<<

Infinity Giraud’s Theorem 18 and 25 March 2019

The notion of a in infinity categories depends only of left exact localization unlike the clas- sical case because there does not exist a between left exact localization and Grothendieck in infinity categories. The main reference is Lurie [2].

Definition 1. Let X be an ∞-. We will say that X is an ∞-topos if there exists a small ∞-category C and accessible left exact localization L : P(C) → X. So the Giraud’s theorem for infinity categories is the following. Theorem 1. Let X be an ∞-category. The following conditions are equivalent: 1. The ∞-category X is an ∞-topos. 2. The ∞-category X satisfies the following ∞-categorical analogues of Giraud’s axioms: (a) The ∞-category X is presentable. (b) Colimits in X are universal. (c) in X are disjoint. (d) Every groupoid object of X is effective.

1 Background in ∞-topos theory

The idea of working with ∞-topos is analogous to the classical case, i.e. We prove all in the presheaves categories with help of the properties of the category of spaces S and we send all the constructions to the topos of study, and most of the constructions are conserved thanks to the left exact localization condition.

equivalent ∞-Giraud’s axioms notions Thanks to l.e.l. sends Left exact localizations ∞-topos all the construccions Works in looks like First prove in P(C) S prove "pointwise" in

Generalize in equivalent Giraud’s axioms notions Left exact localizations topos Grothendieck topologies Thanks to l.e.l. sends all the construccions looks Works in like

P(C) Sets prove pointwise in

1.1 Presentability The first Giraud axiom tells the category X is a λ-presentable ∞-category for some regular cardinal λ. To prove this axiom the following facts are needed. The first one is to characterize the λ-compact objects in P(C).

1 Proposition 1. Let C be a small ∞-category, λ a regular cardinal and F an object of P(C). The following conditions are equivalent:

1. The object F is λ-compact.

2. There exist a diagram p : K → C indexed by a λ-small simplicial , such that j ◦ p has a colimit G in P(C) and F is a retract 1 of G, where j : C → P(C) is the Yoneda embbeding.

The second one gives the tool of see a presheaf as a colimit of λ-compact objects. Lemma 1. Let C be a small and let j : C → P(C) denote the Yoneda embedding. Then idP(C) is a left of j along itself. To prove the previous staments we need some previous elements so only we uses their and the proofs can see in [2] as Proposition 5.3.4.17 and Lemma 5.1.5.3.

Proposition 2. Let C be a small ∞-category. The ∞-category of presheaves P(C) is presentable.

Proof. (Step 1) The category P(C) has small colimits.

We need to use the fact the category S has small colimits, and the colimits in P(C) are calculated ”pointwise", this mean if p : K → P(C) is a diagram, p : K. → P(C) is a colimit diagram iff . each pc : K → S is a colimit diagram for pc : K → S, where c is a vertex of C and pc = p ◦ ec with ec : P(C) → S the evaluation map.

. Since S is cocomplete then pc : K → S is a colimit diagram and this happens for each vertex c, we can conclude p : K. → P(C) is a colimit diagram. Therefore P(C) is cocomplete.

In fact, we can deduce this category has λ-filtered colimits using the same argument since S has λ-filtred colimits.

(Step 2) The of λ-compact objects Pλ (C).

The λ-compacts objects of P(C) are characterizad by the proposition 1. To prove Pλ (C) is small it will suffice to show that the collection of classes of objects in the homo- topy category Pλ (C) is small.

For this, we use the proposition 1, so every λ-compact object F of P(C) is a retract of some G, wich is itself the colimit of some composition.

p j K / C / P(C) where K is λ-small. Since there is a bounded collection of possibilities for K and p and a bounded collection of idempotent maps of Y in Pλ (C), there is an only bounded number of possibilities for F.

1Let C be a category. Let X,Y be objects of C, we will say Y is a retract of X if there is a :

X ? i r Y / Y idY

2 (Step 3) (Sketch) The subcategory Pλ (C) generates P(C) under filtered colimits.

λ Let F a presheaf, we can defined the slice category P (C)/F over F and construct a subcategory over this slice with the λ-compact objects of Pλ (C) as the following pullback:

λ P (C)/F / P(C)/F

  Pλ (C) / P(C)

If we define the following diagram

λ p : P (C)/F → P(C)/F → P(C)

It is possible to prove F is the colimit of p but we need two tecnical arguments an their are very extensive, the details can be find as Lemma 5.4.4.2 and Proposition 5.4.4.3 in [2]. The central idea of that arguments is ilustred in the example 1.

