Belief Dynamics ILLC Dissertation Series 2001-08

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Belief Dynamics ILLC Dissertation Series 2001-08 Belief Dynamics ILLC Dissertation Series 2001-08 For further information about ILLC-publications, please contact Institute for Logic, Language and Computation Universiteit van Amsterdam Plantage Muidergracht 24 1018 TV Amsterdam phone: +31-20-525 6051 fax: +31-20-525 5206 e-mail: [email protected] homepage: http://www.illc.uva.nl/ Belief Dynamics (Epistemo)logical Investigations Academisch Proefschrift ter verkrijging van de graad van doctor aan de Universiteit van Amsterdam op gezag van de Rector Magni¯cus prof. dr. J.J.M. Franse ten overstaan van een door het college voor promoties ingestelde commissie, in het openbaar te verdedigen in de Aula der Universiteit op dinsdag 13 november 2001, te 10.00 uur door Allard Martijn Tamminga geboren te Nijmegen Promotor: Prof. dr. F.J.M.M. Veltman Co-promotor: Prof. dr. H. Rott Afdeling Wijsbegeerte Faculteit der Geesteswetenschappen Universiteit van Amsterdam Nieuwe Doelenstraat 15 1012 CP Amsterdam Copyright °c 2001 by Allard Tamminga Cover design by [lowresmedia.com] Cover photos by Roesmann/Essamba Arts Printed and bound by Febodruk, Enschede ISBN: 90{5776{075{4 Notre t^ete est ronde pour permettre `a la pens¶ee de changer de direction. Francis Picabia v Contents Acknowledgments ix 1 Introduction 1 1.1 General Overview . 1 1.2 Summary . 2 2 Truth as Limit of Inquiry? 7 2.1 Introduction . 7 2.2 C.S. Peirce's Theory of Scienti¯c Inquiry . 10 2.2.1 Analytic and Synthetic Reasoning . 13 2.2.2 Deduction, Induction, and Abduction . 15 2.3 Truth in Terms of Inquiry . 19 2.3.1 The T{I Conditional versus Bivalence . 21 2.3.2 The I{T Conditional is Wide of the Mark . 24 2.4 Conclusion . 28 3 Isaac Levi's Epistemology: A Critique 29 3.1 Isaac Levi's Epistemology . 29 3.1.1 Non-Deductive Logic and the Belief-Doubt-Belief Model . 29 3.1.2 Epistemic States and Their Representations . 33 3.1.3 Revision of Corpora . 38 3.1.4 Two Applications . 47 3.2 A Critique . 50 3.2.1 Corpora? . 50 3.2.2 Contextual Parameters? . 51 3.3 Conclusion . 58 vii 4 Finite State Belief Dynamics 61 4.1 Paraconsistent Belief Revision? . 62 4.1.1 A Novel Approach . 63 4.2 Preliminaries . 64 4.2.1 An Algorithm for Finding Á's Minimal Valuations . 67 4.2.2 Finite States and Their Determiners . 69 4.2.3 Finite States: Information Span . 72 4.3 Operations of Information Change . 74 4.3.1 Expansion . 74 4.3.2 Contraction . 77 4.3.3 Revision . 80 4.4 Extractors: Operations of Belief Retrieval . 81 4.4.1 Making K? Consistent . 82 4.4.2 Selecting K?'s Most Consistent Valuations . 86 4.5 Future Work . 88 4.5.1 Finite State Belief Revision . 88 4.5.2 Relative Trustworthiness of the Sources . 89 4.5.3 Inconsistency-Adaptive Logics . 90 5 Conclusion 91 5.1 Summary of the Results . 91 5.2 Future Work . 92 A A Natural Deduction System for First Degree Entailment 95 A.1 Introduction . 95 A.1.1 First Degree Entailment . 95 A.1.2 Combined Systems . 96 A.2 Language and Semantics . 98 A.3 A Natural Deduction System . 99 A.4 Soundness . 101 A.5 Completeness . 102 A.6 Rejection Eliminated? . 107 Bibliography 111 Samenvatting 119 viii Acknowledgments First and foremost, thanks are due to my promotor, Frank Veltman, and to my co-promotor, Hans Rott. I thank them for the freedom of research they granted me, for their continuing encouragement, and for their constructive criticisms. Second, I wish to thank Johan van Benthem, Wiebe van der Hoek, Erik Krabbe, Michiel van Lambalgen, and Martin Stokhof, for their willingness to participate in the reading committee. Third, I thank Koji Tanaka for being the co-author of the Appendix. More- over, I thank Walter van der Star for translating the second and third chapters of my dissertation into English. Lastly, the following people discussed parts of the thesis with me and thus helped me to improve on the ¯nal text: Paul Dekker, Eduardo Ferm¶e, Jelle Gerbrandy, Carin Gotlieb, Paul Harrenstein, Wolfram Hinzen, Else de Jonge, Theo Kuipers, Karen Kwast, Rosja Mastop, Breannd¶an O¶ Nuall¶ain, Jeanne Pei- jnenburg, Graham Priest, Harry Stein, Anne Troelstra, and Sjoerd Zwart. The conversations with them has made the writing of this thesis an enjoyment. Parts of my thesis have been published as articles in journals. I would like to thank the journals for their kind permission to include these articles in the present thesis. Chapter 