Liberty and Equality in Hedonistic Utilitarianism 1

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Liberty and Equality in Hedonistic Utilitarianism 1 LIBERTY AND EQUALITY IN HEDONISTIC UTILITARIANISM 1. What is Utilitarianism? How should societies be organized? Should we have a democracy with competing political parties, or rule of a single party? Private property or common resources? Religious liberty or an established church; strong privacy rights? How much freedom of expression on political, scientific, cultural, and artistic issues? And what about the policy of a country toward other countries: how much support does one country owe to others? Answering these questions depends in part on empirical knowledge: it is hard to decide what the best tax system is without having some ideas about how people respond to tax rates, and hard to know which form of democracy is best without some ideas about how different forms work. But our answers also depend on our political principles and values: on a political morality. So what political morality should we use to guide our answers? According to the utilitarian tradition of moral and political thought— whose great exponents included Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill—the correct standard is the principle of utility, or "greatest happiness principle." This principle provides the sole ultimate standard of right and wrong conduct. Here is a relatively crisp statement of the principle: Principle of Utility: In any circumstances, that action ought to be done (is right) and that institution ought to obtain (is right) which, of all the alternatives available, produces the greatest net balance of happiness Justice, Spring 2006—2 over unhappiness, when we sum happiness and unhappiness over all sentient beings, from now into the future. The crucial feature of utilitarian political morality is that it calls for the maximization of aggregate happiness: it is concerned only about happiness and unhappiness, and with respect to happiness, only about its sum—and not any particular distribution of happiness. It follows from this emphasis on aggregation that utilitarianism requires that we make simple trade-offs of the burdens on some people (say, slaves) and benefits to other people (say, masters). A large pleasure to a master outweighs a large—but not quite as large—burden of pain on a slave, no matter how severe the pain for the slave. The importance of an individual’s life for political morality, then, is exhausted by the amount of happiness in that life, and thus the contribution to the aggregate. 2. Two Reasons for Endorsing Utilitarianism Why might we endorse the principle of utility as the basis of our political philosophy? Two considerations are especially important to the utilitarian’s case for the principle. Consequentialism: Most fundamentally, the principle of utility represents a refinement of the intuitive idea that conduct and policy are right just in case they have the best overall results: Bentham said that “thinking men look to consequences.” Utilitarianism develops this consequentialist idea by identifying the goodness of an act’s consequences with the amount of happiness produced by the act.1 So if the right institutions or conduct are those with the best Justice, Spring 2006—3 consequences, and if one set of consequences is better than another just in case it contains more overall happiness, then what is right is what produces the greatest happiness overall. Moral Equality: By assigning the happiness of each affected party equal weight, the principle of utility also represents one way to treat affected individuals as moral equals. Utilitarianism does not require that individuals be equally happy, but in maximizing the sum, each individual’s happiness gets precisely the same weight.2 So utilitarianism is a universalistic moral view: the standards of right action take into account all sentient beings. The moral community is not confined to our own society, or to the current generation, nor do the members of our society or current generation or species get any special weight. 3. Utilitarianism, Rights, and Fairness The idea that the goodness of consequences is one important consideration in evaluating conduct and institutions is familiar and not very controversial. And the idea that consequences are better if they involve greater happiness is also plausible. But is this the whole story? Or does utilitarianism unacceptably narrow the range of considerations relevant to deciding what is right? Take the case of rights, for example. It is a commonplace in this political culture that individuals have rights that ought not to be abridged even in the name of promoting greater community welfare. We do not think it is legitimate to punish the innocent or to deprive people of their religious liberty simply Justice, Spring 2006—4 because such punishments and deprivations increase the sum of social happiness by contributing so much to the happiness of others. Or take the value of fairness. We ask whether policies or institutions are in some way unfairly burdensome to some individuals: we look to how opportunities, benefits, and burdens are distributed across people, and resist the purely aggregative idea that a large sum of small benefits distributed across a big group always outweighs a smaller sum of big burdens concentrated on a very small group. But for utilitarians, the principle of utility is the sole axiom of political morality. No matter what the kind or magnitude of the burden a policy or institution imposes on some, utilitarians must endorse it if it confers greater benefits on others. Aggregate happiness is all matters. What then does the utilitarian say about rights and fairness? Consider the issue of basic rights. The classical utilitarians were strong liberals: proponents of a fair legal system with protections for the innocent, rights to religious liberty, and freedom of speech and press. So they did not deny the importance of rights. But they did argue that rights are