Example 1. Let C be a small category and let F a object of P(C). The Grothendieck construc- R tion C F is the category with objects the pairs (C,x) where C is a object of C and x ∈ F(C) and the arrows u : (C,x) → (C0,y) such that u : C → C0 is a in C and u(y) = x.

Fu F(C) F(C0)

x y

R λ We can see C F as a slice category, in fact like P (C)/F , the proof of this generalize the next R one: C y(C) = C/c where y is the Yoneda embedding and y(C) = HomC(−,C).

R Let u : (X, f ) → (Y,g) be a morphism in C y(C), by definition f ,g can seen as objects in the slice category C/C since f ∈ HomC(X,C) and g ∈ HomC(Y,C); also u : f → g is a morphism of C/C because u(g) = f .

λ R P (C)/F has a terminal object and therefore C F need be a ω-filtred category. Additionaly,

R O y F = colim( C F / C / P(C)) where O is a , O(C,x) = C.

1.2 Local Cartesian Closed Categories A category X is called local cartesian closed when the pullback functor f ∗ has a right adjoint for each morphims f . In case X be a presentable category the notion of l.c.c. is equivalent to the following definition. This follows from adjoint functor theorem.

Definition 2. Let X be a presentable ∞-category. We will say the colimits in C are universal if ∗ for any morphism f : X → Y in X the associated pullback functor f : X/Y → X/X preserves colimits.

3 To prove the colimits in an ∞-topos are universal we need the following lemma. Lemma 2. Let X be a presentable ∞-category and L : X → Y be an accessible left exact local- ization. If colimits in X are universal, the colimits in Y are universal. Therefore everything lies, just like the classical case, in proving that P(C) has the property. Proposition 3. Let C be an ∞-category. The colimits in P(C) are universal. Proof. We need to use the following facts: 1. The colimits in S are universal. 2. The colimits in P(C) are calculated "pointwise".

So let τ : F → G a morphism in P(C) and a colimit colimWi in P(C)/G, we can calculate the following pullback. colimWi ×G F / colimWi τ∗( f ) f   F τ / G ∗ ∼ To say that the functor τ preserves colimits means that (colimWi)×G F = colim(Wi ×G F), but this holds iff for each vertex c of C the following equation holds ∼ (colimWi(c)) ×G(c) F(c) = colim(Wi(c) ×G(c) F(c)) Its holds because this equation lives in S and this category has the property, so the colimits are universal in P(C). Proposition 4. Let X be an ∞-topos. The colimits in X are universal. Proof. Applying Lemma 2 and proposition 3. Other way to see universal colimits is the following: Let two diagrams in X with α a cartesian between them: p K α X q

Suppose both diagrams extend to

p KB α X q

Then the colimits are universal can be reformulated as: If α is cartesian and q is a colimit dia- gram, then also p is a colimit diagram.

To prove this formulation, let α : p → q be a cartesian transformacion and let q a colimit cone in X, exist a correspondence between the colimits of X and colimits in slices categories of X, this means q can see as a colimit cone in X/y with x := p(∞) and y := q(∞), where ∞ is the terminal . object of K and f := α∞.

∗ ∗ ∗ We can construct the pullback functor f : X/y → X/x so p = f q. Using the fact f preserves colimits and since q is a colimit diagram then p is a colimit diagram.

4 1.3 Descent Argument Definition 3. Let X be an ∞-category is said to satisfy descent if let p,q two diagrams in X with α a cartesian natural transformation between them: p K α X q

Suppose both diagrams extend to

p KB α X q

If p and q are colimit diagrams, then α is a cartesian transformation. The category of spaces S satisfies descent, the proof of this requires model-category arguments and can find as part of the proof of Lemma 6.1.3.14 in [2]. Proposition 5. Let P(C) be a presheaf ∞-category. Then for every pushout diagram.

α f / g

β β 0   f 0 / g0 α0

1 0 0 in OP(C) = Fun(∆ ,P(C)). If α and β are cartesian transformations, then α and β are also cartesian. The previous pushout diagram in OP(C) can be seen in P(C) has the following cube.

