I “BECAUSE WE ARE ALONE…” ARGUMENTS for HUMANS AS the UNIVERSE’S ONLY INTELLIGENT LIFE FORM from ANCIENT PHILOSOPHERS to TODAY’S SCIENTISTS

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

I “BECAUSE WE ARE ALONE…” ARGUMENTS for HUMANS AS the UNIVERSE’S ONLY INTELLIGENT LIFE FORM from ANCIENT PHILOSOPHERS to TODAY’S SCIENTISTS “BECAUSE WE ARE ALONE…” ARGUMENTS FOR HUMANS AS THE UNIVERSE’S ONLY INTELLIGENT LIFE FORM FROM ANCIENT PHILOSOPHERS TO TODAY’S SCIENTISTS by Joseph Clayton Packer B.A., University of Mary Washington, 2005 M.A., Wake Forest University, 2007 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Kenneth P. Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2012i UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH KENNETH P. DIETRICH SCHOOL OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by Joseph Clayton Packer It was defended on October 31, 2011 and approved by Philip E. Smith, Associate Professor, Department of English Barbara Warnick, Professor, Department of Communication Brent Malin, Assistant Professor, Department of Communication Dissertation Advisor: Ronald J. Zboray, Professor, Department of Communication ii Copyright © by Joseph Clayton Packer 2012 iii “BECAUSE WE ARE ALONE…” ARGUMENTS FOR HUMANS AS THE UNIVERSE’S ONLY INTELLIGENT LIFE FORM FROM ANCIENT PHILOSOPHERS TO TODAY’S SCIENTISTS Joseph Clayton Packer, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2012 Does alien life exist? This perennial question has driven some of humanity’s oldest scientific debates, going back to the ancient Greeks. My work investigates the way individuals have rhetorically deployed speculations about the impossibility of extraterrestrial life to advance other values and beliefs. Specifically, my research traces the unity-of-the-world cosmology or “unity,” for short, meaning the belief that humans are the only intelligent life form in the universe, in contrast to the “plurality-of worlds” one, or “plurality,” which holds open the possibility of multiple intelligent life forms. The unity rhetorical cosmology connects the absence of alien life with the idea of human value and transcendental, absolute ethics. Because “we” are alone, “we” are special, the thinking goes. My dissertation traces the way cosmology serves as an argument in religious, political, and philosophical debates. Specifically, it examines the way that individuals have used claims of the absence of alien life to justify moral absolutism, teleology, and anthropocentrism, from Plato to the present day. The dissertation examines major historical figures as case studies including: Plato, Aquinas, William Whewell, and Alfred Russel Wallace. I draw on Kenneth Burke, Roland Barthes, and rhetoric-of-science- iv literature (as well as many other sources) in order to unveil the hidden rhetorical meaning of a cosmology. v TABLE OF CONTENTS TABLE OF CONTENTS ............................................................................................... VI PREFACE ........................................................................................................................ IX 1.0 INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................... 1 1.1 LIMITATIONS ................................................................................................ 7 1.2 METHODOLOGY AND CHAPTER OUTLINE ...................................... 10 1.3 LITERATURE REVIEW ............................................................................. 17 1.4 CONCLUSION .............................................................................................. 30 2.0 PLATO’S RHETORICAL COSMOLOGY: THE UNITY OF THE WORLD AS FOUNDATIONAL MYTH ...................................................................................... 33 2.1 STATE OF COSMOLOGY AND PLATO’S EARLY DIALOGUES ...... 39 2.2 MYTH AND RHETORIC IN PLATO’S DIALOGUES ........................... 46 2.3 SCIENCE, MATHEMATICS, AND EMPIRICAL ARGUMENT IN PLATO’S DIALOGUES ........................................................................................ 55 2.4 PLATO’S RECONCILIATION WITH COSMOLOGY .......................... 56 2.5 PLATO’S COSMOLOGY: MYTH OR SCIENCE? ................................. 68 2.6 PLATO’S RHETORICAL COSMOLOGY ................................................ 74 2.7 CONCLUSION .............................................................................................. 80 vi 3.0 THE DOMINANCE OF THE UNITY COSMOLOGY: UNITY FROM PLATO TO GALILEO .................................................................................................. 