Law, Language and Lenity Lawrence Solan

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Law, Language and Lenity Lawrence Solan Brooklyn Law School BrooklynWorks Faculty Scholarship 1998 Law, Language and Lenity Lawrence Solan Follow this and additional works at: https://brooklynworks.brooklaw.edu/faculty Part of the Criminal Law Commons, and the Other Law Commons Recommended Citation 40 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 57 (1998) This Article is brought to you for free and open access by BrooklynWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of BrooklynWorks. LAW, LANGUAGE, AND LENITY LAWRENCE M. SOLAN ° TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION ................................ 58 I. A LINGUISTIC APPROACH TO PROBLEMS IN STATUTORY INTERPRETATION ................................ 62 A. Ambiguity ............................... 62 B. Conceptual Problems ....................... 65 1. The Psychology of Conceptualization ....... 65 2. What is a Security?: A Legal Example ...... 75 3. Conceptual Problems in Statutory Construction .......................... 78 a. Vagueness and Overinclusion ......... 79 b. Underinclusionand the Linguistic Wall . 83 C. Summary ............................... 86 II. THREE APPROACHES TO INTERPRETING CRIMINAL STATUTES: A COGNITIVELY DRIVEN HISTORY ......... 86 A. Naked Lenity ............................. 87 B. The American Tradition of Strict Construction ... 89 1. Chief Justice Marshalland Legislative Primacy ............................. 89 2. Justice Story and the Meaning of Words ..... 94 C. Narrowing the Rule of Lenity ................ 97 1. A Shift in the Interpretive Culture ......... 97 * Associate Professor of Law, Brooklyn Law School. This work was supported in part by a summer research stipend from Brooklyn Law School. I wish to thank my research assistants, Nicholas Moyne, Harold Olsen, and Robyn Schneider, for their extremely valuable contributions to this project. I also am grateful to Ursula Bentele, Susan Herman, Roberta Karmel, Gary Minda, Tony Sebok, Steve Siegel, Peter Tiersma, Spencer Waller, and Steve Winter for their discussion of many of the issues that I address in this article. WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 40:57 2. Justice Frankfurterand the Narrow Rule of Lenity ............................ 102 III. LENITY IN THE REHNQUIST COURT ................ 108 A. Lenity and the Debate Over Textual.ism ........ 109 B. Vagueness and Ambiguity in the Rehnquist Court 115 IV. MUST CRIMINAL STATUTES BE INTERPRETED NARROWLY?. 122 A. FailedEfforts to Eliminate Lenity ............ 123 B. Should the Chevron Doctrine Trump Lenity? . 128 C. Lenity's Values .......................... 134 1. N otice .............................. 134 2. Legislative Primacy ................... 141 CONCLUSION .................................. 143 INTRODUCTION The traditional rule for construing criminal statutes is the rule of lenity, a name given to a common law principle that "pe- nal statutes should be strictly construed against the government or parties seeking to enforce statutory penalties and in favor of the persons on whom penalties are sought to be imposed."1 The motivating purpose of the rule is to provide adequate notice to defendants (due process), and to reinforce the notion that only the legislature has the power to define what conduct is criminal and what conduct is not (separation of powers).2 Although widely accepted, the rule is by no means adhered to universally. The legislatures of many states, frustrated by what seemed to be unnaturally narrow judicial readings of criminal statutes, have eliminated the rule of lenity. New York and Cali- fornia did so more than a century ago.3 Recent academic litera- l. NORMAN J. SINGER, STATUTES AND STATUTORY CONSTRUCTION § 59.03 (5th ed. 1992). 2. See Babbitt v. Sweet Home Chapter of Communities for a Great Or., 515 U.S. 687, 704 n.18 (1995) (mentioning the rationales). 