2 appeared in Dutch as `Waarheid als limiet van on- derzoek: de ontoereikendheid van Charles Sanders Peirce' waarheidsopvatting' in the Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 93, 2001, pages 73{92. The Appendix, the result of joint work with Koji Tanaka, appeared in 2001 as `A Natural Deduction System for First Degree Entailment' in the Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40, 1999, pages 258{272. Amsterdam amt September, 2001. ix Chapter 1 Introduction 1.1 General Overview This thesis deals with the dynamics of belief. In three interconnected, though independent studies, a viable alternative to foundational approaches in episte- mology is explored. Rather than accept the research agenda dictated by tradi- tional epistemology, with its stress on the pursuit of conditions under which our beliefs are justi¯ed or even true, the present work follows the lead of American pragmatism, and focusses on the articulation and defense of criteria according to which a change of mind may be judged legitimate. The second and third chapters discuss the attempts of two pragmatist philoso- phers, Charles Sanders Peirce and Isaac Levi, to formulate and to formalize the belief-doubt-belief model, a model that sets out to set forth systematically the optimal strategies according to which to change our minds. In the course of this undertaking, more and more logical considerations come to the fore, culminating in a discussion and an evaluation of formal systems for belief change. It is argued that belief change systems, despite the naturalistic setting in which they were ¯rst conceived, have outgrown their pragmatist origin and have metamorphosed into a branch of philosophical logic, where empirical considerations have become obsolete. To restore the connection between logical theory and epistemological practice, a case is made for reformulations of belief change systems that are cleared from elements that obstruct practical applications and empirical tests. In the fourth chapter, a belief change system is presented that (1) uses ¯nite representations of epistemic states, (2) can deal with inconsistencies adequately, (3) has ¯nite operations of change, (4) can do without, but does not rule out, extra-logical elements, and (5) only licenses consistent beliefs. An Appendix, where the underlying logic of the belief change system of the fourth chapter is studied proof-theoretically, concludes the thesis. 1 2 Chapter 1. Introduction 1.2 Summary In order to pave the way for more fruitful logical and epistemological investiga- tions within the pragmatist tradition in philosophy, the second chapter clears the ground from metaphysical entanglements that result from the wish to construct theories of truth and reality, a wish that has, by and large, dominated the in- terests of pragmatist philosophers (and not only them) until the present day. A focus on the necessary and su±cient conditions for a statement to be true or on a conception of reality which is adequate to a preferred reading of the truth predicate still obfuscate research in contemporary epistemology, as they tend to restrict philosophical research to questions which have resisted plausible answers for ages. Hence, the second chapter purports to show that Peirce's metaphysical aspi- rations for de¯nitions of truth and reality in terms of a theory of inquiry cannot coherently be met by a pragmatist theory of knowledge. In order to come to grips with Peirce's de¯nition of truth as the ideal limit of inquiry, a succinct exposition of Peirce's theory of inquiry and his philosophical logic is given. Attention is paid to deductive, inductive, and abductive reasoning and their interrelations, so as to be in a position to sketch Peirce's early ideas concerning the pragmatist belief- doubt-belief model, a model that will be the guiding line of this thesis. With his investigations into that model, Peirce aimed to articulate the `method of science', a method that enables us to adapt our present pattern of expectations for the better in case of surprising or even contrary experience. Peirce maintained that if we would consciously follow the method of science, we would ultimately reach a pattern of expectations that would never be thwarted by any future experience. Since such a pattern of expectations would lead to the very same practical con- sequences as a true `theory of the world', to borrow a phrase of Quine's, Peirce's pragmatist stand on meaning