not independent bases of political argument, operating alongside the general happiness. Rather, people ought to have rights if and only if rights contribute to overall happiness. Take a contemporary example: Should people who are suffering and whose future prospects are dim, have a right to terminate their own lives and call on a doctor to help? To answer, the utilitarian asks whether the reduction in pain for the suffering individual is overbalanced by, for example, increased suffering Justice, Spring 2006—5 for family members, or greater suffering in society because assisted suicide indirectly reduces respect for life. If the reduced suffering is not overbalanced, then there is a right to assisted suicide. About bodily integrity more generally, the utilitarians thought that the burdens imposed by infringements of bodily integrity were greater than the benefits to others resulting from those infringements. And the same for religious liberty: the burdens on dissenters were greater than the benefits to others of religious uniformity. And that’s why people should have rights to bodily integrity and religious liberty. Common views about rights, then, mix truth and illusion: the truth is that rights are important; the illusion is that their importance is fundamental, indeed more fundamental than the general welfare.3 Instead, they are important because they increase overall happiness: they promote aggregate social welfare. And that, in the end, is all that matters. 4. Bentham's Interpretation of the Principle of Utility I have been discussing utilitarianism in general, and have referred several times to deriving various conclusions from the principle of utility. But to apply the principle of utility, we need to understand what happiness is, and what sorts of things produce it. Thus consider Bentham’s account of utility. First, then, "utility" is "the tendency to produce good consequences." So the principle of utility expresses the consequentialist idea that conduct is right just in case it has the best consequences. Justice, Spring 2006—6 But what makes some consequences better than others? Bentham’s proposes a hedonist theory of value on which pleasure (which he identifies with happiness) is the only thing good in and of itself, and not good because of its consequences.4 Knowledge and beauty, for example, are not good in themselves, but only for their effects. So conduct has utility only if it tends to produce pleasure5; and choices maximize utility when they are maximally productive of pleasure. But what is pleasure? Bentham tells us that pleasures are "interesting perceptions,"6 by which he means mental states that we take an interest in or find it desirable to have. And what produces pleasure and pain? Bentham's answer is (basically) a self-interested variant of psychological hedonism. "Psychological hedonism" is the view that people act to produce the greatest pleasure for themselves; the egoistic variant claims that what brings a person pleasure is principally a matter of the state of that agent—that pleasures and pain are principally “self- regarding”—from bodily enjoyment, money, power, and life itself. Bentham agrees that we sometimes derive pleasure from the pleasures of others— motivated by goodwill, we get the pleasures of sympathy or benevolence.7 Sometimes we derive pleasures from their pain: the pleasures of antipathy or malevolence.8 But self-regarding pleasures are the “most powerful, most constant, and most extensive.”9 Finally, to maximize the sum of happiness, we need to measure pleasures, and compare magnitudes across people. To this end, Bentham Justice, Spring 2006—7 proposes that the quantity of pleasure is determined by its two natural dimensions—its intensity, and its duration (the amount of time it lasts).10 Better pleasures are interesting perceptions that last longer and/or are more intense. 5. Utilitarianism and Liberty Thus far, I have been focusing on the foundations of political morality. But the classical utilitarians—Bentham and Mill—were political reformers. A utilitarian society, they thought, would not only be a more rational society—founded on a calculation on beneficial consequences—but one with greater freedom and equality.
Recommended publications
  • Animals and the Frontiers of Citizenship
    Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 34, No. 2 (2014), pp. 201–219 doi:10.1093/ojls/gqu001 Published Advance Access February 5, 2014 Animals and the Frontiers of Citizenship Will Kymlicka* and Sue Donaldson** Abstract —Citizenship has been at the core of struggles by historically excluded Downloaded from groups for respect and inclusion. Can citizenship be extended even further to domesticated animals? We begin this article by sketching an argument for why justice requires the extension of citizenship to domesticated animals, above and beyond compassionate care, stewardship or universal basic rights. We then consider two objections to this argument. Some animal rights theorists worry that extending citizenship to domesticated animals, while it may sound progressive, would in fact http://ojls.oxfordjournals.org/ be bad for animals, providing yet another basis for policing their behaviour to fit human needs and interests. Critics of animal rights, on the other hand, worry that the inclusion of ‘unruly’ beasts would be bad for democracy, eroding its core values and principles. We attempt to show that both objections are misplaced, and that animal citizenship would both promote justice for animals and deepen fundamental democratic dispositions and values. Keywords: citizenship, animal rights, justice, co-operation at Queen's University on June 23, 2014 1. Introduction In our recent book Zoopolis, we made the case for a distinctly ‘political theory of animal rights’.1 In this Lecture, we attempt to extend that argument, and to respond to some critics of it, by focusing specifically on the novel idea of ‘animal citizenship’. To begin, let us briefly situate our approach in the larger animal rights debate.
