have been the effect of and have helped to constitute the theological, philosophical and ethical systems which many Enlightenment thinkers sought to challenge.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction 1 Silence and the Pantheistic Sublime in Coleridge's
    Notes Introduction 1. McFarland Coleridge and the Pantheist Tradition xxiii–xl, 1–52. 2. Ibid. 107–8, 191–7. 3. Ibid. 54–60. 4. Coleridge draws on a tradition of similar distinctions (e.g. Goethe’s and Schelling’s; see The Philosophical Lectures of Samuel Taylor Coleridge 51–5). 5. Dombrowski ‘McFarland, Pantheism and Panentheism’. 6. McFarland Coleridge and the Pantheist Tradition 54, 63. 7. Ibid. 54–70. 8. Ibid. 79–82. 9. Ibid. 130. 10. McFarland ‘Aspects of Coleridge’s Distinction Between Reason and Under- standing’ 177. 11. BL I 248n1. Taken from Abhandlungen zur Erläuterung des Idealismus der Wissenschafttslehre (SW I 444–6). 12. Gadamer ‘On the Circle of Understanding’ 68–70. 13. Gadamer discusses the history of hermeneutics in depth. Gadamer Truth and Method 173–264. 14. Gadamer Truth and Method 271–7. 15. Heidegger 153. 16. Gadamer Truth and Method 245, 302–7. 17. Gadamer Philosophical Hermeneutics 56–8, 65–6. 18. The ‘classical’ is Gadamer’s key example because it is both an interpretive result and a judgement or prejudice that establishes interpretive categories. Thus Gadamer discusses the hermeneutical significance of temporal distance itself. Gadamer Truth and Method 285–300. 19. Bloom’s theory originally focused on Coleridge. Bloom ‘Coleridge: The Anxiety of Influence’. 1 Silence and the pantheistic sublime in Coleridge’s early poetry 1. Usher 114. 2. See Burke 125–6, 144–7; Usher 107–10, 114–18; Priestley A Course of Lectures on Oratory and Criticism 159; Blair I 48–50; Knight 361–4. 3. For discussion of the emergence of the sublime, see Cassirer 297–331; Monk The Sublime.
    [Show full text]