forbids him to withhold the predicate `true' from that pattern of expectations. Thus Peirce accounts for the notion of truth. In the remainder of the second chapter, the arguments of the foremost rep- resentative of a group of contemporary apologists of Peirce's account of truth, Cheryl Misak, are subjected to scrutiny and found to be insu±cient: the princi- ple of bivalence is defended improperly and her main argumentation for a Peircean account of truth turns out to be incompatible with a pragmatist epistemology. Hence, Peircean accounts of truth are found to be inadequate. Rather than accept the problem setting of traditional philosophy, with its focus on truth and reality, and plead, in the face of the failure of Peircean accounts of truth, for some alter- native view on truth, the chapter ends with a plea for a more modest approach.
Recommended publications
  • Stanislaw Piatkiewicz and the Beginnings of Mathematical Logic in Poland
    HISTORIA MATHEMATICA 23 (1996), 68±73 ARTICLE NO. 0005 Stanisøaw PiaËtkiewicz and the Beginnings of Mathematical Logic in Poland TADEUSZ BATO G AND ROMAN MURAWSKI View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Adam Mickiewicz University, ul. Matejki 48/49, 60-769 PoznanÂ, Poland provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector This paper presents information on the life and work of Stanisøaw PiaËtkiewicz (1849±?). His Algebra w logice (Algebra in Logic) of 1888 contains an exposition of the algebra of logic and its use in representing syllogisms. This was the ®rst original Polish publication on symbolic logic. It appeared 20 years before analogous works by èukasiewicz and Stamm. 1996 Academic Press, Inc. In dem Aufsatz werden Informationen zu Leben und Werk von Stanisøaw PiaËtkiewicz (1849±?) gegeben. Sein Algebra w logice (Algebra in der Logik) von 1888 enthaÈlt eine Darstel- lung der Algebra der Logik und ihre Anwendung auf die Syllogistik. PiaËtkiewicz' Schrift war die erste polnische Publikation uÈ ber symbolische Logik. Sie erschien 20 Jahre vor aÈhnlichen Arbeiten von èukasiewicz und Stamm. 1996 Academic Press, Inc. W pracy przedstawiono osobeË i dzieøo Stanisøawa PiaËtkiewicza (1849±?). W szczego lnosÂci analizuje sieË jego rozpraweË Algebra w logice z roku 1888, w kto rej zajmowaø sieË on nowymi no wczas ideami algebry logiki oraz ich zastosowaniami do sylogistyki. Praca ta jest pierwszaË oryginalnaË polskaË publikacjaË z zakresu logiki symbolicznej. Ukazaøa sieË 20 lat przed analog- icznymi pracami èukasiewicza i Stamma. 1996 Academic Press, Inc. MSC 1991 subject classi®cations: 03-03, 01A55.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Late British Associationism and Its Context This Is a Story About Philosophy. Or About Science
    Chapter 1: An Introduction to Late British Associationism and Its Context This is a story about philosophy. Or about science. Or about philosophy transforming into science. Or about science and philosophy, and how they are related. Or were, in a particular time and place. At least, that is the general area that the following narrative will explore, I hope with sufficient subtlety. The matter is rendered non-transparent by the fact that that the conclusions one draws with regard to such questions are, in part, matters of discretionary perspective – as I will try to demonstrate. My specific historical focus will be on the propagation of a complex intellectual tradition concerned with human sensation, perception, and mental function in early nineteenth century Britain. Not only philosophical opinion, but all aspects of British intellectual – and practical – life, were in the process of significant transformation during this time. This cultural flux further confuses recovery of the situated significance of the intellectual tradition I am investigating. The study of the mind not only was influenced by a set of broad social shifts, but it also participated in them fully as both stimulus to and recipient of changing conditions. One indication of this is simply the variety of terms used to identify the ‘philosophy of mind’ as an intellectual enterprise in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.1 But the issue goes far deeper into the fluid constitutive features of the enterprise - including associated conceptual systems, methods, intentions of practitioners, and institutional affiliations. In order to understand philosophy of mind in its time, we must put all these factors into play.