3. See CAL. PENAL CODE § 4 (West 1988) ("The rule of the common law, that pe- nal statutes are to be strictly construed, has no application to this Code. All its pro- visions are to be construed according to the fair import of their terms, with a view to effect its objects and to promote justice."); N.Y. PENAL LAW § 5 (McKinney 1998) ("The general rule that a penal statute is to be strictly construed does not apply to 1998] LAW, LANGUAGE, AND LENITY ture has been critical as well. Professors Jeffries and Kahan crit- icize the principle on the grounds that its application does not further its stated rationales-legislative primacy and fair no- tice.4 Other commentators object to lenity as inappropriate in particular situations, such as RICO,5 civil bankruptcy,6 govern- ment corruption cases,' and environmental crimes.' Moreover, not even lenity's strongest supporters can believe in it without qualification. Courts have good reason not to want every in- stance in which statutory language underdetermines meaning to require acquittal. This Article takes issue with lenity's critics, new and old. Crit- ics either assume lenity in a strong version not now used by the courts, or have too much confidence in how well we can construe statutes without some overriding principle to resolve ambigu- ities. The rule of lenity has been narrowed dramatically over time in response to changes in the ways that courts generally interpret statutes. In seventeenth century England, a very broad rule of lenity was developed to thwart the will of a legislature bent on seeing statutory violators hanged.9 American courts, notably through Chief Justice Marshall and Justice Story, adopt- ed the rule early on, but with qualifications that gave additional this chapter, but the provisions herein must be construed according to the fair im- port of their terms to promote justice and effect the objects of the law."). 4. See John Calvin Jeffries, Jr., Legality, Vagueness, and the Construction of Pe- nal Statutes, 71 VA. L. REV. 189, 198-200 (1985); Dan M. Kahan, Lenity and Federal Law Crimes, 1994 SUP. CT. REV. 345, 345-46; see also the benchmark article by Livingston Hall, Strict or Liberal Construction of Penal Statutes, 48 HARV. L. REV. 748 (1935) (discussing the factors that control judges' interpretation of penal stat- utes). 5. See Bryan T. Camp, Dual Construction of RICO: The Road Not Taken in Reves, 51 WAsH. & LEE L. REv. 61, 61-62 (1994). 6. See Bruce A. Markell, Bankruptcy, Lenity, and the Statutory Interpretation of Cognate Civil and Criminal Statutes, 69 IND. L.J. 335, 336-37 (1994). 7. See Ross E. Davies, Comment, A Public Trust Exception to the Rule of Lenity, 63 U. CH. L. REV. 1175, 1175 (1996). 8. See David E. Filippi, Note, Unleashing the Rule of Lenity: Environmental En- forcers Beware!, 26 ENVTL. L. 923, 924-27, 944-48 (1996); Patrick W. Ward, Com- ment, The Criminal Provisions of the Clean Water Act as Interpreted by the Judicia- ry and the Resulting Response from the Legislature, 5 DICK. J. ENVIL. L. & POL. 399 (1996). 9. See infra notes 123-28 and accompanying text. WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 40:57 deference to the intent of the legislature."0 In the early part of the twentieth century, American courts began looking seriously at legislative history and at other extratextual materials as a routine aspect of the interpretation of statutes. Fueled largely by a series of opinions by Justice Frankfurter, the rule of lenity subsequently was narrowed further, relegating it to a tie break- er only after courts exhausted all other interpretive aids." Using advances from linguistics and cognitive psychology, this Article argues that the narrow, Frankfurter approach to lenity best approximates the way we use language and form concepts. Early attempts to impose a more mechanical rule of lenity gave inadequate recognition to the flexibility of our conceptual struc- ture at the price of undermining legislative intent. The Frank- furter approach best serves the dual purposes of deference to legislative will and adequate notice to defendants. Attempts to dispense with the rule altogether also come at great expense to widely held jurisprudential values. Language is sometimes vague and sometimes ambiguous. When we do not know how a legislature intended a statute to apply even after careful study, we have to look outside the statutory language for an answer. This Article argues that the narrow rule of lenity embodies important values with which we are unwilling to dis- pense. For this reason, courts in jurisdictions that have elimi- nated lenity legislatively continue to apply it anyway. For this same reason, we should not accept academic proposals to elimi- nate lenity, such as Professor Kahan's proposal to replace lenity with definitive interpretations by the Department of Justice. 