F f F α g G G β β 0 F0 F0 f 0 α0 g0 G0 G0

Proof. We need use the following facts: • The proposition is true in S. • The colimits and cartesian transformation are calcluted ”pointwise". So α0 and β 0 are cartesian transformations iff α0(c) and β 0(c) are cartesian, where c is a vertex of C. Evaluating c in each functor of the previous cube the following pullback diagram can be built in OS αc fc / gc

0 βc βc  0 0 fc 0 / gc αc

5 0 0 Since αc and βc are cartesian squares and the property holds in S then αc and βc are a cartesian transformations, so this happens for each vertex of C. Therefore α0 and β 0 are cartesian transformations.

Additionally, the property it is preserved for left exact localizations. Proposition 6. Let X be an ∞-topos. Then for every pushout diagram

α f / g

β β 0   f 0 / g0 α0

1 0 0 in OX = Fun(∆ ,X), if α and β are cartesian transformations, then α and β are also carte- sian.

o Proof. Let L : P(C) / X : R be a left exact localization and the following diagram in X:

α f / g

β  f 0

Applying the functor R and consider the fact that P(C) is cocomplete, then the following is a pushout diagram in P(C). Rα R f / Rg

0 Rβ β   R f 0 / g0 α0 0 Since R is left exact, Rα and Rβ are cartesian transformations. Since α0 and β are cartesian transformations in P(C) (Proposition 5), applying L to the pushout diagram and the left exact 0 condition of L, the following diagram is a pushout in X and Lα0 and Lβ are cartesian transfor- mations. LRα LR f / LRg

0 LRβ Lβ   LR f 0 / Lg0 Lα0 But the left exact conditions of L allows us to rewrite the diagram as:

α f / g

β β 0   f 0 / g0 α0 where α0 and β 0 are cartesian transformations. Example 2. Descent argument is satisfies by S on the contrary of the , for example take the functions f ,g : {4} → {2} and form the cube diagram in Sets, it’s easy check α0 is not a cartesian transformation

6 4 2 f g α • 2 1 • • • g • • • • 2 4 2 2 1 f g α0 1 1

Note that α is a pullback but α0 doesn’t because the pullback of the diagram 1 → 1 ← 1 is 1 ← 1 → 1.

The lemma 3 can be see as a equivalent notion of the proposition 5 if the colimits are universal, the proof need a few of equivalent terminology, we only use the result and the proof can be find as part of the theorem 6.1.3.9 in [2].

Lemma 3. Let X be an presentable ∞-category where the colimits are universal and satisfies the descent argument. Let K be a small simplicial set and α : p → q a natural transformation of . diagrams p,q : K → X. Suppose that q is a colimit diagram, and that α = α|K is a cartesian transformation. Then p is a colimit diagram iff α is a cartesian transformation.

p p

K α X KB α X q q

Example 3. Let X be an presentable ∞-category where the colimits are universal and satifying general descent argument. Let K be the following diagram shape • ← • → •, p,q : K → X two diagrams and α : p → q a natural transformation.

p

V 0 V01 V1 U01 U1 α

U 0 U01 U1 U0 U q

We would like construct an object V over U by gluing it together from a local date. This means, we can calculate the colimit diagram of p and this fits correctly (be Cartesian) with the natural transformation that is created thanks to the of pushouts. The following diagram ilustre that.

V01 V1

U1 V0 V w

U0 U

So we can see the above diagram as following:

7 p

V0 V V1

w α

U0 U U1 q

1.4 Disjoint coproducts condition The third Giraud’s axiom is the following. Definition 4. Let X be an ∞-category with coproducts and initial object. The coproducts in X are disjoint, if the following diagram is a pullback in X:

/0 / Y

  X / X qY To prove the coproducts are disjoint in an ∞-topos, we need the following results. Lemma 4. Let X be a presentable category in which the colimits are universal and f : X → /0 be a morphism, where /0 is an initial object of X. Then X is also initial. The previous lemma tell us that for an accessible infinity category the initial object is strict.

The following cube can be define in an ∞-topos. /0 Y id /0 α idY /0 Y idY β 0 β g f /0 Y f 0 g α ` X X Y

Where α is cartesian because /0is initial, also β is cartesian thanks to the Lemma 4. Proposition 7. Let X be an ∞-topos. The coproducts in X are disjoint. Proof. (Option 1) Let α0 be the following pushout diagram in X.

/0 / Y

  X / X qY

0 The following diagram is constructed from α in OX.

α id/0 / idY

β β 0   f / g α0

8 We know α and β are cartesian and applying proposition 6, we have α0 is cartesian.

(Option 2) We need use the following facts: 1. The property holds in S. 2. The coproducts are disjoint in P(C) because the following diagram is a pullback diagram.

