About Practical Problem Solving

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

About Practical Problem Solving ISSN 1392-1126. PROBLEMOS 2016 89 ABOUT PRACTICAL PROBLEM SOLVING Arto Mutanen Adjunct Professor Finnish National Defence University P.O. Box 7 FI-00861 Helsinki, Finland E-mail: [email protected] Abstract. Knowledge is, by definition, reliable and, hence, it can be applied to a variety of different problems. Nevertheless, in practical problem solving, we do not rely on mere truthful knowledge, but also on information which frames the practical acceptability. We are not looking for truthful solution but an optimal solution. Optimal solution is found out by optimizing some given (practical) parameters. The optimization is both theory based and practice based process. That is, practical problem solving is a human deliberation that interconnects theoretical and practical knowledge. So, the philosophical foundation of practical problem solving interconnects theoretical and practical philosophy. Especially ethical deliberation plays – or should play – central role in practical problem solving. The complexity of the advanced scientific knowledge needed in solving present day practical problems separates the people who know, from the people who do (decide). The situation makes immediate that we need some deeper pedagogical conviction: we need ecological education. Keywords: knowledge, practical reasoning, practical syllogism, responsibility The notion of knowledge has been under to recognize when we achieve knowledge. philosophical discussion since Plato. The So, Hintikka (2007) speaks about informa- classical notion of knowledge, which tion and knowledge as becoming an ideal originates from Plato’s dialog Theatetus, end state. In this sense it would be adequate says that knowledge is a well justified true to speak about information needed in prob- belief. The classical notion has been under lem solving. extensive philosophical discussion. In par- The notion of knowledge discussed in epistemology has been “so called” proposi- ticular, the truth condition and the justifica- tional knowledge, i.e. knowledge that can be tion condition have been philosophically expressed linguistically. This emphasis has interesting ones. The notion of truth is far implied that the problems of epistemology from clear; in realistic tradition, truth has consider the special problems of truth and been understood as a fundamental semantic justification conditions. All this, of course, notion, and in pragmatist tradition, truth has has been very interesting and important. been understood as an epistemic notion. It However, the connection of knowledge to is not clear at all what kind of justification human practical life has not been close. proper knowledge supposes. In fact, justifi- How is knowledge related to human prac- cation is an unending process. It is not easy tical life? What kind of activity is human 85 practical life? What is knowledge? It is best (uncertain) information we have. Still, obvious that knowledge is related to the hu- propositional knowledge has a positive man activity, but, at the same, it is obvious role in human practical activity. Human that “so called” propositional knowledge practical activity is not a “blind” activity, is not very closely connected to human but a deliberating activity. The notion of activity (ibid.). deliberation is essential here. What kind of Knowledge as a propositional knowl- deliberation is there under human activity? edge can be expressed in the form “A knows How knowledge is related to the delibera- that p’, where A is an agent of knowledge tion process? and p is a statement, or a proposition, which Sometimes humans act reactively, which expresses the content of the knowledge. For does not allow any deeper deliberation or example, “John knows that snow is white”, reflection: the agent is John and the sentence “snow is And so what we do without reflection, we do white” expresses the content of the knowl- quickly. For when a man actualizes himself in edge. However, it is important to recognize relation to his object, either by perceiving, or that the propositional knowledge is “subject imagining or conceiving it, what he desires, he does at once. For the actualizing of desire centred”, in the obvious sense: the definition is a substitute for inquiry or reflection. I is related to the agent of knowledge. In this want to drink, says appetite; this is drink, obvious sense, propositional knowledge is says sense or imagination or mind: straight “subjective”. However, it is also important away I drink. (Aristotle, On the Motion of to recognize that propositional knowledge Animals: Part 7) is not language dependent. Even if we are Such a quick action without deliberation saying that the content of the knowledge – in is sometimes called intuitive. Moreover, principle – can be expressed linguistically, such action does not separate humans from the content is not language-dependent: it (other) animals. There are several