82 3.1 ARISTOTLE .................................................................................................. 85 3.2 EARLY CHRISTIANITY AND COSMOLOGY ....................................... 88 3.3 AQUINAS ....................................................................................................... 93 3.4 AQUINAS’ LEGACY ................................................................................. 102 3.5 THE COPERNICAN SYSTEM ................................................................. 107 3.6 GALILEO AND HIS TELESCOPE .......................................................... 112 3.7 THE SHIFT TO PLURALISM .................................................................. 118 3.8 CONCLUSION ............................................................................................ 126 4.0 WILLIAM WHEWELL AND ALFRED RUSSEL WALLACE: UNITY COSMOLOGY IN THE MODERN ERA .................................................................. 128 4.1 WILLIAM WHEWELL ............................................................................. 132 4.2 THE VESTIGES OF CREATION ............................................................. 143 4.3 PLURALITY OF WORLDS AND THE UTILITY DEBATE ................ 150 4.4 PLURALITY OF WORLDS: TIMAEUS .................................................. 156 4.5 THE RESPONSE ......................................................................................... 166 4.6 A. R. WALLACE: BRIDGE TO THE 20TH CENTURY ......................... 172 4.7 SOCIAL DARWINISM .............................................................................. 175 4.8 WALLACE’S SCIENTIFIC EVOLUTION ............................................. 180 4.9 PUBLIC BATTLE ....................................................................................... 189 4.10 CONCLUSION .......................................................................................... 192 5.0 TIPLER AND BARROW .................................................................................... 194 vii 5.1 THE STATE OF THE DEBATE ............................................................... 197 5.2 TIPLER’S RHETORICAL ANALYSIS ................................................... 201 5.3 THE ANTHROPIC PRINCIPLE .............................................................. 206 5.4 THE SCIENTIFIC FRAME ....................................................................... 210 5.5 THE UNITY RHETORIC .......................................................................... 214 5.6 ABSENT ALIENS ....................................................................................... 222 5.7 RECEPTION ............................................................................................... 226 5.8 EXPLAINING THE SUCCESS ................................................................. 232 5.9 PUBLIC RECEPTION ............................................................................... 236 5.10 TIPLER’S LATER WORK ...................................................................... 242 5.11 CONCLUSION .......................................................................................... 248 6.0 CONCLUSION: MAN AS THE MEASURE VS. THE UNITY OF THE WORLD ......................................................................................................................... 250 6.1 THE RHETORICAL PROBLEM OF UNITY ......................................... 252 6.2 THE DANGERS OF UNITY ...................................................................... 253 6.3 CONCLUSION ............................................................................................ 255 BIBLIOGRAPHY ......................................................................................................... 256 viii PREFACE I have many individuals to thank for helping me bring this project to fruition. I am thankful to have come in to the Communication Department at the University of Pittsburgh with such an amazing cohort: Tom Dunn, David Landes, Brita Anderson, Josh Beaty, Candi Carter Olson, John Jasso, and Heather Liebling. The nickname “demon cohort” seems to best encapuslate the experience. Along with my cohort, the graduate student community helped create an amazing atmosphere. During my time as a Pitt I attended a mock funeral, held a poetry reading outside the Cathedral, paraded around a cardboard cutout of Josh Beaty, and went sky diving. On occasion we grad student even got some work done and I would like to thank Brita Anderson, John Rief, and Michael Vicaro for editing parts