<<

Fiction and

PHI371 Fiction and Truth

Module Convener

Dr Niall Connolly

[email protected]

Office hours: Tuesdays 2-3 & Wednesdays 3-4

Structure of the Course

Two one-hour lectures every week from week 1 to week 11, plus a one-hour seminar every week from week 3 to week 11.

Lecture and Locations:

Tue 1-2 HI-LT10 Wed 12-1 NG-G14

Seminar Times and Locations:

Mon 11-12 IC-1.27 Wed 1-2 9MS-G12

Essay Deadline tba

Course Description

Fiction raises puzzles for . First of all there are the puzzles of non-. How can there be about non-existent objects (like the truth that Sherlock Holmes is a famous fictional detective)? How is it even possible to think and talk about – so to speak – merely fictional entities? The first part of the course will tackle these puzzles, examining both realist explanations of and talk about fictional entities - that take Sherlock Holmes and Hermione Granger to be examples of ‘non-actual’ ‘non-existent,’ or ‘non- concrete’ objects - and anti-realist accounts that deny that there are any such things. This will involve grappling with metaphysical notions like ‘existence’, ‘abstract entity’ ‘possible worlds’ ‘impossible worlds’ and ‘ontological dependence’ as well as with free logics and accounts of engagement with fiction as involving pretence. The second part of the course will focus on a series of puzzles over the of ‘true in the fiction’. What is it for something to be true in a fiction? What is the extent of authorial authority? Can it be true in a fiction that it is ok to intentionally kill innocent people? This last question raises the so- called ‘puzzle of imaginative resistance’. The final part of the course will bring some of the insights we will have encountered about fiction to bear on Fictionalism - the view that a type of discourse (e.g. moral discourse, mathematical discourse) is best understood, not as aiming at truth, but rather as a sort of fiction.

*

Because I would like there to be plenty of questions and discussion in the lectures it is hard to be precise about what will be covered in each lecture. But the provisional plan is to spend the first week covering background and basic : particularly ideas from the regarding the of proper names and definite descriptions. The aim is to make clear why the puzzles of non-existence arise and why they are not as easily resolved as you might initially feel they should be. The required reading for these lectures (we will also discuss this famous paper in the seminar in week 3) is W.V. Quine’s “On What There Is”.

Realist approaches (which allow that there are such things as fictional entities) to the puzzles of non-existence will be the focus of the next two weeks. The two most popular types of realist approaches are Meinongianism – Meinongians endorse Alexius Meinong’s infamous thesis that there are things that don’t exist – and Creationism. ’ paper ‘The Methodology of Nonexistence’ is the required reading on Meingongianism. His book: Nonexistent Objects is also worth checking out and it is possible to get the gist of the view without having to plough through the extensive technical sections. Ed Zalta and offer alternative takes on this sort of position. Amie Thomasson’s Fiction and is the most clear and comprehensive elaboration of Creationism. Stacie Friend’s survey article highlights some of the variations within this approach and compares it to anti-realism. Thomasson’s view is that fictional characters are ‘abstract artefacts’: they are created by the authors of fictions and they exist, but they are not concrete people creatures etc. Thomasson compares them to other alleged kinds of dependent entity. The that some entities depend for their existence on other, more fundamental entities is very much discussed in metaphysics at the moment, and we will look into this idea.

If you find the proposal that there is such a thing (even an abstract or non-existent thing) as Pegasus, the fictional winged horse, just too silly, then you will be inclined towards an antirealist solution to the puzzles of non-existence. One approach takes the things we say ‘about’ fictional entities to express ‘gappy propositions’ (see David Braun’s paper ‘Empty Names’). Another (see Mark Sainsbury’s book Reference without Reference) takes the logic of our language to be a free logic (free logics allow for truths involving genuinely non- referring names). Perhaps the most popular approach invokes pretence. Kendall Walton’s book Mimesis as Makebelieve sets out in detail the view that engaging with fiction involves participating in a special form of pretence: ‘prop-based make-believe’. It is an obvious and natural thought that an author writing a story is only pretending to talk about wizards or detectives or whatever. What is more controversial is that when I say ‘the character of Harry Potter has featured in seven books and eight movies’ I am only pretending to talk about an individual called ‘Harry Potter’. Anyway we will spend two or three weeks on antirealism. The puzzles of non-existence in all should occupy us for five or six weeks. The next topic - truth in fiction and imaginative resistance - should occupy us for two to three weeks. The required reading on the question of truth in fiction is David Lewis’s classic paper. According to Lewis for it to be true in the Harry Potter stories that some children have magical powers is for it to be the case that, in the closest possible world to ours in which the stories are told as known truth, some children have magical powers. We will look at Lewis’s account, problems with that account, and some alternatives, including the alternative view put forward in Alex Byrne’s paper ‘Truth and Fiction: the Story Continued’. The required reading on the problem of imaginative resistance is Tamar Gendler’s seminal paper: ‘The Puzzle of Imaginative Resistance’, and Kathleen Stock’s: ‘Resisting Imaginative Resistance’. Gendler’s article on ‘Imagination’ in the Stanford Encyclopedia notes there are several distinct related puzzles and distinguishes the two main types of strategy that have been adopted in tackling the ‘puzzle of fictionality’: why does it seem that it is can’t be true in the story that punching babies is ok?

