Friendship & Politics
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
000 FM-intro (i-viii, 1-18) 3/20/08 12:46 PM Page iii Friendship & Politics Essays in Political Thought Edited by John von Heyking and Richard Avramenko University of Notre Dame Press Notre Dame, Indiana © 2008 University of Notre Dame Press 000 FM-intro (i-viii, 1-18) 3/20/08 12:46 PM Page iv Copyright © 2008 by University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana 46556 www.undpress.nd.edu All Rights Reserved Manufactured in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Friendship and politics : essays in political thought / edited by John von Heyking and Richard Avramenko. p. cm. Includes index. ISBN-13: 978-0-268-04370-4 (pbk. : alk. paper) ISBN-10: 0-268-04370-1 (pbk. : alk. paper) 1. Political science-Philosophy. 2. Friendship-Political aspects. I. Heyking, John von. II. Avramenko, Richard. JA71.F65 2008 320.01-dc22 2008010164 This book is printed on recycled paper. © 2008 University of Notre Dame Press 000 FM-intro (i-viii, 1-18) 3/20/08 12:46 PM Page 1 Introduction The Persistence of Friendship in Political Life John von Heyking and Richard Avramenko Throughout the greater part of the history of political philosophy, friendship has occupied a central place in the conversation. If we draw on conventional historical distinctions, friendship perennially figured as the sine qua non of discussions among ancient and medieval political thinkers regarding good political order and the good human life. As Horst Hutter explains, up to the end of the Middle Ages the idea of friendship was at the core of political thinking: “Western political specu - lation finds its origin in a system of thought in which the idea of friend- ship is the major principle in terms of which political theory and practice are described, explained, and analyzed.”1 It is only in the modern era that friendship has lost its prominence and been relegated to the backbenches of political philosophy. It simply has not been a central concern for political thinkers within the liberal tradition, or any other, in the past five hundred years or so. 1 © 2008 University of Notre Dame Press 000 FM-intro (i-viii, 1-18) 3/20/08 12:46 PM Page 2 2 T John von Heyking and Richard Avramenko This demotion has not gone unnoticed. Hans-Georg Gadamer, for in- stance, remarks that while justice needs only one book, friendship “fills two books in Aristotle’s Ethics [but] occupies no more than a page in Kant.”2 Where friendship is actually afforded some attention in the tradi- tion, liberal thinkers are, at best, lukewarm toward it. John Rawls, for ex- ample—contemporary liberalism’s most famous expositor—regards it as a “nonmoral value,” but at the same time he nonetheless recognizes that it helps to sustain justice.3 There is, then, a shift in the history of political thought and in the practice of politics at the end of the Middle Ages. At the dawn of the modern state, the beginning of the scientific revolution, the outset of the spread of universal principles of rights and freedoms, and the advent of international truck and trade, friendship as a political concern nearly drops out of sight. However, as this book’s essays on modern and contemporary political thinkers show, friendship does not drop completely out of sight. One notable example of a liberal for whom friendship was important yet ambiguous was Thomas Jefferson, who in- dicated in his First Inaugural that friendship may even be more impor- tant than liberty: “Let us restore to social intercourse that harmony and affection without which liberty and even life itself are but dreary things”4 Yet, nearly out of sight has friendship dropped today. So whither friendship? Commentators often observe that the modern era, and liberal democracies in particular, are so committed to liberty and autonomy—that the individual is emphasized to such a degree—that he perforce becomes isolated from other human beings. This is true as well for liberalism’s critics including nationalists, socialists, and romantics who prize “the nation,” “the people,” the universal proletariat, and “the state” as an abstract entity that subsumes individuals and his intermedi- ate relations, which is the predominant scope of his actions. So whereas liberalism and its offspring liberal democracy promise the individual lib- erty, the cost of this liberty is often isolation. Loneliness, or as Joshua Mitchell refers to it, “brooding withdrawal,” therefore becomes one of the central experiences people have as liberal democratic citizens. This phenomenon is often recognized and painfully experienced by immi- grants and visitors from outside North America and Europe, especially Muslims.5 Homegrown accounts of life in liberal democracies also bear this out; one need only think of Robert Putnam’s Bowling Alone and David Riesman’s Lonely Crowd as testaments. © 2008 University of Notre Dame Press 000 FM-intro (i-viii, 