kinds of does not make the difference which lan- non-deliberating or intuitive actions (Booth, guage we use in expressing the content. This Rowbottom 2014). We intuitively do such language independence is in need of deep and such things. One class of intuitive ac- philosophical analysis, which has been one tions is acts that we have learned to do and research area in epistemology. the action has become automatic (Goldman How can such linguistically expressible 1970). Kahneman (2011: 20–24) separates knowledge be related to human practice? system 1 and system 2. System 1 is intuitive The relationship between practical activity and fast. In everyday contexts, this system is and propositional knowledge is not easily working well. However, we also need a slow characterized: Human practice is neither and calculating system 2, when we have something which is based on linguistically to guarantee that the result will be the one expressed knowledge nor it is not mediated intended. If we take a closer look at human by linguistically expressed knowledge. activity, we recognize that there is proper Moreover, it is not possible to wait that deliberation behind it. The discussion about the (unending) justification process justi- deliberation is connected to Kahneman’s fies the knowledge, but we have to use the separation of system 1 and system 2, but it 86 is not the same. Such deliberation can be in this, he will often fail to cure; for it is the characterized as practical inference: individual that is to be cured. (Aristotle, Metaphysics: Book I, Part 1) But how is it that thought (viz. sense, ima- gination, and thought proper) is sometimes The role of knowledge is not just seen by followed by action, sometimes not; some- looking at the practical action. Knowledge times by movement, sometimes not? What gives a reason why something happens. happens seems to be parallel to the case of Knowledge gives an understanding, which thinking and inferring about the immovable objects of science. There, the end is the truth makes an experienced agent a master. Mere seen (…), but here the two premises result in experience gives knowledge about a singu- a conclusion which is action – for example, lar case at his or her hands, but not general one conceives that every man ought to walk, knowledge; mere experience tells that the one is a man oneself: straight away one walks; case is such-and-such, but not why it is so. or that, in this case, no man should walk, one is a man: straight away one remains at rest. There is proper need for general knowledge (Aristotle, On the Motion of Animals: Part 7) about reason: Aristotle says that the conclusion in But yet, we think that knowledge and un- derstanding belong to art, rather than to such a practical inference is action. This experience, and we suppose artists to be separates the practical inference from the wiser than men of experience (which implies theoretical inference, in which the conclu- that Wisdom depends in all cases, rather on sion is a statement. However, Aristotle says knowledge); and this is because the former that practical and theoretical reasoning are know the cause, but the latter do not. For men of experience know that the thing is so, but parallel processes. As a conclusion, the do not know why, while the others know the action is, or should be, a conclusion from ‘why’ and the cause. (ibid.) some set of premises. Aristotle’s examples Aristotle assumes that the agent needs demonstrate that practical reasoning is causal knowledge, which tells why some- an “incomplete” inference, i.e. not all the thing happens or is the case. How this causal premises are explicated. However, we have knowledge is connected to the activity, is to study the character of the inference more not obvious. We have to study practical closely. What kind of reasoning is in ques- inference more closely and how knowl- tion? What is its “binding power”? We have to consider the interconnection edge is connected to it. Moreover, we also of knowledge (theory) and action more have to more closely consider what kind of closely. According to common opinion knowledge causal knowledge is and how it intuition, or Kahneman’s system 1, is good is related to practical reasoning. More gen- enough, that is mere experience is enough, erally we are considering practical human which is “justified” by stories how an reasoning which is related to the dynamic experienced agent acts just as well as and turn in logic (van Eijck; Visser 2012; Go- even better than a knowing agent. This was chet 2002; Rebuschi, M., 2006). In the fol- already noted by Aristotle: lowing we will consider practical syllogism and generalize it in order to see how the very If, then, a man has the theory without the experience, and recognizes the universal, fundamental conceptual ideas allows us to but does not know the individual included understand more complex practical problem 87 solving situations. In the paper we follow To get a better grasp, let us consider von Wright’s ideas very closely.