2 Section I of this Article explores the problem that the rule of lenity is intended to solve: What is it about the way we write criminal laws that leads to such uncertainty in our understand- ing of them? Coming to grips with this issue is a prerequisite for evaluating approaches to the interpretation of criminal statutes. The relevant literature on criminal statutes rarely addresses this problem, however, and the courts virtually never do, apart 10. See infra notes 135-78 and accompanying text. 11. See infra notes 179-228 and accompanying text. 12. See Dan M. Kahan, Is Chevron Relevant to Federal Criminal Law?, 110 HARV. L. REv. 469, 488-89 (1996). 19981 LAW, LANGUAGE, AND LENITY from general remarks about the indeterminacies of language. This Article begins by describing the interpretive problems in cognitive and linguistic terms, an analysis that serves as a framework for the remainder of the Article. Section II describes in more detail
Recommended publications
  • Parliamentary Debates in Statutory Interpretation: a Question Of
    Parliamentary Debates in Statutory Interpretation:A Question of Admissibilityor of Weight? St6phane Beaulac" The exclusionary rule which prohibits references La r~gle qui exclue l'utilisation des debats parle- to parliamentary materials as an aid to statutory inter- mentaires comme outil d'interpr6tation legislative a te pretation has been applied for decades in most common appliqude pendant des d6cennies dans la plupart des ju- law jurisdictions. The House of Lords handed down its ridictions de common law jusqu'a la decision de prin- fundamental decision in Pepper v. Hartwhich allowed cipe du comit6 d'appel de la House ofLords dans Pep- reference to parliamentary debates in limited circum- per c. Hart. L'auteur examine d'abord les origines an- stances. glaises de la r~gle d'exclusion ainsi que ses applica- The author first examines the English origins of tions dans d'autres juridictions de common law telles the exclusionary rule as well as its application in other I'Australie, la Nouvelle-Z6lande, les ttats-Unis et le 1998 CanLIIDocs 38 common law jurisdictions, including Australia, New Canada. L'auteur commente aussi la situation dans le Zealand, the United States and Canada. The author also syst~me de droit civil qu6b6cois. L'exclusion des d6- comments on the situation prevailing in Quebec's civil bats parlementaires est ensuite consid6r6e dans le con- law system. The exclusion of parliamentary debates is texte plus global des m6thodes et des principes then considered in the broader context of the methods d'interpretation legislative. and principles of statutory construction. L'auteur soutient que l'utilisation des d6bats par- The author contends that the issue of parliamen- lementaires dans l'interpretation legislative est une tary debates in statutory interpretation is a question of question de poids plutft que d'admissibilite.
    [Show full text]
  • A Clash of Canons: Lenity, Chevron, and the One- Statute, One-Interpretation Rule
    A Clash of Canons: Lenity, Chevron, and the One- Statute, One-Interpretation Rule JUSTIN LEVINE* TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION ..................................................... 1424 I. THE RULE OF LENITY AND THE CHEVRON DOCTRINE . 1427 A. THE RULE OF LENITY ...................................... 1427 1. Types of Canons ............................... 1427 2. Rule of Lenity Examined......................... 1429 B. THE CHEVRON DOCTRINE ................................... 1430 1. Pre-Chevron Jurisprudence ....................... 1430 2. Chevron's Two-Step Doctrine ..................... 1431 3. Chevron's Rationales ........................... 1432 4. Mead's Emphasis on Congressional Intent. 1433 C. LENITY AND CHEVRON IN CONFLICT .......................... 1434 1. Overview .................................... 1434 2. Possible Resolutions ............................ 1435 a. Lenity Over Chevron (Lenity in Step One). 1435 b. Chevron Limited by Lenity (Lenity in Step Two) . 1436 c. Chevron Over Lenity ........................ 1436 d. Path Dependence ........................... 1438 II. ONE-STATUTE, ONE-INTERPRETATION RULE REJECTED . 1438 A. OVERVIEW .............................................. 1438 B. SUPREME COURT PRECEDENT RE-EXAMINED .................... 1440 1. Leocal v. Ashcroft .............................. 1441 * Georgetown Law, J.D. expected 2019; Dartmouth College, A.B. 2016. © 2019, Justin Levine. I would like to extend my sincere appreciation to Professors Bernick and Westmoreland for their insights on administrative law and