The final major topic of the course, which in a way the others build up to and lay the groundwork for, is Fictionalism. We will cover this in the remaining weeks. Mark Sainsbury’s book Fiction and Fictionalism considers fictionalism in the light of questions about the of fiction. There are two varieties of fictionalism: hermeneutic fictionalism (see Jason Stanley’s critical article) says that typical participants in a type of discourse (e.g. mathematicians talking about numbers, ordinary people arguing about what is the right thing to do) are only pretending to aim at the literal truth. Revolutionary fictionalism on the other hand doesn’t seek to interpret what people typically mean, it holds that when participating in a type of discourse we should only pretend to speak the literal truth. Fictionalists typically want to avoid controversial ‘ontological commitments’. For instance they want to avoid allowing that there are really such things as numbers or such properties as rightness and wrongness. This is the motivation for passing off talk of numbers, or talk of right of rightness and wrongness as a sort of fiction. Of course it is not clear that fictionalism about, for instance, mathematics, allows us to avoid ontological commitment to abstract objects, if realist approaches to the puzzles of non-existence are defensible. And it is not clear that fictionalism about discourse about necessity and possibility allows us to avoid ontological commitment to other worlds if Lewis’s analysis of truth in fiction is defensible.

We will cover fictionalism as a general approach, and also focus on fictionalism about specific types of discourse: moral discourse (talk of right and wrong is, or should be fictional), and discourse about ordinary objects (tables and chairs are convenient fictions).

Reading List

(required readings are starred and in bold; recommended readings in bold)

I’ve included a wide range of readings but I don’t expect anyone to read most or all of them.

Topic 1 The Puzzle of Nonexistence

Background: thinking and talking about objects.

Frege, G. (1892). “Über Sinn und Bedeutung”, Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 100: 25–50; translated by M. Black in P.T. Geach & M. Black (eds.), Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, Oxford: Blackwell, 1980, 56–78. Russell, B. (1905a). “”, , 14: 473–493. ––– (1905b). “Critical Notice of: A. Meinong, Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandtheorie und Psychologie”, Mind, 14: 530–538. *Quine, W.V.O. (1948). “On What There Is”, Review of Metaphysics, 2: 21–38. Reprinted in W.V. O. Quine, From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953. Kripke, S. (1972/1980). Naming and Necessity, Oxford: Blackwell