Recommended publications
  • Deliberation and the Role of the Practical Syllogism
    Deliberation and the Role of the Practical Syllogism Thesis submitted to the Kent State University College and Graduate School of Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MA in Philosophy By Timothy A. Elsey May 2011 © Copyright, 2011 by Timothy A. Elsey All Rights Reserved ii Thesis written by Timothy A. Elsey B.A., Mount Union College, 2007 M.A., Kent State University, 2011 Approved by Gina Zavota, Ph.D. , Advisor David W. Odell-Scott, Ph.D. , Chair, Department of Philosophy Timothy Moerland, Ph.D. , Dean, College of Arts and Sciences iii TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER INTRODUCTION . 1 I AN OVERVIEW OF ARISTOTLE . 6 The Soul According to Aristotle . 7 Wish . 9 The Necessary Balance . 11 Agents Must Deliberate About Means, Tendencies, and Character . 14 Decision vs. Appetite . 16 What Controls Actions? . 18 Voluntary and Involuntary Actions . 21 Mixed Actions . 22 Ethical Evaluation and Accountability . 23 Continence vs. Incontinence . 25 Conclusions . 27 II AN OVERVIEW OF JOHN M. COOPER . 32 Why Deliberation is Essential . 35 The Means-End Pattern and the Rule-Instance Pattern . 38 The Practical Syllogism . 42 The End of Deliberation . 49 III AN OVERVIEW OF FRED D. MILLER . 52 The Action-Terminating and Action-Type Terminating Interpretations . 55 Miller’s Analysis of Aristotle . 58 The Role of the Practical Syllogism . 63 The Necessary Insight . 67 IV AN OVERVIEW OF MY THESIS . 71 Against Cooper . 72 Support From Aristotle . 75 Paula Gottlieb’s Reflective Deliberation . 76 Cooper, Gottlieb, and Miller . 79 Deliberation Occurs, Until Action is Performed . 83 REFERENCES . 88 iv An Introduction One distinguishing aspect of a moral theory is the point at which ethical evaluations are assigned.
    [Show full text]
  • ED305329.Pdf
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 305 329 SP 030 956 AUTHOR Sarvimaki, Anneli TITLE Knowledge in Interactive Practice Disciplines. An Analysis of Knowledge in Education and Health Care. Research Bulletin 68. INSTITUTION Helsinki Univ. (Finland). Dept. of Education. REPORT NO ISBN-951-45-4787-X PUB DATE 88 NOTE 292p. PUB TYPE Reports - Research/Technical (143) EDRS PRICE MF01/PC12 Plus Postage. DESCRIPTORS *Educational Objectives; Educational Philosophy; Educational Practices; *Educational Principles; Health Promotion; *Interaction; Sociolinguistics; *Theory Practice Relationship; Values ABSTRACT This study formulates a conception of knowledge in interactive practice disciplines such as education and health care and clarifies different types of knowledge in these disciplines. Focus is on the relationship between practical and theoretical knowledge. Four theses are discussed: (1) the role of knowledge in an interactive practice is to guide practice; (2) different types of knowledge in an interactive practice consist of value-knowledge, factual knowledge and procedural knowledge, parts of which are unarticulated, parts articulated; (3) science is a way of articulating and creating knowledge that can be used as internal action determinants in the practice concerned; and (4) theories in an interactive practice can have both a theoretical and a practical purpose but the theoretical purpose is also indirectly linked to the practical. (Author/JD) "t***************************************************2****************** * Reproductions supplied by EDRS are the
    [Show full text]
  • Practical Rationality–Its Nature and Operation
    Studia Humana Volume 8:2 (2019), pp. 55—68 DOI: 10.2478/sh-2019-0018 Practical Rationality – its Nature and Operation Andrzej Niemczuk University of Rzeszów, Rejtana 16c Av., 35-959 Rzeszów, Poland e-mail: [email protected] Abstract: The article presents a proposal of explanation what practical rationality is, how it works and what are its criteria. In order to define practical rationality, the author starts from the general characteristics of reason, and then in the realm or reason activity distinguishes practical rationality from theoretical rationality. The necessary conditions of practical rationality are presented, as well as its standing between freedom and values. Next, the sources and nature of practical reasons are characterized, as well as their relation to values and desires. The problem of practical syllogism is briefly commented on. In the final part of the article the author proposes five criteria of practical rationality. Keywords: practical rationality, reason, practical reasons, criteria of rationality, practical syllogism, freedom, values. 1. General Remarks on the Concept of Rationality The typologies of rationality proposed in the literature on the subject are too varied to comment on them in detail in the present article. The differences between them vividly come to light when relevant works by Ryszard Kleszcz, Mieszko Tałasiewicz, Józef Życiński, Ryszard Szarfenberg and other authors are compared [3], [16], [17], [18], [14], [7]. Differentiated types are usually created by adding a domain adjective to the notion of rationality (e.g. epistemic, methodological, ontological, pragmatic rationality etc.), or a noun defining a field of thinking (e.g. rationality of science, politics, common thinking, decision, economic choice, etc.).