    [Show full text]
  • Can Legislatures Constrain Judicial Interpretation of Statutes? Anthony D'amato Northwestern University School of Law, [email protected]
    Northwestern University School of Law Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons Faculty Working Papers 2010 Can Legislatures Constrain Judicial Interpretation of Statutes? Anthony D'Amato Northwestern University School of Law, [email protected] Repository Citation D'Amato, Anthony, "Can Legislatures Constrain Judicial Interpretation of Statutes?" (2010). Faculty Working Papers. Paper 71. http://scholarlycommons.law.northwestern.edu/facultyworkingpapers/71 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Working Papers by an authorized administrator of Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. Can Legislatures Constrain Judicial Interpretation of Statutes? by Anthony D’Amato*, 75 Va. L. Rev. 561-603 (1989) Abstract: An aspect of the battle over deconstruction is whether resort to legislative intent might help to determine the content of a statutory text that otherwise, in splendid isolation, could be deconstructed by simply positing different interpretive contexts. I examine the same issue by recounting my own quest for determinate meaning in statutes—a sort of personal legislative history. I do not claim for jurisprudence the role of ensuring faithful reception of the legislature's message, for that is impossible. At best, jurisprudential theory only reduces the degrees of interpretive freedom, and then only probably, not necessarily. The more significant thesis of this article is that all theories of statutory interpreta- tion can only do that much and no more. Tags: legislative intent, statutory interpretation, jurisprudence, deconstruction, doctrinalists [pg561]** An aspect of the current battle over deconstruction [FN1] is whether resort to legislative intent might help to determine the content of a statutory text that otherwise, in splendid isolation, could be deconstructed by simply positing different interpretive contexts.
    [Show full text]
  • Judicial Interpretation of Statutes April 2020
    Judicial Interpretation of Statutes April 2020 Executive Summary Courts in the United States serve several functions. They oversee civil and criminal trials, issue orders requiring or prohibiting certain actions, decide whether a particular law violates the constitution, and determine the meaning of language in a contract or law. This publication discusses the role the courts play in interpreting statutes. The primary focus of statutory interpretation is the language of a statute. Courts only move beyond that language when there is ambiguity. This publication discusses the tests and tools the court uses to resolve ambiguity and includes questions for legislators to consider when crafting legislation. Authority to Interpret Statutes The judicial system in the United States adopted the common law system from England.1 Under that system there were few statutes. Courts developed the law by relying on general principles, following decisions of prior courts, and applying that guidance to the specific facts of a case. The common law tradition gave courts great power to say what the law was, and there was an understanding that courts in the United States retained that power. In one of the most famous decisions by the United States Supreme Court, Marbury v. Madison, the court said: “It is emphatically the province and duty of the judicial department to say what the law is. Those who apply the rule to particular cases, must of necessity expound and interpret that rule.”2 Every court has the authority to interpret statutes. Minnesota has three levels of courts— district courts, the court of appeals, and the supreme court.