Realism about non-existent objects: Meinongianism

Berto, F. (2011). “Modal Meinongianism and Fiction: the Best of Three Worlds”, Philosophical Studies, 152: 313–334. Caplan, B. (2004). “Creatures of Fiction, Myth, and Imagination”, American Philosophical Quarterly, 41: 331–337. Everett, A. (2005). “Against Fictional Realism”, Journal of Philosophy, 102: 624–649. Fine, K. (1982). “The Problem of Non-Existents. I. Internalism”, Topoi, 1: 97–140. Jacquette, D. (1989). “Mally's Heresy and the Logic of Meinong's Theory”, and Philosophy of Logic, 10: 1–14. Howell, R. (1979). “Fictional Objects: How They Are And How They Aren't.” Poetics, 8: 129–77. ––– (2010). “Fictional Realism and Its Discontents”, in Lihoreau, F. (ed.) (2010). Truth in Fiction, Munich: Ontos Verlag. 153–202. http://www.academia.edu/4892094/Truth_in_Fiction Meinong, A. (1904). “Über Gegenstandtheorie”, in A. Meinong (ed.), Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandtheorie und Psychologie, Leipzig: Barth. Reprinted in Gesammelte Abhandlungen (Gesamtausgabe bd. II), : Akademische Druck- und Verlagsanstalt, 1971, 481-535. Translation by I. Levi, D.B. Terrell, & R.M. Chisholm, in R. Chisholm (ed.),Realism and the Background of Phenomenology, Glencoe: Free Press, 1960, 76–117. *Parsons, T. (1979). “The Methodology of Nonexistence.” Journal of Philosophy 76 (11):649-662. - (1980). Nonexistent Objects, New Haven: Yale University Press. - (1982) “Are there Nonexistent Objects?” American Philosophical Quarterly 19 (4): 365 - 371 Priest, G. (2005). Towards Non-: the Logic and Metaphysics of , Oxford: Clarendon Press. Phillips, J. (2000). “Two Theories of Fictional Discourse,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 37: 107–119. Rapaport, W.J. (1978). “Meinongian Theories and a Russellian Paradox”, Noûs, 12: 153– 180. Reimer, M. (2001). “A “Meinongian” Solution to a Millian Problem” American Philosophical Quarterly 38 (3):233 - 248. Russell, B. (1905b). “Critical Notice of: A. Meinong, Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandtheorie und Psychologie”, Mind, 14: 530–538. Zalta, E. and McMichael, A. (1983). “An Alternative Theory of Nonexistent Objects”, Journal of Philosophical Logic, 9: 297-313 Zalts, E. (1992). “On Mally's Alleged Heresy: A Reply”, History and Philosophy of Logic, 13: 59– 68. ––– (2000). “Pretense Theory and ”, in Everett & Hofweber (2000), Empty Names, Fiction and the Puzzles of Non-existence, Stanford: CSLI Publications. 117–147.

Realism about nonexistent objects: Creationism

Brock, S. (2010). “The Creationist Fiction: the Case against Creationism about Fictional Characters”,Philosophical Review, 119: 337–64. Caplan, B. (2004). “Creatures of Fiction, Myth, and Imagination”, American Philosophical Quarterly, 41: 331–337. *Friend, Stacie. “Fictional Characters”, Philosophy Compass 2 (2007): 141–56. Goodman, J. (2004). “A Defense of Creationism in Fiction”, Grazer Philosophische Studien, 25: 131–155. Kripke, S. (2011) “Vacuous Names and Fictional Entitites”, in Philosophical Troubles – Collected Papers vol. 1. New York: OUP. Salmon, N. (1998). “Nonexistence”, Noûs, 32: 277–319. Sawyer, Sarah (2002) “Abstract Artefacts in Pretence” Philosophical Papers, 31 (2). pp. 183-198. Schiffer, S. (1996). “Language-Created Language-Independent Entities”, Philosophical Topics, 24: 149–166. ––– (2003). The Things We Mean, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Schneider, B. & von Solodkoff, T. (2009). “In Defence of Fictional Realism”, The Philosophical Quarterly, 59: 138–149. *Thomasson, A.L. (1999). Fiction and Metaphysics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ––– (2003a). “Fictional Characters and Literary Practices”, British Journal of Aesthetics, 43: 138–157. ––– (2003b). “Speaking of Fictional Characters”, Dialectica, 57: 205–223. Van Inwagen, P. (1977). “Creatures of Fiction”, American Philosophical Quarterly, 14: 299–308. ––– (2000). “Quantification and Fictional Discourse”, in Everett & Hofweber (2000) Empty Names, Fiction and the Puzzles of Non-existence, Stanford: CSLI Publications. , 235–247. Voltolini, A. (2003). “How Fictional Works Are Related to Fictional Entities”, Dialectica, 57: 225–238. Yagisawa, T. (2001). “Against Creationism in Fiction”, Philosophical Perspectives, 15: 153–172.