/0 / G

  F / X qY iff for each vertex c of C the following diagram is a pullback in S.

/0 / G(c)

  F(c) / F(c)qG(c)

but the previous diagram is a pullback because the property holds in S. Therefore the coproducts are disjoint in P(C). So let X,Y objects of X, applying the right adjoint R of the left exact localization L : P(C) → X, and construct the of RX,RY then we have the following pushout diagram.

/0 / RY

  RX / RX qRY So applying the functor L and the conditions of left exacts, we have the following pushout in X.

L/0 / LRY

  LRX / L(RX qLRY) but the above diagram for the properties of L can be rewritten as:

/0 / Y

  X / X qY

2 Groupoid objects

The fourth Giraud’s axiom in the classical case told us, every R is effective, we can see this property as the following diagram

d0 R X q d1

X q X/R

9 The above diagram can seen as the following simplicial diagram

d q 1 X/R X s0 R d0

By effective condition of R we can garantizate that the previous diagram has all data that we need because after R all the morphims are determined by some composition of morphisms in the above diagram. Additionaly, reflective and transitive property tell us R can seen as category and symmetric condition allows to prove the morphisms are invertible. Therefore R is a groupoid.

Since the equivalence relations can seen as groupoids, then the following definitions come nat- urally to construct the fourth ∞-Giraud’s axiom. Definition 5. A simplicial object of an ∞-category C is a map of ∞-categories.

op U• : N(∆) → C We need the simplicial objects that meet a good gluing properties. This motivates the following definition.

Definition 6. Let C be an ∞-category and U• a simplicial object of C. We will say that U• is a groupoid object if for every n ≥ 0 and every partition n = S ∪ S0 such that S ∩ S0 consists of a single element s, the following diagram is a pullback in C.

U([n]) / U(S0)

  U(S) / U({s})

Let ∆+ be the category of finite (possible empty) linearly ordered sets, we can extend the notion of groupoid object for this category. Definition 7. An augmented simplicial object of C is a map.

+ op U• : N(∆+) → C For the case of an augmented simplicial object the notion of good gluing properties motivates ≤n the following definiton, where ∆+ denote the full subcategory of ∆+ spanned by the objects {[k]}−1≤k≤n. + Proposition 8. Let C be an ∞-category and let U• be an augmented simplicial object. We will + ˇ 2 say U• is a Cech if it satisfies the equivalent conditions: + 1. The underlying simplicial object of U• is a groupoid object of C and the following dia- + gram U• | ≤1 is a pullback square in C. N(∆+ )

U1 / U0

  U0 / U−1 2In case C is a category with pullbacks and given a morphism f : U → X in C, the Cechˇ Nerve of f is the simplicial object

C(X) =( U ×X U ×X U U ×X U U X )

10 + + 2.U • is a right Kan extension of U• | ≤0 . N(∆+ ) Now we have the elements to define a groupoid object with good gluing properties.

Definition 8. Let U• be a simplicial object of an ∞-category C. We will say that U• is an effective + + ˇ groupoid if can be extended to a colimit diagram U• such that U• is a Cech Nerve.

U• N(∆)op / C ;

+ U•  op N(∆+)

2.1 Dec> Construction To prove the groupoid objects in an ∞-topos are effective we need two special tools, the first one is the Dec> construcction of a simplicial object. Let X be a simplicial set (or a simplicial object in an ∞-category, it does matter because the construcction holds in any case), we can define a new simplicial set removing the top face map d> in all the simplicial diagram of X.

X0 X1 X2 X

d1 d2 d3

d d1 2 X1 X2 X3 Dec>X d 0 d0

Additionally, we can see X0 has a colimit of Dec>X.

d d1 2 X X X2 X 0 d0 1 3 d 0 d0

The last stament holds, if we see the above diagram as the following split augmented diagram

s1 s2 s0 X X X2 X 0 d0 1 3 and using the following lemma.

Lemma 5. Every split augmented diagram of a simplicial set is a colimit diagram

To prove lemma we need some technical arguments, but those generalize the following con- struction. A fork in X is a diagram of the form

f q A B C g such that, q◦ f = q◦g. A split fork is a fork such that exist t : B → A and s : C → B that satisfying q ◦ s = idC, f ◦ = idB and s ◦ q = g ◦t.

11 t s

f A B q C g

Lemma 6. A split fork is a coeaqualizer.