    [Show full text]
  • An Analysis of the Theory of Original Intent Russell Pannier
    William Mitchell Law Review Volume 18 | Issue 3 Article 15 1992 An Analysis of the Theory of Original Intent Russell Pannier Follow this and additional works at: http://open.mitchellhamline.edu/wmlr Recommended Citation Pannier, Russell (1992) "An Analysis of the Theory of Original Intent," William Mitchell Law Review: Vol. 18: Iss. 3, Article 15. Available at: http://open.mitchellhamline.edu/wmlr/vol18/iss3/15 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Reviews and Journals at Mitchell Hamline Open Access. It has been accepted for inclusion in William Mitchell Law Review by an authorized administrator of Mitchell Hamline Open Access. For more information, please contact [email protected]. © Mitchell Hamline School of Law Pannier: An Analysis of the Theory of Original Intent AN ANALYSIS OF THE THEORY OF ORIGINAL INTENT RUSSELL PANNIERt I. INTRODUCTION ..................................... 696 II. To WHAT QUESTION IS THE THEORY OF ORIGINAL INTENT AN ANSWER? ............................... 697 A. The Concept of a Legal Rule ..................... 697 B. The Linguistic Formulation of Legal Rules ......... 698 C. Causes of Uncertainty in the Application of Legal R ules .......................................... 699 1. Semantic Vagueness .......................... 699 2. Semantic Ambiguity .......................... 701 3. Amphiboly .................................. 703 4. Unreasonableness of Applications to Apparently Clear Cases ................................. 703 D. The Question Which the Theory of Original Intent Is Intended to Answer .............................. 705 III. WHAT IS THE THEORY OF ORIGINAL INTENT? ........ 706 A. Underlying Motivations and the General Proposal ... 706 B. Application of the Original Intent Theory ........... 707 1. Case of a Single Rulemaker Who Left Accurate Records .................................... 708 2. Case of a Single Rulemaker Who Either Left No Intent Records, Left Incomplete Records, or Left Records Which Cannot be Trusted ............
    [Show full text]
  • Whither the Rule of Lenity by Dan Levin & Nathaniel Stewart*
    Whither the Rule of Lenity by Dan Levin & Nathaniel Stewart* he “rule of lenity” “requires ambiguous criminal laws to manner based on strict statutory construction, it is perhaps be interpreted in favor of the defendants subjected to not surprising that at times it results in interesting coalitions them.”1 Although long a favorite of defense attorneys, that cross the Court’s traditional conservative-liberal lines. As T 10 actual applications of the rule, at least at the Supreme Court noted, Justice Scalia’s plurality opinion in Santos was joined level,2 have been relatively rare. Th is is perhaps somewhat by Justices Th omas, Ginsburg, and Souter; Justice Stevens surprising as the rule’s roots in due process principles, and concurred in the judgment and wrote separately, also endorsing potential application where a strict construction of a statute application of the rule. Justice Alito fi led a dissenting opinion results in an ambiguity, could lead both traditionally liberal joined by Chief Justice Roberts, Justices Kennedy and Breyer. and traditionally conservative Justices to favor its use. In 2008, Other discussions of the rule of lenity in the most recent in United States v. Santos, the Supreme Court issued a plurality three terms have included the following: Justice Ginsburg opinion holding that a key term in a federal money laundering acknowledging that the statutory defi nition in question was statute was ambiguous and applied the rule of lenity to resolve “not a model of the careful drafter’s art” and yet declining to the ambiguity
    [Show full text]
  • Download Download
    THE SUPREME COURT’S STRANGE BREW: HISTORY, FEDERALISM AND ANTI-ORIGINALISM IN COMEAU Kerri A. Froc and Michael Marin* Introduction Canadian beer enthusiasts and originalists make unlikely fellow travellers. However, both groups eagerly awaited and were disappointed by the Supreme Court of Canada’s decision in R v Comeau.1 The case came to court after Gerard Comeau was stopped and charged by the RCMP in a “sting” operation aimed at New Brunswickers bringing cheaper alcohol from Quebec across the provincial border to be enjoyed at home.2 Eschewing Gerard Comeau’s plea to “Free the Beer”, the Court upheld as constitutional provisions in New Brunswick’s Liquor Control Act, which made it an offence to possess liquor in excess of the permitted amount not purchased from the New Brunswick Liquor Corporation.3 The Court’s ruling was based on section 121 of the Constitution Act, 1867, which states that “[a]ll articles of Growth, Produce, or Manufacture of any one of the Provinces…be admitted free into each of the other Provinces.”4 In the Court’s view, this meant only that provinces could not impose tariffs on goods from another province. It did not apply to non-tariff barriers, like New Brunswick’s monopoly on liquor sales in favour of its Crown corporation. In so deciding, the Court upheld the interpretation set out in a nearly 100-year-old precedent, Gold Seal Ltd v Attorney- General for the Province of Alberta,5 albeit amending its interpretation of section 121 to prohibit both tariffs and “tariff-like” barriers. The Supreme Court also criticized the trial judge’s failure to respect stare decisis in overturning this precedent.