    [Show full text]
  • Neural Networks
    Neural Networks 1. Introduction Spring 2020 1 Neural Networks are taking over! • Neural networks have become one of the major thrust areas recently in various pattern recognition, prediction, and analysis problems • In many problems they have established the state of the art – Often exceeding previous benchmarks by large margins 2 Breakthroughs with neural networks 3 Breakthrough with neural networks 4 Image segmentation and recognition 5 Image recognition https://www.sighthound.com/technology/ 6 Breakthroughs with neural networks 7 Success with neural networks • Captions generated entirely by a neural network 8 Breakthroughs with neural networks ThisPersonDoesNotExist.com uses AI to generate endless fake faces – https://www.theverge.com/tldr/2019/2/15/18226005/ai-generated- fake-people-portraits-thispersondoesnotexist-stylegan 9 Successes with neural networks • And a variety of other problems: – From art to astronomy to healthcare.. – and even predicting stock markets! 10 Neural nets can do anything! 11 Neural nets and the employment market This guy didn’t know This guy learned about neural networks about neural networks (a.k.a deep learning) (a.k.a deep learning) 12 Objectives of this course • Understanding neural networks • Comprehending the models that do the previously mentioned tasks – And maybe build them • Familiarity with some of the terminology – What are these: • http://www.datasciencecentral.com/profiles/blogs/concise-visual- summary-of-deep-learning-architectures • Fearlessly design, build and train networks for various tasks
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatism and 'Pragmatism'
    Appendix THE BEGINNING OF PRAGMATISM AND 'PRAGMATISM' PEIRCE CLAIMS TO HAVE USED THE WORD "PRAGMATISM" in philosophical conversations from the mid-'seventies on, to designate his theory of be­ lief, and, although he explained the main elements of his pragmatic theory of meaning in the two articles published in the Popular Science Monthly in 1877 and 1878, he still did not dare to use the word "prag­ matism" in print until 1902. He used it then only in response to a spe­ cial request, in Baldwin's Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, under the heading "Pragmatism" (5.414n; 5.1-4). In preparing to write the articles for Baldwin, Peirce wrote to James on November 10, 1900: "Who originated the term pragmatism, I or you? Where did it first appear in print? What do you understand by it?" And on a postcard dated November 26, 1900 James replied: "You invented 'pragmatism' for which I gave you full credit in a lecture entitled 'Philosophical con­ ceptions and practical results' of which I sent you 2 (unacknowledged) copies a couple of years ago" (8.253). The lecture to which James refers was his famous paper delivered in 1898 at the University of California, wherein he presented his views of pragmatism. James' understanding of pragmatism was so different from Peirce's that the latter, to avoid ambiguity, devised a n ew term "pragmaticism" to describe his doctrine, in an article in The Monist in 1905. "The writer, finding his bantling 'pragmatism' so promoted, feels 147 148 PEIRCE's THEORY OF SCIENTIFIC METIIOD that it is time to kiss his child good-by and relinquish it to its higher destiny; while to serve the precise purpose of expressing the original definition, he begs to announce the birth of the word 'pragmaticism,' which is ugly enough to be safe from kidnappers" (5.414).