1-18) 3/20/08 12:46 PM Page 3 Introduction T 3 But not only have the bonds of friendship been eviscerated, the bonds between individuals generally have taken on a completely different hue. We commonly characterize the individual’s relationship with others in terms of the contract. In fact, the liberal principle that society is grounded in a contract reaches into other areas of life to the point that we regard all our relationships in similar terms. We come to our private rela- tionships, our loves and friendships, with the same desire to get a good bargain as we do when we purchase a car or a computer. We network, we schmooze, and we realize the “autonomous self,” the ideal to which much of contemporary liberalism seeks. The autonomous self, however, while proudly asserting her independence, is forced to seek respite from her existential solitude in the companionship offered by her dog, the chitchat found on the internet, and the respite found in her lithium.6 If we seek less utilitarian, deeper, or more “authentic” relations, we almost naturally turn to romance, on the assumption that erotic attach- ments and bodily intimacy are the most profound expressions of con- necting to another. Even if this is true, and there are good reasons to think there exist more profound expressions of love, romance fails to help us connect to the wider community, with those with whom we will not enter into romantic relationships. What we are left with is ro- mance in private and contract in public, with the proviso that the con- tract will dominate one’s private life once the heat of romance runs out of fuel. Romance fails to resolve the problem of how we can integrate our personalities into our political community. Moreover, romance does not apply to so-called Platonic relations, as evidenced by the con- fusion heterosexual males have regarding their relationships with other males. Beyond engaging in sports and women, modern society sheds little light on how they can share each other’s company. Intimate con- versation—which many thinkers in the Western tradition regard as the hallmark of friendship—is rejected as unmanly or “gay.” This, com- bined with the widespread tolerance of homosexuality, does nothing to alleviate that sense of not knowing what to do with one’s friend or, for that matter, how to be a friend. We seem unable to understand friend- ship and the act of sharing in terms that are neither romantic nor sexual.7 We seem unable to be at leisure in the Aristotelian sense of ac- tivity, and, as he observes in the case of the Spartans, a people incapable of leisure becomes an imperial one.8 © 2008 University of Notre Dame Press 000 FM-intro (i-viii, 1-18) 3/20/08 12:46 PM Page 4 4 T John von Heyking and Richard Avramenko The confusion over friendship in the private realm is mirrored in the public when we seek relationships deeper, or more “authentic,” than those marked by mere economic contract. Oft times when in search of this, compassion (and sympathy and pity) becomes the most likely mode of connecting and the surrogate for friendship. There is extensive suffer- ing in our society and in the world at large, and we can identify with the plight of others because we share a common humanity with them. But compassion and its related emotions are unreliable precisely because they are emotions. Our compassion might lead us to help others, but it might simply make us feel good about ourselves, allowing us to indulge our- selves for feeling compassionate. We feel anger at the person, group, or party causing the suffering, but do we merely flatter ourselves for feeling indignation without seeking to alleviate suffering? Compassion as an emotion still depends on our ability to judge rightly about the justice of the case. This inclination toward self-indulgence, of viewing others and ourselves as tragic figures in the theater, is a constant danger in large soci- eties where face-to-face encounters with fellow citizens are limited and replaced by media images meant to promote social cohesion as much as they purport to inform. With Aristotle, one may wonder whether our daily activity of guessing at the character and circumstance of our fellow citizens is in fact a daily act of injustice.9 Furthermore, to whom do we owe compassion? Who is our neighbor, as Christians ask? Should we prefer our fellow citizen to someone suffer- ing (perhaps more severely) in a distant land? Why should a national border make a difference for a moral problem so serious? But if we prac- tice “telescopic philanthropy,” as Charles Dickens calls it in Bleak House, do we not neglect our own community and ultimately ourselves? What moral status does “our own” have anyway? As Alexis de Toc- queville found, liberal democrats find a distant solidarity with universal humanity because they lack an informed sense of “their own.” The iden- tity of “our own” shifts daily as alliances, affections, and friendships come and go.