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]
  • The Practical Syllogism in Context: De Motu 7 and Zoology
    The Practical Syllogism in Context: De Motu 7 and Zoology Pierre-Marie Morel, Ecole Normale Supérieure de Lettres et de Sciences humaines, Lyon Ziel dieses Beitrags ist es, die Erörterungen zum Praktischen Syllogismus in De motu animalium, Kapitel 7, in ihren unmittelbaren Kontext einzuordnen. Dieser Kontext ist keineswegs ein logischer. De motu ist eine psychologische oder zoo- logische Abhandlung, die in den Rahmen der Naturphilosophie gehört. Darüber hinaus kann der Praktische Syllogismus aus De motu nicht auf „praktische“, d.h. anthropologische Fälle wie akrasia eingeschränkt werden. Er ist vielmehr in eine physiologische Erörterung eingefügt, die die biologische Erklärung der Emotionen, Reaktionen und Handlungen von Lebewesen betrifft. Daher bedeutet die Notwen- digkeit der Konklusion – hier der Handlung selbst – nicht, dass die Handlungsbe- dingungen auf Propositionen oder logische Beziehungen reduziert werden könnten. Eher steht sie für die Notwendigkeit, welche die Relation zwischen Handelndem und Leidendem in der Bewegung der Lebewesen bestimmt. Anyone who intends to explore Aristotle’s conception of the so-called practical syllogism, or practical reasoning, immediately feels embarrassed: there is neither a clear definition, nor a logical justification of this procedure in Aristotle’s texts. Moreover, Aristotle makes use of the practical syllogism in particular contexts – ethical (EN VII 5), psychological (De an. III 11), zoological (MA 7) – without explaining the general conditions of this use. This particular exegetical situation entails an obvious methodological rule: one needs, at first, to describe and analyze the immediate context of the specific uses of the practical syllogism in order to explain its meaning and theoretical function. 1 My first and foremost aim in this paper is to inscribe chapter 7 of the De motu animalium on the practical syllogism in its immediate context.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Theory of Practical Wisdom
    ¥ ARISTOTLE'S THEORY OF PRACTICAL WISDOM By YoSHlo FUJII Professor of Philosophy Aristotelian philosophy has been studied assiduously by scholars of the world for the last two thousand years. It seems that no Aristotelian stone has been left unturned and that nothing new can be said about the Stagirite in the sphere of philosophy and philology. But one can always expect to find a new angle, from which to study his outstanding works on philosophical problems. In any new undertaking, however, we should not follow the Scholastic formulae or the well-beaten path of Aristotelian study. What we are called upon to do today is to throw a new light on the incarnate system of Aristotelian philosophy evolved through following' its development rather than on his pre-harmonized system. This problem has been successfully dealt with by Prof. Werner Jaeger in his work, Aristoteles, Grueedlegueeg eil~er Geschich,te seileer L;fatwicklu,~g (Berlin, 1923). A. E. Taylor was quite right when he said, "If any of us henceforth ventures to make assertions about Aristotle without having taken Mr. Jaeger's fascinating work into account, he will at least be speaking very terribly at his own peril." I That development of Aristotelian philo- sophy seen in the studies effected on the Jaeger method has been followed and furthered largely by F. Solmsen and R. Walzer in both logical and ethical ficlds.2 1 myself have traced by this same method the history of Aristotle's metaphysical and epistemological developments in my work, Aristotelione Studies (in Japanese, Tokyo, 1940). Again in another treatise, The ~thics of Aristotle (in Japanese, Tokyo, 1951), I have endeavoured to survey and analyse the development and structure of the practical wisdom (~)Pb!)~alS) of Aristotle which constitutes the most fundamental concept of all the intellectual virtues.