    [Show full text]
  • The Development and Early Research Results of Mill Marginalia Online
    ILCEA Revue de l’Institut des langues et cultures d'Europe, Amérique, Afrique, Asie et Australie 39 | 2020 Les humanités numériques dans une perspective internationale : opportunités, défis, outils et méthodes Handwritten Marginalia and Digital Search: The Development and Early Research Results of Mill Marginalia Online Marginalia manuscrits et recherche numérique : développement et résultats préliminaires de l’édition en ligne de Mill Marginalia. Albert D. Pionke Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ilcea/8582 DOI: 10.4000/ilcea.8582 ISSN: 2101-0609 Publisher UGA Éditions/Université Grenoble Alpes Printed version ISBN: 978-2-37747-174-4 ISSN: 1639-6073 Electronic reference Albert D. Pionke, « Handwritten Marginalia and Digital Search: The Development and Early Research Results of Mill Marginalia Online », ILCEA [Online], 39 | 2020, Online since 03 March 2020, connection on 10 October 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/ilcea/8582 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/ ilcea.8582 This text was automatically generated on 10 October 2020. © ILCEA Handwritten Marginalia and Digital Search: The Development and Early Research... 1 Handwritten Marginalia and Digital Search: The Development and Early Research Results of Mill Marginalia Online Marginalia manuscrits et recherche numérique : développement et résultats préliminaires de l’édition en ligne de Mill Marginalia. Albert D. Pionke 1 Victorian Britain’s leading philosophical empiricist and liberal theorist—and, perhaps the dominant figure in Victorian intellectual life from the 1860s, when he was elected to Parliament as Liberal Member for Westminster, through the 1880s, the decade after his death in which intellectuals in a variety of fields continued to define themselves with respect to his legacy—John Stuart Mill authored significant works on logic, epistemology, political economy, aesthetics, and social reform.
    [Show full text]
  • UNIVERSITY of CALIFORNIA Los Angeles Dread: the Literary History
    UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Los Angeles Dread: The Literary History of a Political Affect, 1750-1900 A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in English by Samantha Ellen Morse 2020 © Copyright by Samantha Ellen Morse 2020 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Dread: The Literary History of a Political Affect, 1750-1900 by Samantha Ellen Morse Doctor of Philosophy in English University of California, Los Angeles 2020 Professor Sarah Tindal Kareem, Chair This dissertation analyzes the cultural urgency of dread—a profound feeling of fear about the future—in a range of canonical and popular British novels, poems, periodicals, and philosophical treatises. In our own time, we tend to think of dread as a negative, paralyzing affect. Yet I elucidate the many ways in which nineteenth-century authors, philosophers, political reformers, and theologians regarded this feeling as an impetus for bringing about a better future. The anticipatory qualities of dread served as a catalyst for ethical and political transformations in the Enlightenment all the way through the Victorian era. Beginning with David Hume and ending with H. G. Wells, I examine the ways in which dread entered into and shaped philosophical thought, popular culture, and political life, especially radicalism, through shifting literary forms, many of which stemmed from the Gothic mode. While numerous studies have investigated fearful affects such as terror, horror, and anxiety, my dissertation is the first ii sustained examination of dread, which reconceptualizes the Gothic’s literary and political significance. While it is a critical commonplace that Gothic fiction stages encounters with the past, I show how the Gothic stimulates dread in order to orient its readers toward future possibilities.
    [Show full text]
  • Empiricist Roots of Modern Psychology
    Raymond Martin Department of Philosophy Union College Schenectady, NY 12308 USA Empiricist Roots of Modern Psychology From the thirteenth through the sixteenth centuries, European philosophers were preoccupied with using their newfound access to Aristotle’s metaphysics and natural philosophy to develop an integrated account, hospitable to Christianity, of everything that was thought to exist, including God, pure finite spirits (angels), the immaterial souls of humans, the natural world of organic objects (plants, animals, and human bodies) and inorganic objects. This account included a theory of human mentality. In the sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries, first in astronomy and then, later, in physics, the tightly knit fabric of this comprehensive medieval world view began to unravel. The transition from the old to the new was gradual, but by 1687, with the publication by Isaac Newton (1642-1727) of his Principia Mathematica, the replacement was all but complete. Modern physical science had fully arrived, and it was secular. God and angels were still acknowledged. But they had been marginalized. Yet, there was a glaring omission. Theorists had yet to expand the reach of the new science to incorporate human mentality. This venture, which initially was called “moral philosophy” and came to be called “the science of human nature,” became compelling to progressive eighteenth century thinkers, just as British empiricism began to seriously challenge an entrenched Cartesian rationalism. Rationalism and Empiricism The dispute between rationalists and empiricists was primarily over concepts and knowledge. In response to such questions as, where does the mind get its stock of concepts, how do humans justify what they take to be their knowledge, and how far does human knowledge extend, rationalists maintained that some concepts are innate, and hence not derived from experience, and that reason, or intuition, by itself, independently of experience, is an important source of knowledge, including of existing [25] 1 things.