Proof. There exist W and w : B → W that w ◦ f = w ◦ g.

t s

f A B q C g w W

We can define a morphism w ◦ s from C and W such that satisfies the following.

w ◦ (s ◦ q) = w ◦ (g ◦t) = (w ◦ g) ◦t = (w ◦ f ) ◦t = w ◦ ( f ◦t)

= w ◦ idB

Therefore q is the of f ,g. To prove the first part of lemma 7 is necessary used the split augmented argument uses in the proof of split fork are coequalizer and can be find in [2] as Lemma 6.1.3.16 and the second part is deduced from the analogous of the prisma lemma3 for pushout.

op Lemma 7. Let X be an ∞-category and let U• : N(∆) → X be a simplicial object of X. Let Dec>U• be the augmented simplicial object given by composing U• with the functor F. Then:

1. The augmented simplicial object Dec>U• is a colimit diagram.

2. If U• is a groupoid object of X, then α : (Dec>U•)|N(∆)op → U• is cartesian. The groupoid objects over a category, where the colimits are universal and satisfies descent argument, are effective.

Theorem 2. Let X be an ∞-category such that:

1. The colimits in X are universal. 3The prisma lemma tells if β is a pullback. Then α is a pullback diagram iff all the diagram is a pullback.

• • •

α β

• • •

12 2. For every pushout diagram: α f / g

β β 0   f 0 / g0 α0 0 0 in OX, if α and β are cartesian transformations then α and β are also cartesian trans- formations.

Then the groupoid objects of X are effective.

op Proof. Let U• be a groupoid object of X and let U• : N(∆+) → X be a colimit cocone` of U•. op Let Dec>U• : N(∆+) → X be the composition of U• with F : ∆+ → ∆+, F(J) = J {∞}; for the construction of F, we have Dec>Un = Un+1.

And applying lemma 7, Dec>U• is a colimit diagram in X. Additionally for the second impli- cation of the lemma 7, α = α|N(∆)op is cartesian.

U•

U•

U−1 q U0 U1 U2

q d1 d2 d3 α

U0 U1 U2 U3

Dec>U•

Applying the lemma 3, α : Dec>U• → U• is a cartesian transformation because Dec>U• is a colimit diagram. Additionally, we can construct the following pullback diagram in X.

Dec>U0 / Dec>U−1

  U0 / U−1

This pullback can be rewritten using Dec>Un = Un+1 and U•|N(∆)op = U•

U1 / U0

  U0 / U−1

Then U• is an effective groupoid. Corollary 1. Let X be an ∞-topos. Then the groupoid objects in X are effective.

13 3 Giraud’s theorem

The previous section told us that if the ∞-category is an ∞-topos then satisfies the Giraud’s axioms. To prove the converse, we need the following result.

Proposition 9. Let C be a small ∞-category wich admits finite limits and let X be an ∞-category wich satisfies the Giraud’s axioms. Let F : P(C) → X be a colimit preserving functor. Supposse that the composition F ◦ j : C → X is left exact, where j is the Yoneda embedding. Then F is left exact.

Let Indλ C be the subcategory of P(C) formed by those presheaves that classify right fibrations of λ-filtered categories. Simpson’s theorem allow us to see Indλ C as a localization of P(C), in fact, its a left exact localization applying the proposition 9.

Proposition 10. Let X be an ∞-category. Suppose that X satisfies the ∞-categorical Giraud’s axioms then there exists a small ∞-category C that admits finite limits and an accessible left exact localization functor L : P(C) → X. In particular X is an ∞-topos. Proof. The category X is accessible so this is equivalent (Simpson’s theorem) to the exis- tence of a small category C an ∞-category which admits λ-small colimits, and an equivalence Indλ C ≡ X.

So the candidate to construct the left exat localization is the category P(C). We have i : Indλ C ,→ P(C) has a left adjoint L : P(C) → Indλ C. The composition of L with the Yoneda embedding 0 j : C → P(C) can be seen as the Yoneda embedding j : C → Indλ C and therefore preserves all limits that exists in C.

Applying proposition 9, we have that L is left exact, so Indλ C is a left exact localization and therefore X it is also.

References

[1] C. Rezk, and toposes.

[2] J. Lurie, Higher Topos Theory, Annals of Mathematics Studies 170, Princeton University Press, Princeton and Oxford, 2009.

[3] S. Mac Lane, I. Moerdijk, Sheaves in and Logic, A first introduction to topos theory, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1992.

14