of the dissertation for me. I began my dissertation project at Wake Forest and I would like to thank Ananda Mitra, Allan Louden, Mary Dalton, and Michael Hyde for beginning me on the project that ultimately took the form of this dissertation. At the University of Pittsburgh I owe a debt to many scholars outside of my committee, who I would like to thank. John Poulakos helped brainstorm with me about my chapter on classical Greece. John Lyne offered sage advice on my use of rhetoric of science literature. Paul Scade (despite being out of the country and working at a different university) read several drafts of my chapter on Plato and offered a crucial philosophical ix perspective. Finally, I owe a great debt of
Recommended publications
  • The Logic of Desire
    Alexis Turner Indiana University 03.28.2013 Presented at the annual conference for the Western Political Science Association Draft. Please do not cite or distribute without permission The Logic of Desire In ancient Greek thought, which had not yet formally theorized a mathematical concept of zero, the idea of nothing or lack nonetheless held a prominent place, perhaps most fully articulated through eros: desire. Or, as we more gently tend to translate it in English, love. This is an unfortunate softening, for the Greeks understood all too well that to play with love is to play with fire. Such pyrotechnics do not require the abandonment of reason, contrary to most common readings – just as we can admire jaguars, canyons, Siren songs, and other beautiful things without being witless enough to throw ourselves headlong into them, so we can flirt with desire without being consumed. This paper explores the possibility that refusing nothing – refusing to live with desire – is the fundamental error that sits at the heart of The Republic. If I am not entirely mistaken, the Socratic notion of desire is a deeply logical one deployed as a response to, and critical of, question-begging elements inherent in positive declarations derived from a reasoning process based wholly essentialist either/or oppositions. If so, the problem shifts from one of authoritative, unidirectional truth to one of diplomacy, tactics, and strategy. Truth has not disappeared, but it becomes enmeshed in relations between people and depends on the exercise of judgment, restraint, and friendship. Starting with nothing brings us back to politics. Is the modern world really so disenchanted as we are continually being told? The claim resonates, and yet trends in modern photography indicate that things are practically fetishized, each object lovingly isolated and focused on in macro-miniature, each of its colors and curves fondled by the camera.
    [Show full text]
  • A Contextual Examination of Three Historical Stages of Atheism and the Legality of an American Freedom from Religion
    ABSTRACT Rejecting the Definitive: A Contextual Examination of Three Historical Stages of Atheism and the Legality of an American Freedom from Religion Ethan Gjerset Quillen, B.A., M.A., M.A. Mentor: T. Michael Parrish, Ph.D. The trouble with “definitions” is they leave no room for evolution. When a word is concretely defined, it is done so in a particular time and place. Contextual interpretations permit a better understanding of certain heavy words; Atheism as a prime example. In the post-modern world Atheism has become more accepted and popular, especially as a reaction to global terrorism. However, the current definition of Atheism is terribly inaccurate. It cannot be stated properly that pagan Atheism is the same as New Atheism. By interpreting the Atheisms from four stages in the term‟s history a clearer picture of its meaning will come out, hopefully alleviating the stereotypical biases weighed upon it. In the interpretation of the Atheisms from Pagan Antiquity, the Enlightenment, the New Atheist Movement, and the American Judicial and Civil Religious system, a defense of the theory of elastic contextual interpretations, rather than concrete definitions, shall be made. Rejecting the Definitive: A Contextual Examination of Three Historical Stages of Atheism and the Legality of an American Freedom from Religion by Ethan Gjerset Quillen, B.A., M.A. A Thesis Approved by the J.M. Dawson Institute of Church-State Studies ___________________________________ Robyn L. Driskell, Ph.D., Interim Chairperson Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Baylor University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts Approved by the Thesis Committee ___________________________________ T.