    [Show full text]
  • Humour and Incongruity JOHN LIPPITT
    Humour and incongruity JOHN LIPPITT The first in aseries of articles on the philosophy of humour and laughter looks at attempts made to explain humour in terms of incongruity. Introduction The philosophy of humour and laughter is a rarely studied field. This is despite the fact that many of the West's most celebrated thinkers-Plato, Aristotle, Descartes, Hobbes, Kant, Schopenhauer, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, Bergson, Freud-have advanced views on the subject; and the fact that interdisciplinary research on humour has grown enormously in the recent past. This series of articles will attempt to offer a survey of some major views on the nature of humour and laughter. Throughout, in line with contemporary humour research, 'humour' will be used as an umbrella term to cover all categories of the funny; the general term of which wit, satire, jokes, etc., may be viewed as subcategories. Contemporary humour researchers often divide accounts of humour into three main theoretical traditions, focusing on, respectively, incongruity, superiority and the release of energy. We will consider one of these traditions in each of the first three articles. This first piece will examine the 'incongruity' tradition; it will offer a critical analysis of attempts made to argue that the nature of humour is to be explained in terms of incongruity. By far the most commonly discussed comments in this tradition are those of Arthur Schopenhauer, and we will turn to these shortly. But a brief comment from Kant's Critique of Judgement will be useful to get us going. Kant claims that: 'Something absurd (something in which, therefore, the understanding can of itself find no delight) must be present in whatever is to raise a hearty convulsive laugh.
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatism in Florence: the Magicians and the Logicians
    Chapter 1 Pragmatism in Florence: The Magicians and the Logicians Cornelis de Waal As, to papal minds, protestantism has often seemed a mere mess of anar- chy and confusion, such, no doubt, will pragmatism often seem to ultra- rationalist minds in philosophy. William James Pragmatism is often seen as America’s contribution to world philosophy. It emerged in the early 1870s when a small group of young men from Cambridge, Massachusetts, came together to discuss philosophy. With an ironic and defi- ant air, they called themselves—in honour of a discipline they considered obsolete—The Metaphysical Club. No records of their meetings survive, but from correspondence and publications it is clear that they rejected philosophy as it was practiced at the time. The group included, among others, William James (1842–1910), Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914), and the future Supreme Court justice Oliver Wendell Holmes Jr. (1841–1935). At a pivotal moment their discussions centered around Alexander Bain’s definition of belief as “that upon which a man is prepared to act.” As Peirce later recalled, once that definition is granted, pragmatism follows almost immediately. In the eyes of both Peirce and James, who became the first major proponents of this philosophical out- look, pragmatism was not some revolutionary new approach, but was merely the conscious and systematic adoption of a method that philosophers had been practicing from antiquity onward. Peirce boldly declared that the new- ness of a philosophical idea is one of the surest signs that it is false, and he called even Jesus a pragmatist. James sought to drive home this same point when he subtitled his famous book Pragmatism as “A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking.” Despite the pragmatists’ claim that philosophers have always been practic- ing pragmatism, its explicit enunciation as a method for doing philosophy by James, Peirce, and others got a cold reception in Europe, where it was seen as designed for people who have little patience for philosophy and who prefer to stick to practical affairs.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mystery of Common Sense