    [Show full text]
  • St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death
    The University of Akron IdeaExchange@UAkron Williams Honors College, Honors Research The Dr. Gary B. and Pamela S. Williams Honors Projects College Spring 2020 St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death Christopher Choma [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ideaexchange.uakron.edu/honors_research_projects Part of the Christianity Commons, Epistemology Commons, European History Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, History of Religion Commons, Metaphysics Commons, Philosophy of Mind Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Please take a moment to share how this work helps you through this survey. Your feedback will be important as we plan further development of our repository. Recommended Citation Choma, Christopher, "St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death" (2020). Williams Honors College, Honors Research Projects. 1048. https://ideaexchange.uakron.edu/honors_research_projects/1048 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by The Dr. Gary B. and Pamela S. Williams Honors College at IdeaExchange@UAkron, the institutional repository of The University of Akron in Akron, Ohio, USA. It has been accepted for inclusion in Williams Honors College, Honors Research Projects by an authorized administrator of IdeaExchange@UAkron. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. 1 St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death By: Christopher Choma Sponsored by: Dr. Joseph Li Vecchi Readers: Dr. Howard Ducharme Dr. Nathan Blackerby 2 Table of Contents Introduction p. 4 Section One: Three General Views of Human Nature p.
    [Show full text]
  • Environmental Ethics Anthropocentrism
    Environmental Ethics Anthropocentrism Introduction Anthropcentrism is the world view that places human beings as the center of the cosmos Five Interconnected Themes: 1) natural order has a grand hierarchy (a “Great Chain of Being) 2) the ontological divide between human and nonhuman nature 3) nature as a machine 4) only humans beings have intrinsic value/nature has only instrumental value 5) the moral community is limited to human beings Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274) The Summa Contra Gentiles develops the ethical implications of the Great Chain of Being humans are closest to the likeness of God rational creatures exercise free will God bestows intrinsic value on rational creatures “Accordingly intellectual creatures are ruled by God, as though He cared for them for their own sake, while other creatures are ruled as being directed to rational creatures” (63) other creatures are slaves to their environment their actions casually determined by the environment thus human beings alone are morally considerable only human beings have freedom “he is free who is cause of himself . intellectual nature alone is free” human beings have the right to subjugate other beings below on the hierarchy “Hereby is refuted the error of those who said it is sinful for man to kill dumb animals: for by divine providence they are intended for man’s use in the natural order” (64) anticipating Kant, the only danger in killing dumb animals is that such behavior might lead to cruelty to human beings Francis Bacon (1561-1626) The Great Instauration focus of knowledge should be practical the improvement of the human condition knowledge is power over nature “the roads to human power and to human knowledge lie close together, and are nearly the same” this view of knowledge as power is stated more clearly in New Organon (1620) Title refers to Aristotle’s logical and methodological works known collectively as the Organon this will be a new organon, thus a new scientific method “Human knowledge and human power meet in one; for where the cause is not known the effect cannot be produced.