    [Show full text]
  • “We Wanted a Parliament but They Gave Us a Stone” the Coronation Stone of the Scots As a Memory Box in the Twentieth Century
    “We wanted a parliament but they gave us a stone” The Coronation Stone of the Scots as a Memory Box in the Twentieth Century JÖRG ROGGE In this article a memory box is presented, in which and to which different meanings were contained and attached in the course of seven centuries.1 This memory box is the coronation stone of Scottish kings, nowadays on display in Edinburgh Castle, the external form of which has remained for the most part unchanged. The roughly 150 kg heavy, 67 cm long, 42 cm wide and 28 cm high sandstone block was used in the Middle Ages at the inauguration of Scottish kings.2 In the course of history, however, it was removed from its original functional context and transferred to other cultural and political contexts. In this connection, both diachronic and also synchronic transfers of the coronation stone and the concepts of political order in the island of Britain stored in it were carried out. At present it is still an important memory box filled with political concepts, and it was and is a starting point for research into the relationship between the Scots and the English over the past 700 years. It is remarkable that this stone was used by nationally emotional Scots and also by the Government in London as symbol in important debates in the twentieth century. Historical recollections are transported by the Scots and the English with the stone that one may certainly call a container of memory. Here I 1 My thanks go to John Deasy for translating the German text into English as well as to the editors for finishing the final formatting.
    [Show full text]
  • Calcidius's Commentary on Plato's Timaeus in Latin Astronomy of the Ninth to Eleventh Centuries
    BRUCE S. EASTWOOD CALCIDIUS'S COMMENTARY ON PLATO'S TIMAEUS IN LATIN ASTRONOMY OF THE NINTH TO ELEVENTH CENTURIES Prior to the twelfth-century recovery of Greek and discovery of Arabic astronomical (and astrological) texts, the character of European astronomy derived from three traditions: computus, classical texts, and observation (including instruments). By the ninth century each of these was involved with the others, producing an increasing variety of ideas and investigations. While the computistical and observational traditions combined in certain ways to bring about more practical and mathematical understanding of solar, lunar, and occasionally stellar motions, generally in the context of reckoning time intervals, the classical tradition led scholars to expand their frameworks for understanding the order and regularity of the heavens created by God.1 More speculative or theoretical and quite unmathematical in nature, the classical Latin materials that offered astronomical information and doctrines tested the wits of early medieval investigators in quite different ways than did the problems of the other traditions. Among these Roman astronomical works—the writings of Aratus (in translation), Pliny the Elder, Calcidius, Macrobius, and Martianus Capella were predominant—the translation of and commentary upon Plato's Timaeus by Calcidius has received the least attention by modern students of early medieval astronomy. Yet the work of Calcidius, especially his commentary, offers us a revealing field for the display of bold exploration, limits of comprehension, and successful innovation in medieval astronomical study more than half a century before the influx of Greco-Arabic works from ca. 1100 onward. Here I present examples of the boldness, the limits, and the successes from three manuscripts of Calcidius from the ninth to early eleventh centuries.
    [Show full text]
  • Planet Formation