    [Show full text]
  • Statutory Interpretation in Comparative Perspective
    BOOK REVIEW THE HERMENEUTIC TOURIST: STATUTORY INTERPRETATION IN COMPARATIVE PERSPECTIVE DanielA. Farberf INTERPRETING STATUTES: A COMPARATWVE STUDY. Edited by D. Neil Mac- Cormick and Robert S. Summers. Aldershot: Dartmouth Publishing Co., Ltd. 1991. Pp. xiv, 567. As with tourism, one of the pleasures of comparative law is the collection of amusing trivia. Consider, for example, the plight of judges in the lower French courts. Their opinions are rarely pub- lished, and even then, only at the sufferance of the editors of the law journals.' (Imagine if federal court of appeals judges had to submit their work to the third-year students who edit ourjournals.) But then, French judicial opinions themselves are rather different from those elsewhere. We are told of a comparative study of three judicial opin- ions on the same subject from courts in France, Germany, and the United States. The French decision had three hundred words, the German two thousand, and the American majority opinion alone had eight thousand.2 It is little wonder, however, that French opinions are so brief, for the highest civil court in France decides twenty thousand appeals annually.3 t HenryJ. Fletcher Professor of Law, Associate Dean for Research, and Acting Associ- ate Vice President for Academic Affairs, University of Minnesota. I would like to thank Phil Frickey and Fred Morrison for their helpful comments. 1 INTERPRETING STATUTES: A COMPARATIVE STUDY 198 (D. Neil MacCormick & Robert S. Summers eds., 1991) [hereinafter MACCoRMICK & SUMMERS]. THE SAME IS TRUE FOR GER- MANJUDGES. Id. at 105. This reflects the salutary principle of the civil law that law profes- sors are more important than judges.
    [Show full text]
  • WHAT IS TEXTUALISM? Caleb Nelson* VER the Past Two Decades
    NELSONBOOK 3/18/2005 5:21 PM WHAT IS TEXTUALISM? Caleb Nelson* VER the past two decades, eminent scholars and judges have O devoted renewed attention to both the goals and the methods of statutory interpretation. In the academy, indeed, “theories of statutory interpretation have blossomed like dandelions in spring.”1 The range of theories is not quite so broad in actual American courtrooms, but judges too are of different minds about how to ap- proach statutes. One of the leading approaches, championed by Justices Scalia and Thomas on the Supreme Court and by Judge Easterbrook on the Seventh Circuit, goes by the name of “textualism.” Although its advocates accept that label,2 they did not choose it; the approach was named more by critics than by adherents.3 Perhaps not surpris- * Professor of Law and Albert Clark Tate, Jr., Research Professor, University of Virginia. I thank Barry Cushman, Earl Dudley, John Harrison, Paul Mahoney, John Manning, Tom Merrill, Tom Nachbar, Kent Olson, Jim Ryan, and workshop partici- pants at Virginia for helpful conversations and comments. 1 William N. Eskridge, Jr., Dynamic Statutory Interpretation 1 (1994). 2 See, e.g., Antonin Scalia, Common-Law Courts in a Civil-Law System: The Role of United States Federal Courts in Interpreting the Constitution and Laws, in A Matter of Interpretation: Federal Courts and the Law 3, 23 (Amy Gutmann ed., 1997); Herrmann v. Cencom Cable Assocs., 978 F.2d 978, 982–83 (7th Cir. 1992) (Easter- brook, J.). 3 The earliest usage of “textualism” reported by the Oxford English Dictionary comes from 1863, when an author used the term to criticize Puritan theology.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Textualism in the Progressive Toolbox
    TRACZ (DO NOT DELETE) 4/27/2021 11:15 PM WORDS AND THEIR MEANINGS: THE ROLE OF TEXTUALISM IN THE PROGRESSIVE TOOLBOX BY ELIOT T. TRACZ* I.INTRODUCTION ................................................................................................... 353 II.TEXTUALISM ........................................................................................................ 355 A. Textualism ............................................................................................. 355 i. Legislative intent ......................................................................... 355 ii. Textualism ...................................................................................... 