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by CommonKnowledge Essays in Philosophy Volume 3 Article 2 Issue 2 Pragmatism and Neopragmatism 6-2002 Who is Exaggerating? The ysM tery of Common Sense Heidi Salaverria Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/eip Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Salaverria, Heidi (2002) "Who is Exaggerating? The ysM tery of Common Sense," Essays in Philosophy: Vol. 3: Iss. 2, Article 2. Essays in Philosophy is a biannual journal published by Pacific nivU ersity Library | ISSN 1526-0569 | http://commons.pacificu.edu/eip/ Essays in Philosophy Essays in Philosophy A Biannual Journal Volume 3, Number 2 Who is Exaggerating? The Mystery of Common Sense “The most difficult thing in the world to learn to see is the obvious, the familiar, the universally taken for granted.”1 (John Dewey) Throughout the history of Pragmatism, the notion of common sense has been recurrent, but rather than a central feature it seems to be an underlying, over the time changing, and indefinite motif, which nevertheless has unceasingly accompanied pragmatist thought. common sense has taken on a range of meanings, varying from vague beliefs, everyday-knowledge, common experience, sound understanding, good judgment, anachronistic truth, hidden intuition, custom and routine on the one hand to innate knowledge and universal truth on the other hand - just to name a few. To add some confusion, common sense has sometimes been located in the past, sometimes in the present or even in the future. It focuses either on epistemological, moral, or aesthetic questions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy David Hume
    THE PHILOSOPHY OF DAVID HUME A CRITICAL STUDY OF ITS ORIGINS AND CENTRAL DOCTRINES BY NORMAN KEMP SMITH D.LITT., LL.D., F.B.A. SOMETIME PROFESSOR OF LOGIC AND METAPHYSICS IN THE UNIVERSITY Or EDINBURGH WITH A NEW INTRODUCTION BY DON GARRETT ©Norman Kemp Smith 1941 Introduction © Don Garrett ZOOS All rights reserved. No reproduction, copy or transmission of this publication may be made without written permisston. No paragraph of th1s publication may be reproduced, copied or transmitt save with written permission or in accordance with the provisions of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, or under the terms of any licen· permitting limited copying issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency, 90 Totten ham Court Road, London W1T 4LP. Any person who does any unauthorised act in relation to this publication may be liable to criminal prosecution and civil claims for damages. The authors have asserted their rights to be identified as the authors oft work in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. First published 1941 This edition published 2005 by PALGRAVE MACMILLAN Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire RG21 6XS and 175 Fifth Avenue, New York, N.Y. 10010 Companies and representatives throughout the world PALGRAVE MACMILLAN is the global academic imprint of the Palgrave Macmillan division of St. Martin's Press, LLC and of Palgrave Macmillan Lt Macmillan"' is a registered trademark in the United States, United Kingdc and other countries. Palgrave is a registered trademark in the European Union and other countries. ISBN 978-1-4039-1507-8 ISBN 978-0-230-51117-0 (eBook) DOI 10.1057/9780230511170 This book is printed on paper suitable for recycling and made from fully managed and sustained forest sources.
    [Show full text]
  • European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IX-1 | 2017 Habit Beyond Psychology 2
    European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy IX-1 | 2017 Pragmatism and Psychologism Habit Beyond Psychology The Evolution Of The Concept Aleksandar Feodorov Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/1007 DOI: 10.4000/ejpap.1007 ISSN: 2036-4091 Publisher Associazione Pragma Electronic reference Aleksandar Feodorov, « Habit Beyond Psychology », European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy [Online], IX-1 | 2017, Online since 22 July 2017, connection on 12 June 2020. URL : http:// journals.openedition.org/ejpap/1007 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/ejpap.1007 This text was automatically generated on 12 June 2020. Author retains copyright and grants the European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy right of first publication with the work simultaneously licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. Habit Beyond Psychology 1 Habit Beyond Psychology The Evolution Of The Concept Aleksandar Feodorov Introduction 1 Psychologists would often attribute the success or failure of our everyday behavior to the habits we develop throughout our lives. Walking, eating or even speaking are acquired habits, whereas physiological processes like breathing or even the ability to think – inherent habits or instincts. Beyond the level of the individual, all conventions of society and moral values signaling the emergence of civilization can be analyzed into elements, which form a structural equivalent to the habits of a single person. Since it is possible to approach a given multitude such as a congestion of atoms or a social community as an individual, nothing surprising emerges out of these propositions: there is no immediate reason to doubt the effects of habit.
    [Show full text]