    3. Planet form ation Frontiers of A stronom y W orkshop/S chool Bibliotheca A lexandrina M arch-A pril 2006 Properties of planetary system s • all giant planets in the solar system have a > 5 A U w hile extrasolar giant planets have semi-major axes as small as a = 0.02 A U • planetary orbital angular momentum is close to direction of S un’s spin angular momentum (w ithin 7o) • 3 of 4 terrestrial planets and 3 of 4 giant planets have obliquities (angle betw een spin and orbital angular momentum) < 30o • interplanetary space is virtually empty, except for the asteroid belt and the Kuiper belt • planets account for < 0.2% of mass of solar system but > 98% of angular momentum Properties of planetary system s • orbits of major planets in solar system are nearly circular (eMercury=0.206, ePluto=0.250); orbits of extrasolar planets are not (emedian=0.28) • probability of finding a planet is proportional to mass of metals in the star Properties of planetary system s • planets suffer no close encounters and are spaced fairly n regularly (Bode’s law : an=0.4 + 0.3×2 ) planet semimajor axis (A U ) n an (A U ) Mercury 0.39 −∞ 0.4 V enus 0.72 0 0.7 Earth 1.00 1 1.0 Mars 1.52 2 1.6 asteroids 2.77 (Ceres) 3 2.8 Jupiter 5.20 4 5.2 S aturn 9.56 5 10.0 U ranus 19.29 6 19.6 N eptune 30.27 7 38.8 Pluto 39.68 8 77.2 Properties of planetary system s • planets suffer no close encounters and are spaced fairly n regularly (Bode’s law : an=0.4 + 0.3×2 ) planet semimajor axis (A U ) n an (A U ) Mercury+ 0.39 −∞ 0.4 V enus 0.72 0 0.7 Earth 1.00 1 1.0 *predicted
    [Show full text]
  • Planets of the Solar System
    Chapter Planets of the 27 Solar System Chapter OutlineOutline 1 ● Formation of the Solar System The Nebular Hypothesis Formation of the Planets Formation of Solid Earth Formation of Earth’s Atmosphere Formation of Earth’s Oceans 2 ● Models of the Solar System Early Models Kepler’s Laws Newton’s Explanation of Kepler’s Laws 3 ● The Inner Planets Mercury Venus Earth Mars 4 ● The Outer Planets Gas Giants Jupiter Saturn Uranus Neptune Objects Beyond Neptune Why It Matters Exoplanets UnderstandingU d t di theth formationf ti and the characteristics of our solar system and its planets can help scientists plan missions to study planets and solar systems around other stars in the universe. 746 Chapter 27 hhq10sena_psscho.inddq10sena_psscho.indd 774646 PDF 88/15/08/15/08 88:43:46:43:46 AAMM Inquiry Lab Planetary Distances 20 min Turn to Appendix E and find the table entitled Question to Get You Started “Solar System Data.” Use the data from the How would the distance of a planet from the sun “semimajor axis” row of planetary distances to affect the time it takes for the planet to complete devise an appropriate scale to model the distances one orbit? between planets. Then find an indoor or outdoor space that will accommodate the farthest distance. Mark some index cards with the name of each planet, use a measuring tape to measure the distances according to your scale, and place each index card at its correct location. 747 hhq10sena_psscho.inddq10sena_psscho.indd 774747 22/26/09/26/09 111:42:301:42:30 AAMM These reading tools will help you learn the material in this chapter.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 When Induction Was About Concepts John P. Mccaskey
    When Induction Was About Concepts John P. McCaskey Stanford University The philosophy professor says, ―This swan is white. That swan is white. And so is the other,‖ and asks, ―May we legitimately infer that all swans are white?‖ In this way the students are introduced to induction or, as we seem always to call it, the ―problem‖ of induction. Deduction presents no real problem, we say, but induction brings no end of trouble. It is stubborn, recalcitrant, rebellious. We can almost hear Henry Higgins singing, ―Why can‘t a woman be more like a man?‖ or ―Why can‘t induction be more like deduction? / Deduction is so honest, so thoroughly square / eternally noble, historically fair. / Why can‘t induction be more like deduction ?‖ Higgins does not sing that, but Nicholas Rescher, for example, says, ―An inductive inference can always be looked upon as an aspiring but failed deductive inference.‖1 Rescher speaks for virtually all epistemologists of the last hundred years. But this position was not always so common. There were times when induction was not thought to be a problematic sort of inference. In fact, there were times induction was not thought to be primarily about propositional inference at all. Induction was about forming sound concepts and good definitions. This essay recalls those times. Recalling them is important for three reasons. First, doing so will help check our temptation to think our predecessors were too naïve, careless, or stupid to see the obvious. ―How could Francis Bacon have thought his method of induction would lead to certainty?!‖ ―How could William Whewell not have appreciated Hume‘s challenge to induction?!‖ ―How could Aristotle have thought all induction reduces to complete enumeration?!‖ But these men were not stupid.