- Ontological Dependence, ontological permissiveness and ‘pleonastic entities’

Fine, K. (1994), “Ontological Dependence”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 95: 269–290. *Schaffer, j. (2009). “On What Grounds What”. In David Manley, David J. Chalmers & Ryan Wasserman (eds.), Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of . Oxford University Press. 347-383 (2009) < http://www.jonathanschaffer.org/grounds.pdf> Schiffer, S. (1996). “Language-Created Language-Independent Entities”, Philosophical Topics, 24: 149–166. ––– (2003). The Things We Mean, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Thomasson, A.L. (1999). Fiction and Metaphysics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Antirealism about nonexistent objects

Adams, F., Fuller, G., & Stecker, R. (1997). “The Semantics of Fictional Names”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 78: 128–148. *Braun, D. (1993). “Empty Names,” Noûs, 27: 449–469. ––– (2005). “Empty Names, Fictional Names, Mythical Names,” Noûs, 39: 596–631 Brock, S. (2002). “Fictionalism about Fictional Characters”, Noûs, 36: 1–21. Crane, T. The Objects of Thought, Oxford: OUP. 2013 Everett A. The Nonexistent. (2013) Oxford: OUP. Kroon, F. (1994) “A problem about make-believe” Philosophical Studies, 75(3), pp.201- 229 Orenstein, A. (2003). “Fiction, Propositional Attitudes, and Some Truths about Falsehood”,Dialectica, 57: 177–190. Phillips, J. (2000). “Two Theories of Fictional Discourse,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 37: 107–119. *Sainsbury, R.M. (2005). Reference without Referents, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (2009). Fiction and Fictionalism, London: . ––– (2010). “Fiction and Acceptance-Relative Truth, Belief, and Assertion”, in Lihoreau Lihoreau, F. (ed.) (2010). Truth in Fiction, Munich: Ontos Verlag. 137–152. http://www.academia.edu/4892094/Truth_in_Fiction Reimer, M. (2001). “The Problem of Empty Names.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 79 (4):491 – 506. - (2001). “A “Meinongian” Solution to a Millian Problem” American Philosophical Quarterly 38 (3):233 - 248. Sawyer, Sarah (2012) “Empty names” In: The Routledge companion to philosophy of language. Routledge philosophy companions . Routledge, London, pp. 153-162 *Walton, K.L. (1990). Mimesis as Make-Believe, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

- Free Logic

Bencivenga, E. (1986) “Free Logics,” in D. Gabbay and F. Guenthner (eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic, vol. III: Alternatives to Classical Logic, Dordrecht: D. Reidel, pp. 373–426. Lambert, K. 1983. Meinong and the of independence: its place in Meinong's theory of objects and its significance in contemporary philosophical logic. Cambridge [Cambridgeshire]: Cambridge University Press. - 2001 “Free Logics,” in Lou Goble (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, pp. 258–279. Nolt, J. “Free Logic”, in Stanford Encyclodia of Philosophy http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-free/ Sainsbury, R. M., 2005, Reference without Referents, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Topic 2: Truth in Fiction and Imaginative Resistance

Truth in Fiction Alward, P. ‘Truth in fiction: the story concluded’ working paper. Beardsley, Monroe. Aesthetics: Problems in the Philosophy of Criticism, 2nd ed. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1980. *Byrne, Alex. ‘Truth in Fiction: The Story Continued.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (1993): 34–25. Currie, Gregory. The Nature of Fiction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1990. ——. ‘Unreliability Refigured: Narrative in Literature and Film.’ Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 (1995a): 19–29. ——. ‘On Being Fictional.’ Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 55 (1995b): 425–7. Hanley, Richard. ‘As Good As It Gets: Lewis on Truth in Fiction.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82 (2004): 112–28. Lamarque, Peter and Stein Haugom Olsen. Truth, Fiction and Literature, Oxford: Clarendon Press. 1994. Le Poidevin, Robin. ‘Worlds within Worlds? The Paradoxes of Embedded Fiction.’ The British Journal of Aesthetics 35 (1995): 227–38. Levinstein, Ben. ‘Facts, Interpretation and Truth in Fiction.’ The British Journal of Aesthetics 47 (2007): 64–75. *Lewis, David. ‘Truth in Fiction.’American Journal of Philosophy 15 (1978): 37–46. Reprinted with an added postscript in his Philosophical Papers 1, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983. 261-80. Matravers, Derek. ‘Beliefs and Fictional Narrators.’ Analysis 55 (1995): 121–2. Pavel, Thomas. Fictional Worlds. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1986. Phillips, John. ‘Truth and Inference in Fiction.’ Philosophical Studies 94 (1999): 273–93. Priest, Graham. ‘Sylvan’s Box: A short story and ten morals.’ Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38 (1997): 573– 82. Proudfoot, Diane. ‘Possible Worlds Semantics and Fiction.’ Journal of Philosophical Logic 35 (2006): 9–40. Robinson, Jenefer. ‘Style and Personality in the Literary Work.’ Philosophical Review 94 (1985): 147–58. Searle, John. ‘The Logical Status of Fictional Discourse.’ New Literary History 6 (1975): 319–32. Walton, Kendall. Mimesis as Make-Believe. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1990. Wolterstorff, Nicholas. Worlds and Works of Art. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980. Woods, John. The Logic of Fiction: A Philosophical Sounding of Deviant Logic. The Hague: Mouton, 1974.