    [Show full text]
  • Educational Rights and the Roles of Virtues, Perfectionism, and Cultural Progress
    The Law of Education: Educational Rights and the Roles of Virtues, Perfectionism, and Cultural Progress R. GEORGE WRIGHT* I. INTRODUCTION ................................................................................... 385 II. EDUCATION: PURPOSES, RECENT OUTCOMES, AND LEGAL MECHANISMS FOR REFORM ................................................................ 391 A. EDUCATIONAL PURPOSES AND RIGHTS LANGUAGE ...................... 391 B. SOME RECENT GROUNDS FOR CONCERN IN FULFILLING EDUCATIONAL PURPOSES ............................................................. 393 C. THE BROAD RANGE OF AVAILABLE TECHNIQUES FOR THE LEGAL REFORM OF EDUCATION ............................................................... 395 III. SOME LINKAGES BETWEEN EDUCATION AND THE BASIC VIRTUES, PERFECTIONISM, AND CULTURAL PROGRESS ..................................... 397 IV. VIRTUES AND THEIR LEGITIMATE PROMOTION THROUGH THE EDUCATIONAL SYSTEM ...................................................................... 401 V. PERFECTIONISM AND ITS LEGITIMATE PROMOTION THROUGH THE EDUCATIONAL SYSTEM ...................................................................... 410 VI. CULTURAL PROGRESS OVER TIME AND ITS LEGITIMATE PROMOTION THROUGH THE EDUCATIONAL SYSTEM .............................................. 417 VII. CONCLUSION: EDUCATION LAW AS RIGHTS-CENTERED AND AS THE PURSUIT OF WORTHY VALUES AND GOALS: THE EXAMPLE OF HORNE V. FLORES ............................................................................................ 431 I. INTRODUCTION The law of education
    [Show full text]
  • Reading List for Comprehensive Examination in Political Theory
    READING LIST FOR COMPREHENSIVE EXAMINATION IN POLITICAL THEORY Department of Political Science Columbia University Requirements Majors should prepare for questions based on reading from the entire reading list. Minors should prepare for questions based on reading from the core list and any one of the satellite lists. CORE LIST Plato, The Republic Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics Books I, II, V, VIII, X; Politics Polybius, Rise of the Roman Empire, Book I paragraphs 1-10 (“Introduction”) and Book VI Cicero, The Republic Augustine, City of God, Books I, VIII (ch.s 4-11), XII, XIV, XIX, XXII (ch.s 23-24, 29-30) Aquinas, Summa Theologica, Questions 42, 66, 90-92, 94-97, 105 Niccolò Machiavelli, The Prince; Discourses (as selected in Selected Political Writings, ed. David Wootton) Jean Bodin, On Sovereignty (ed. Julian Franklin) Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (as selected in Norton Critical Edition, ed. David Johnston) James Harrington, Oceana (Cambridge U. Press, ed. J.G.A. Pocock), pp. 63-70 (from Introduction), pp. 161-87; 413-19 John Locke, Second Treatise of Government; “A Letter Concerning Toleration” David Hume, “Of the Original Contract,” “The Independence of Parliament,” “That Politics May Be Reduced to A Science,” “Of the First Principle of Government,” “Of Parties in General” 1 Montesquieu, Spirit of the Laws (as selected in Selected Political Writings, ed. Melvin Richter) Adam Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Part I ("On the propriety of action"); Part II, Section II ("Of justice and beneficence"); Part IV ("On the effect of utility on the sentiment of approbation") Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Discourse on the Origins of Inequality; On The Social Contract Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations (as selected in World’s Classics Edition, ed.
    [Show full text]
  • REID-DISSERTATION-2018.Pdf
    VEGANISM AND THE ETHICS AND EPISTEMOLOGY OF DISAGREEMENT: A NEO-PASCALIAN APPROACH By Adam Curran Reid, B.A., M.A. A dissertation submitted to Johns Hopkins University in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Baltimore, Maryland, February, 2018 © Adam Curran Reid 2018 All Rights Reserved Abstract Disagreement is without a doubt one of the most universal, enduring, and oftentimes quite vexing, features of our life in common. This latter aspect, to be sure, becomes all the more evident when the particular disagreement at hand concerns differing ethical beliefs, value-judgments, or deep questions about the nature, and scope, of morally permissible action as such. One such question—also the chief subject of dispute to be taken up in this dissertation—is whether or not human beings are morally justified in killing, eating, wearing—in a word, exploiting—non-human animals for our benefit when doing so is neither required for us to survive or to flourish. Ethical vegans answer ‘no,’ insisting that non-human animals, qua sentient, conscious, experiential selves, ought to be treated with fundamental concern and respect, which, at a minimum, demands that we stop exploiting them as resources and commodities. Unsurprisingly, many disagree. While I shall have much more to say about (and in support for) ethical veganism in what follows, the guiding aim of this dissertation is firstly to explore certain key questions regarding the ethics and epistemology of disagreement(s) about veganism. In this way, my approach notably departs from that which has long prevailed (and rightly so) in conventional animal rights theory and vegan advocacy, where the emphasis, and aim, has generally been about making the first-order case for animal rights, abolition, and, therein, for veganism itself.