    [Show full text]
  • Young People & Brexit
    YOUNG PEOPLE & BREXIT by Flavia Williams, Dominic Brind, and Thomas Peto Published by Our Future, Our Choice Our Future, Our Choice is a youth movement campaigning for a People’s Vote on the final Brexit deal. Our Future, Our Choice Millbank Tower, Millbank, Westminster, London SW1P 4QP www.ofoc.co.uk The authors would like to extend their thanks to all those who have helped with this report. As well as those who would prefer not to be named, we would like to thank Dr. Manmit Bhambra for her kind advice and guidance, and the policy team at Open Britain. !2 CONTENTS Foreword 4 The RT Hon Sir John Major KG CH .……………………………………………….……………………………………………………….. Executive Summary 7 ………………………………………………………………………………………………………… An Outward Looking Generation 11 ………………………………………………………………………………………………………… The Price of Brexit 14 Tommy Peto ………………………………………………………………………………………………………… Youth Opportunity: Education and Employment 24 ………………………………………………………………………………………………………… Children and Brexit 27 ………………………………………………………………………………………………………… Securing Data after Brexit 31 ………………………………………………………………………………………………………… Protecting Young Workers 35 ………………………………………………………………………………………………………… The Environmental Cost 38 ………………………………………………………………………………………………………… Bibliography 40 !3 FOREWORD The RT Hon Sir John Major KG CH Our decision to leave the EU is one of the most divisive policies in British history. Our Future, Our Choice sets out with great clarity the implications for young people, and I commend it warmly. Brexit has divided the component parts of the UK, placing England and Wales (as “Leavers”), in opposition to Scotland and Northern Ireland. It has divided our mainstream political parties; business and commerce; communities; friends — and even families. In many cases, these scars run deep. People who voted for Brexit did so with high hopes — most of which will be unrealised. We were told that we would keep the advantages of the Single Market.
    [Show full text]
  • Constantine the Great and Christian Imperial Theocracy Charles Matson Odahl Boise State University
    Boise State University ScholarWorks History Faculty Publications and Presentations Department of History 1-1-2007 Constantine the Great and Christian Imperial Theocracy Charles Matson Odahl Boise State University Publication Information Odahl, Charles Matson. (2007). "Constantine the Great and Christian Imperial Theocracy". Connections: European Studies Annual Review, 3, 89-113. This document was originally published in Connections: European Studies Annual Review by Rocky Mountain European Scholars Consortium. Copyright restrictions may apply. Coda: Recovering Constantine's European Legacy 111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111111 Constantine the Great and Christian Imperial Theocracy Charles Matson Odahl, Boise State University1 rom his Christian conversion under the influence of cept of imperial theocracy was conveyed in contemporary art Frevelatory experiences outside Rome in A.D. 312 until (Illustration I). his burial as the thirteenth Apostle at Constantinople in Although Constantine had been raised as a tolerant 337, Constantine the Great, pagan polytheist and had the first Christian emperor propagated several Olympian of the Roman world, initiated divinities, particularly Jupiter, the role of and set the model Hercules, Mars, and Sol, as for Christian imperial theoc­ di vine patrons during the early racy. Through his relationship years of his reign as emperor
    [Show full text]
  • Debate Over Justification by Faith: Evangelicals and Catholics
    Journal of the Adventist Theological Society, 20:1-2 (2009):112-146. Article copyright © 2009 by Norman R. Gulley. Debate Over Justification by Faith: Evangelicals and Catholics Norman R. Gulley Southern Adventist University 1. Biblical Understanding of Justification by Faith Paul says “they are justified by his grace as a gift, through the redemption which is in Christ Jesus” (Rom 3:24, RSV), for “a man is justified by faith apart from works of the law” (Rom 3:28 RSV), with even faith a gift (Rom 10:17). Humans are “justified by his blood” (Rom 5:9, ESV). Calvary was the “one act of righteousness” which “leads to justification and life for all men” (Rom 5:18b, ESV). “God made him [Christ] who had no sin to be sin for us, so that in him we might become the righteousness of God” (2 Cor 5:21). Justification is found in Christ, and is received by faith. This has nothing to do with Christ’s faithfulness in the covenant which continues human membership in the covenant, as proposed by “New Perspectives on Paul” scholarship. Justification explains how one gets in (not how one stays in) the covenant. Justification is an entry level reality, having to do with how one is saved. The word justify in Hebrew (hitsdiq) and Greek (dikaioun) “never refer to the infusion of righteousness, that is the transformation of someone from being ungodly to being virtuous.” Justification is the same throughout humans’ history, in old and new covenant periods, because it is about the one eternal gospel (Rev 14:6).