The Puzzle of Imaginative Resistance

*Gendler, T. (2000). “The puzzle of imaginative resistance.” The Journal of Philosophy, 97, 55–81. Gendler, T. (2003). “On the relation between pretence and belief”, In M. Kieran & D. Lopes (Eds.), Imagination, philosophy and the arts. Routledge. - “Imagination” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Mahtani, A. (2012). Imaginative Resistance Without Conflict. Philosophical Studies 158 (3):415-429. Moran, R. (1994). “The expression of feeling in imagination”, The Philosophical Review, 103, 75–106. Peacocke, C. (1985) “Imagination, possibility and ”, In J. Foster & H. Robinson (Eds.), Essays on Berkeley. Oxford University Press. Stock, K. (2003). “The tower of Goldbach and other impossible tales”, In M. Kieran & D. Lopes (Eds.), Imagination, philosophy and the arts. London: Routledge. *Stock, K. (2005). “Resisting imaginative resistance”, The Philosophical Quarterly, 55, 607–624. Stock, K (2013). “Imagining and Fiction: Some Issues”. Philosophy Compass 8 (10): 887- 896. Walton, K. (1990). Mimesis as make-believe. Harvard University Press. Walton, K. (1994). “Morals in fiction and fictional morality”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 68, 27–50. Walton, K. (2006). “On the (so-called) puzzle of imaginative resistance”, In S. Nichols (Ed.), The architecture of the imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Weatherson, B. (2004). “Morality, fiction and possibility”, ’ Imprint, 4, 1–27. Weinberg, J., & Meskin, A. (2006). “Puzzling over the imagination: Philosophical problems, architectural solutions”, In S. Nichols (Ed.), The architecture of the imagination. New York: Oxford University Press. Yablo, S. (1993). “Is conceivability a guide to possibility?” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 53, 1–42. Yablo, S. (2002). “Coulda, Woulda, Shoulda”, In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and possibility. Oxford University Press.

Topic 3 Fictionalism

Brock, S. (2002), “Fictionalism about Fictional Characters”, Noûs, 36: 1–21. *Dorr, C. and G. Rosen (2002) “Composition as a Fiction”, in R. Gale (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Metaphysics, Oxford: Blackwell. (also here: http://philpapers.org/archive/DORCAA.pdf) Eklund, M. (2002) “ on Material ”, Ratio, 15: 245–56. Eklund, M. (2005) “Fiction, Indifference, and Ontology”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 71: 557–79. Eklund, M. (2009) “The Frege-Geach Problem and Kalderon's Moral Fictionalism”, Philosophical Quarterly, 59: 705–12. Fine, A. (1993) “Fictionalism”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 18: 1–18. Hinckfuss, I. (1993) “Suppositions, Presuppositions, and Ontology”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 23: 595–618. Hussain, N. (2004) “The Return of Moral Fictionalism”, Philosophical Perspectives,18: 149–87. Joyce, R. (2001) The Myth of Morality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. *Joyce, R. (2005) “Moral Fictionalism”, in Kalderon (2005), pp. 287–313. Kalderon, M., (ed.), (2005) Fictionalism in Metaphysics, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Kalderon, M., (2005a) Moral Fictionalism, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Kennedy, C. and J. Stanley (2009) “On ‘Average’”, Mind, 118: 583–646. Lenman, J. (2008), “Against Moral Fictionalism”, Philosophical Books, 49: 23–32. Lillehammer, H. (2004), “Moral Error Theory”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 104: 95–111. Nolan, D., G. Restall and C. West (2005) “Moral Fictionalism Versus the Rest”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 83: 307–30. Rosen, G. (1990) “Modal Fictionalism”, Mind, 99: 327–54. Rosen, G. (2005) “Problems in the History of Fictionalism”, in Kalderon (2005), pp. 14– 64. *Sainsbury, R.M. (2009) Fiction and Fictionalism, London: Routledge. Sider, T. (1993) “Van Inwagen and the Possibility of Gunk”, Analysis, 53: 285–9. *Stanley, J. (2001) “Hermeneutic Fictionalism”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 25 (1):36–71. < http://philpapers.org/archive/STAHF.pdf> Van Inwagen, P. (1990) Material Beings, Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press. Yablo, S. (2006), “Non-Catastrophic Presupposition Failure”, in J. Thomson and A. Byrne (eds.), Content and Modality: Themes from the Philosophy of Robert Stalnaker, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Seminars