    [Show full text]
  • Connexion: a Note on Praxis for Animal Advocates
    Dalhousie Law Journal Volume 40 Issue 2 Article 5 10-1-2017 Connexion: A Note on Praxis for Animal Advocates John Enman-Beech Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.schulichlaw.dal.ca/dlj Part of the Animal Law Commons Recommended Citation John Enman-Beech, "Connexion: A Note on Praxis for Animal Advocates" (2017) 40:2 Dal LJ 545. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Schulich Law Scholars. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dalhousie Law Journal by an authorized editor of Schulich Law Scholars. For more information, please contact [email protected]. John Enman-Beech* Connexion: A Note on Praxis for Animal Advocates Effective animal advocacy requires human-animal connexion. I apply a relational approach to unfold this insight into a praxis for animal advocates. Connexion grounds the affective relationships that so often motivate animal advocates. More importantly, it enables animal agency, the ability of animals to act and communicate in ways humans can experience and respond to. With connexion in mind, some weaknesses of previous reform efforts become apparent. I join these in the slogan "abolitionismas disconnexion." In so far as abolitionism draws humans and animals apart, it undermines the movement's social basis, limits its imaginative resources, and deprives animals of a deeper freedom. I evaluate political theories of animals and find that only some can frame a picture of humans and animals living together in connexion. I close by noting the limitations of the connexion lens-we cannot simply create connexions without also evaluating whether they are oppressive-and some practical policy measures that can be taken today to further the goods of connexion Pour 6tre efficace, /a defense des animaux exige une connexion entre /'homme et /'animal.
    [Show full text]
  • Critical Guide to Mill's on Liberty
    This page intentionally left blank MILL’S ON LIBERTY John Stuart Mill’s essay On Liberty, published in 1859, has had a powerful impact on philosophical and political debates ever since its first appearance. This volume of newly commissioned essays covers the whole range of problems raised in and by the essay, including the concept of liberty, the toleration of diversity, freedom of expression, the value of allowing “experiments in living,” the basis of individual liberty, multiculturalism, and the claims of minority cultural groups. Mill’s views have been fiercely contested, and they are at the center of many contemporary debates. The essays are by leading scholars, who systematically and eloquently explore Mill’s views from various per spectives. The volume will appeal to a wide range of readers including those interested in political philosophy and the history of ideas. c. l. ten is Professor of Philosophy at the National University of Singapore. His publications include Was Mill a Liberal? (2004) and Multiculturalism and the Value of Diversity (2004). cambridge critical guides Volumes published in the series thus far: Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit edited by dean moyar and michael quante Mill’s On Liberty edited by c. l. ten MILL’S On Liberty A Critical Guide edited by C. L. TEN National University of Singapore CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 8RU, UK Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521873567 © Cambridge University Press 2008 This publication is in copyright.
    [Show full text]
  • Doctor of Philosophy
    RICE UNIVERSITY By Drew Robert Winter A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE Doctor of Philosophy APPROVED, THESIS COMMITTEE Cymene Howe (Apr 15, 2020) Cymene Howe James Faubion James Faubion (Apr 15, 2020) James Faubion Cary Wolfe Cary Wolfe (Apr 16, 2020) Cary Wolfe HOUSTON, TEXAS April 2020 i Abstract Hyperanimals: framing livestock and climate change in Danish Imaginaries By Drew Robert Winter The IPCC and UN FAO have both suggested a global reduction in meat consumption to reduce greenhouse gas emissions. But how do nations and citizens resolve tensions between ecological stewardship and meat consumption? What is implied in eating meat and raising livestock in a country where the historical imaginary yokes national values to the pig-producing countryside? To answer these questions, this dissertation examines how climate change is affecting meat consumption and production logics in Denmark. Though the country has a reputation for progressive environmental policy, its formerly large agricultural sector continues to exert disproportionate political influence, and many citizens consider pork its most "traditional" food. In 2016, a publicly-funded advisory council issued a report suggesting that parliament pass a beef tax to reduce consumption and reflect its environmental impact. The report was the most controversial the council had ever issued, with members receiving angry phone calls and politicians arguing the council should be disbanded. The proposal put national tensions between sustainability
    [Show full text]
  • March, 12. Utilitarianism 1. Ethical Utilitarianism = Consequentialism + Utilitarianism + Hedonism + Social Principle Consequent
    March, 12. Utilitarianism 1. Ethical utilitarianism = consequentialism + utilitarianism + hedonism + social principle Consequentialism: whether an act is morally right depends only on consequences (as opposed to the circumstances or the intrinsic nature of the act or anything that happens before the act). Utilitarianism: whether an consequence is valuable depends only on its utility Hedonic principle: a pleasure is the only value; whether an act is useful depends on its connection with pleasure (happiness consists in pleasures) Social principle: we must consider whether our action produces “social” happiness (not only happiness of some individuals) Utilitarianism (consequentialism) versus deontologism Deontologism: whether an act is morally good depends on its internal qualities (intention, purpose, compatibility with duty and obligation, compatibility with values) “Classic utilitarianism is consequentialist as opposed to deontological because of what it denies. It denies that moral rightness depends directly on anything other than consequences, such as whether the agent promised in the past to do the act now. Of course, the fact that the agent promised to do the act might indirectly affect the act's consequences if breaking the promise will make other people unhappy. Nonetheless, according to classic utilitarianism, what makes it morally wrong to break the promise is its future effects on those other people rather than the fact that the agent promised in the past.” SEP (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consequentialism) „Actual Consequentialism = whether an act is morally right depends only on the actual consequences (as opposed to foreseen, foreseeable, intended, or likely consequences). Direct Consequentialism = whether an act is morally right depends only on the consequences of that act itself (as opposed to the consequences of the agent's motive, of a rule or practice that covers other acts of the same kind, and so on).