    [Show full text]
  • Humanity at the Heart of Practice
    Humanity at the Heart of Practice Humanity at the Heart of Practice: A Study of Ethics for Health- Care Students and Practitioners By Beverly J. Whelton and Jane Neuenschwander Humanity at the Heart of Practice: A Study of Ethics for Health-Care Students and Practitioners By Beverly J. Whelton and Jane Neuenschwander This book first published 2019 Cambridge Scholars Publishing Lady Stephenson Library, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2PA, UK British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Copyright © 2019 by Beverly J. Whelton and Jane Neuenschwander All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner. ISBN (10): 1-5275-3280-1 ISBN (13): 978-1-5275-3280-9 TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction to the Text .............................................................................. 1 Section One: Values and Practical Reasoning Chapter 1 .................................................................................................... 6 Values Introduction Ethical Decisions are Similar to Clinical Decisions Community Values Personal Values Seeking the Principle-based Action Student Starters and Submissions Outline Terminology Chapter 2 .................................................................................................. 13 Practical Reasoning Introductions to
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatism Gateway to Artful Analytic Management Philosophizing
    Philosophy of Management DOI 10.1007/s40926-017-0065-y Actions and Decisions: Pragmatism Gateway to Artful Analytic Management Philosophizing Pierre Guillet de Monthoux1,2 # The Author(s) 2017. This article is an open access publication Abstract How management philosophy is conceived depends on if pragmatism is acknowledged or not! After having been under the main domination of management science both research and education has until recently widened its scope from a decision-making to an action-perspective. It seems to be a recent reconnection to pragmatism that makes the 2011 Carnegie report propose to rethink management in liberal arts terms, whilst the vastly influential 1959 Carnegie Pierson report distanced itself from American pragmatism thus focusing on decisions and forgetting actions. Actions may contain decisions and choices but contain more than that. A decision-perspective explains by causal inference modelling choices as calculated or programmed. The action-perspectives strive at understanding intentions of agents by philosophical interpretations of action stories. It is less limited to finding the logics for constructing worlds, to paraphrase Herbert Simon’s favorite philosopher Rudolf Carnap, than embarking on plausible, although not certain, reconstructions of intentions giving meaning to action stories. This can be illustrated by turning to Elizabeth Anscombe’s Wittgensteinian investigation of intentions as Aristotelian syllogistic reasoning. Her constant analytical care to defend a philosophy of action against metaphysical assumptions and taken-for-granted Bpsychologisms^ shows that an action-perspective is as analytic as ever one of decision-making. What differs is that the latter seems constantly attracted by programming inquiry by Bscientific methodology^ whilst the latter is charmed by philosophical approaches to action welcoming fascinating conundrums, enigmas and human goofs in the reality of managerial practice.
    [Show full text]
  • Appendix: Can Unconditional Moral Principles Be Justified?