358 B. Words and Their Meanings ............................................................ 359 C. Canons of Construction- What happens when the text is vague? ..................................................................................................... 361 D. Some Criticisms ................................................................................... 364 III.TEXTUALISM AS BIG “C” OR LITTLE “C” CONSERVATIVE ............ 365 IV.TEXTUALISM AS A PROGRESSIVE TOOL ............................................... 369 A. Past Examples of Textualism Helping a Progressive Agenda 370 B. Future Areas Where Textualism Can Support Progressive 371 i. Commonsense Gun Reform ..................................................... 371 ii. Qualified Immunity ..................................................................... 374 V. CONCLUSION .......................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Original Intention and Public Meaning in Constitutional Interpretation Richard Kay University of Connecticut School of Law
    University of Connecticut OpenCommons@UConn Faculty Articles and Papers School of Law 2009 Original Intention and Public Meaning in Constitutional Interpretation Richard Kay University of Connecticut School of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://opencommons.uconn.edu/law_papers Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, and the Public Law and Legal Theory Commons Recommended Citation Kay, Richard, "Original Intention and Public Meaning in Constitutional Interpretation" (2009). Faculty Articles and Papers. 5. https://opencommons.uconn.edu/law_papers/5 +(,121/,1( Citation: 103 Nw. U. L. Rev. 703 2009 Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org) Mon Aug 15 16:57:29 2016 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and Conditions of the license agreement available at http://heinonline.org/HOL/License -- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. -- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your HeinOnline license, please use: https://www.copyright.com/ccc/basicSearch.do? &operation=go&searchType=0 &lastSearch=simple&all=on&titleOrStdNo=0029-3571 Copyright 2009 by Northwestern University School of Law Printedin U.S.A. Northwestern University Law Review Vol. 103, No. 2 ORIGINAL INTENTION AND PUBLIC MEANING IN CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION Richard S. Kay* INTRO D U CTION ............................................................................................................. 703 I. THE FLIGHT FROM INTENTION .............................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Divergence of Constitutional and Statutory Interpretation Kevin M
    Vanderbilt University Law School Scholarship@Vanderbilt Law Vanderbilt Law School Faculty Publications Faculty Scholarship 2004 The Divergence of Constitutional and Statutory Interpretation Kevin M. Stack Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.vanderbilt.edu/faculty-publications Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Kevin M. Stack, The Divergence of Constitutional and Statutory Interpretation, 75 Colorado Law Review. 1 (2004) Available at: http://scholarship.law.vanderbilt.edu/faculty-publications/223 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Scholarship@Vanderbilt Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Vanderbilt Law School Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Vanderbilt Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. UNIVERSITY OF COLORADO LAW REVIEW Volume 75, Number 1 2004 THE DIVERGENCE OF CONSTITUTIONAL AND STATUTORY INTERPRETATION KEVIN M. STACK* INTRODUCTION ..................................................................................... 2 I. THE CONVERGENCE OF CONSTITUTIONAL AND STATUTORY INTERPRETATION IN CONTEMPORARY THEORY ........................... 10 A. Scalia's Textualist Originalism........................................ 10 B. Eskridge's Dynamism ......................................................... 15 II. THE DEMOCRATIC FOUNDATIONS OF ORIGINALISM IN CONSTITUTIONAL AND STATUTORY INTERPRETATION ..................... 22 A. MajoritarianOriginalism ................................................
    [Show full text]