    [Show full text]
  • The Legacy of Sovereign
    LegacySovereignJoy.48134.int.qxd 9/21/07 10:01 AM Page 1 T HE L EGACY OF S OVEREIGN J OY LegacySovereignJoy.48134.int.qxd 9/21/07 10:01 AM Page 2 OTHER BOOKS BY THE AUTHOR The Justification of God: An Exegetical and Theological Study of Romans 9:1–23 2nd Edition (Baker Book House, 1993, orig. 1983) The Supremacy of God in Preaching (Baker Book House, 1990) The Pleasures of God: Meditations on God’s Delight in Being God (Multnomah Press, 1991) Recovering Biblical Manhood and Womanhood: A Response to Evangelical Feminism (edited with Wayne Grudem, Crossway Books, 1991) What’s the Difference? Manhood and Womanhood Defined According to the Bible (Crossway Books, 1991) Let the Nations Be Glad: The Supremacy of God in Missions (Baker Book House, 1993) The Purifying Power of Living by Faith in Future Grace (Multnomah Press, 1995) Desiring God: Meditations of a Christian Hedonist (Multnomah Press, revised 1996) A Hunger for God: Desiring God through Fasting and Prayer (Crossway Books, 1997) A Godward Life: Savoring the Supremacy of God in All of Life (Multnomah Press, 1997) God’s Passion for His Glory: Living the Vision of Jonathan Edwards (Crossway Books, 1998) The Innkeeper (Crossway Books, 1998) A Godward Life, Book Two: Savoring the Supremacy of God in All of Life (Multnomah Press, 1999) LegacySovereignJoy.48134.int.qxd 9/21/07 10:01 AM Page 3 s a r e n a n o t w s s i l e e n h t t BOOK ONE LegTHEacy of Sovereign Joy God’s Triumphant Grace in the Lives of Augustine, Luther, and Calvin J OHN P IPER CROSSWAY BOOKS A PUBLISHING MINISTRY OF GOOD NEWS PUBLISHERS WHEAT O N , ILLINO IS LegacySovereignJoy.48134.int.qxd 9/21/07 10:01 AM Page 4 The Legacy of Sovereign Joy Copyright © 2000 by John Piper Published by Crossway Books a publishing ministry of Good News Publishers 1300 Crescent Street Wheaton, Illinois 60187 All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant and the Role of Pleasure in Moral Action
    Morrisson.1-25 7/11/08 9:02 AM Page 1 INTRODUCTION ............................... methodology and two kinds of ethics Kant’s theory of moral motivation is notoriously controversial. Indeed, few areas of Kant scholarship have drawn as much attention or prompted as much disagreement. Kant himself was so confounded by the issue of how the moral law can provide an incentive that moves the will to action that he refers to this problem as the “philosophers’ stone” (LE 27:1428). Unfortunately, Kant’s perplexity ultimately translates into an unusually elusive theory of moral motivation. As a result, the list of scholars who have presented divergent, often mutually exclusive interpre- tations of Kant’s account of moral motivation is long and distinguished.1 In this study, I want to contribute to the debate over how Kant thinks we are moved to act morally by approaching the issue in a new and, I argue, wholly enlightening way. The problem that is perhaps central to this debate is as follows: how can Kant account for moral motivation while divorcing the basis of morality from the pathological, and therefore motivational, side of human agents?2 To put this pivotal question another way: if Kant thinks that morality is not grounded in our sensuous and affective natures (as the British moral sense theorists suggest), then how does he think we are moved by moral considerations at all? Kant (notoriously) introduces the concept of respect (Achtung) as an answer to this question. On the face of it, his solution seems to be that respect is a moral feeling, and, as such, bridges the gap between the moral law and the capacity of hu- mans—as sensuously affected beings—to be motivated.
    [Show full text]