    [Show full text]
  • Meteorites and the Origin of the Solar System
    Meteorites and the origin of the solar system STEPHEN G. BRUSH University of Maryland, College Park, MD 20742, USA (e-mail: [email protected]) Abstract: During the past two centuries, theories of the origin of the solar system have been strongly influenced by observations and theories about meteorites. I review this history up to about 1985. During the 19th century the hypothesis that planets formed by accretion of small solid particles ('the meteoritic hypothesis') competed with the alternative 'nebular hypothesis' of Laplace, based on condensation from a hot gas. At the beginning of the 20th century Chamberlin and Moulton revived the meteoritic hypothesis as the 'planetesimal hypothesis' and joined it to the assumption that the solar system evolved from the encounter of the Sun with a passing star. Later, the encounter hypothesis was rejected and the planetesimal hypothesis was incorporated into new versions of the nebular hypothesis. In the 1950s, meteorites provided essential data for the establishment by Patterson and others of the pre- sently accepted 4500 Ma age of the Earth and the solar system. Analysis of the Allende meteorite, which fell in 1969, inspired the 'supernova trigger' theory of the origin of the solar system, and furnished useful constraints on theories of planetary formation developed by Urey, Ringwood, Anders and others. Many of these theories assumed condensation from a homogeneous hot gas, an assumption that was challenged by astrophysical calculations. The meteoritic-planetesimal theory of planet formation was developed in Russia by Schmidt and later by Safronov. Wetherill, in the United States, established it as the preferred theory for formation of terrestrial planets.
    [Show full text]
  • Title Spons Agency Bureau No Pub Date Contract Note
    DOCUMENT LIZSUME ED 071' C87 82 015 524 TITLE Project Musics Reader 2,Motion in the Heavens. .INSTITUTION Harvard Univ., Cambridge,Mass. Harvard Project _Physics. SPONS AGENCY Office of Education (DREW), Washington, D.C.,Bureau of Research. BUREAU NO BK-5-1038 PUB DATE 68 CONTRACT 08C-5-10-058 NOTE 233p.; Authorized InterimVersion EDRS PRICE MF -$0.65 HC-89.87 _DESCRIPTORS Astronomy; Instructional Materials;.*Motion; *Physics; Science, Fiction;. Science Materials; _Secondary Grades; *Secondary School Science; *Space; *Supplementary Reading Materials IDENTIFIER'S Harvard Project Physics ABSTRACT As a supplement to.Projpct Physics Unit 2, specially, selected articles are presented in this reader for student browsing. _Eight excerpts are given under headings:,the starry messenger, Newton_. And the principia, an appreciation of the earth, space the unconquerable, Is there intelligent life beyond the earth3,11 the life story of a galaxy, expansion of the universe, and Dyson sphere. Seven book passages. are included under. the, headings of the black cloud, roll call, a night at the observatory, Repler's celestial music, universal gravitation, a table of stars within twenty-two light years that could have habitable planets, and three poetic _fragments about astronomy. The remaining articles includea preface to the books of the ,revolutions, Kepler, Kepler on. Mars, laws of ..motion and proposition one,, garden of Epicurus, a search for life on earth at Kilometer resolution, the. boy who redeemed his father's _name, great comet of 1965, gravity experiments, unidentified flying objects, and negative mass. Illustrations for explanationpurposes . are provided. The work of Harvard. Project Physics has been .financially supported by: the Carnegie Corporation of New York, the Ford.
    [Show full text]