There will be two seminars (you must sign up for one of them) every week from week 3 to week 12. Each seminar will focus on a text. You are required to read this and bring a copy to the seminar.

Week 3: Quine W.V.O. (1948). “On What There Is”, Review of Metaphysics, 2: 21–38. Reprinted in W.V. O. Quine, From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953.

Week 4: Parsons, T. (1979). “The Methodology of Nonexistence.” Journal of Philosophy 76 (11): 649-662.

Week 5: Thomasson, A.L. (1999). Fiction and Metaphysics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Chapter 1.

Week 6: Schaffer, j. (2009). “On What Grounds What”. In David Manley, David J. Chalmers & Ryan Wasserman (eds.), Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Oxford University Press. 347-383 (2009)

Week 7: Walton, K. (1978). “Fearing Fictions”. The Journal of Philosophy 75 (1): 5- 27.

Week 8: Lewis, D. (1978) ‘Truth in Fiction.’ American Journal of Philosophy 15: 37– 46. Reprinted with an added postscript in his Philosophical Papers 1, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983. 261-80.

Week 9: Gendler, T. (2000). “The puzzle of imaginative resistance.” The Journal of Philosophy, 97, 55–81.

Week 10: Stanley, J. (2001) “Hermeneutic Fictionalism”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 25 (1): 36–71.

Week 11: Joyce, R. (2005) “Moral Fictionalism”, in M. Kalderon (2005) ed. Fictionalism in Metaphysics, Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 287–313.

Plagiarism

The following are serious academic offences and may result in penalties that could have a lasting effect on your career, both at University and beyond.

Plagiarism (either intentional or unintentional) is the stealing of ideas or work of another person (including experts and fellow or former students) and is considered dishonest and unprofessional. Plagiarism may take the form of cutting and pasting, taking or closely paraphrasing ideas, passages, sections, sentences, paragraphs, drawings, graphs and other graphical material from books, articles, internet sites or any other source and submitting them for assessment without appropriate acknowledgement.

Submitting bought or commissioned work (for example from internet sites, essay “banks” or “mills”) is an extremely serious form of plagiarism. This may take the form of buying or commissioning either the whole assignment or part of it and implies a clear to deceive the examiners. The University also takes an extremely serious view of any student who sells, offers to sell or passes on their own assignments to other students.

Double submission (or self plagiarism) is resubmitting previously submitted work on one or more occasions (without proper acknowledgement). This may take the form of copying either the whole assignment or part of it. Normally credit will already have been given for this work.

Collusion is where two or more people work together to produce a piece of work, all or part of which is then submitted by each of them as their own individual work. This includes passing on work in any format to another student. Collusion does not occur where students involved in group work are encouraged to work together to produce a single piece of work as part of the assessment process.

More on plagiarism in particular: In any essay or exam answer submitted for assessment, all passages taken from other people's work, either word for word, or with small changes, must be placed within quotation marks, with specific reference to author, title and page. No excuse can be accepted for any failure to do so, nor will inclusion of the source in a bibliography be considered an adequate acknowledgement. If the marker decides that plagiarism has occurred, it becomes a of report to a University Committee. The student may be judged to have failed the essay and/or exam and/or module (depending on the degree of severity). The plagiarism will also be recorded on the student's record.

Plagiarism from handouts: There has in the past been some scope for confusion on this issue, since many staff offer the advice that ideas deriving from the lecturer do not need to be cited when used. But the department has agreed that a distinction needs to be drawn between use of ideas or arguments expounded in lectures, on the one hand (which is legitimate without citation), and verbatim or near-verbatim reproduction of material from lecture handouts or lecture notes/transcripts, on the other hand (which is not). Any essay that is judged to rely too heavily on course handouts — even when it is considered to fall short of plagiarism — will be penalised.