    Appendix: Can Unconditional Moral Principles Be Justified?1 This attempt to justify unconditional moral principles in Aristotle’s ethics will make use of subject matter taken directly from the Nicomachean Ethics, but it will not rest on this material entirely. Some tools from contemporary model theory are imple- mented too. Constructing an axiomatic model for a portion of Aristotle’s ethics is not only possible, but helpful in making explicit relationships among concepts at the core of Aristotle’s theory. When its subject matter is understood from the perspec- tive of a deductive paradigm, this Aristotelian approach to ethics offers a promising basis for a realist ethical theory. Of course, a large portion of ethical subject matter would not fall within the scope of a science of ethics, but an important set of core ethical concepts can. Seeing how these concepts relate to one another puts us in a better position to understand the nature of the subject matter of ethics. Let us assume that it is legitimate to treat a significant portion of Aristotle’s ethics deductively. With this assumption in place we can ask how far a deductive paradigm of ethics would extend and how the basic concepts within Aristotle’s ethics are interrelated. The model developed below will offer a specific proposal about how we might get started. Methodological Considerations As we saw in Chapter 3, much of the subject matter in Aristotle’s ethics could be fit within the model of science that Aristotle proposes in the Posterior Analytics. That specific type of model will not be developed here because of the difficulties that come with working with such a cumbersome structure, which would be distracting.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Francisco De Vitoria on Prudence and the Nature of Practical Reasoning the History of the Concept of Prudence in Moral Philoso
    Francisco de Vitoria on Prudence and the Nature of Practical Reasoning The history of the concept of prudence in moral philosophy is often portrayed as a history of loss. According to the classical version of this view, it is, more specifically, a loss in moral significance: On Aristotle's account, there is a constitutive link between prudence and morality. Prudence provides morality with a sense for the particularities and the contingency of the situations in which agent has to act. And morality, by way of a substantial conception of the good life for human beings, provides prudence with an ethical impregnation that sets it apart from mere cleverness or cunning.1 Aquinas and other medieval authors largely adopt this Aristotelian doctrine, though they relocate it in the wider framework of Christian moral theology.2 In the philosophy of modernity, however, the constitutive link between morality and prudence is cut off by authors like Machiavelli, Hobbes, and Kant. They take prudence to be the ability to identify the most effective means to goals set no longer by morality but by the agent's contingent desires. So for them, prudence is mere cleverness or cunning after all.3 There is, however, an alternative to this classical version of the history of the concept of prudence. It is also essentially a history of loss, but it suggests that the history of the concept of prudence must be divided in a rather different manner: not between antiquity and the Middle Ages on the one hand and modernity on the other, but rather between antiquity on the one hand and the Middle Ages and modernity on the other; and not for moral, but for epistemological reasons.4 According to this view, the overly Aristotelian interpretation of Aquinas's moral philosophy implied in the classical version of the history of prudence has been justly criticized for overlooking an important difference between the moral theories of Aristotle and Aquinas: For Aristotle, there can be no such thing as a moral or practical science.
    [Show full text]
  • An Anthology of Philosophical Studies Volume 4
    Variety in Mass Communication Research: An Introduction AN ANTHOLOGY OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES VOLUME 4 Editor Patricia Hanna University of Utah USA Editorial Board Gerald Doppelt University of California, SanDiego USA Carol Nicholson Rider University USA Donald Poochigian University of North Dakota USA T. Ann Scholl United Arab Emirates University UAE 1 An Anthology of Philosophical Studies Board of Reviewers Chrysoula Gitsoulis CUNY USA Jonas S. Green Brikbeck College UK Keith Green East Tennessee State University USA Jan-Christoph Heilinger Berlin-Brandenburg Academy of Sciences and Humanities Germany Mark McEvoy Hofstra University USA Chris Onof Birkbeck College UK Elizabeth Schiltz College of Wooster USA Andrew Ward University of York UK 2 Variety in Mass Communication Research: An Introduction Athens Institute for Education and Research 2010 AN ANTHOLOGY OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES VOLUME 4 Edited by Patricia Hanna 3 An Anthology of Philosophical Studies First Published in Athens, Greece by the Athens Institute for Education and Research. ISBN: 978-960-6672-65-1 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored, retrieved system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the written permission of the publisher, nor be otherwise circulated in any form of binding or cover. Printed and bound in Athens, Greece by ATINER SA. 8 Valaoritou Street Kolonaki, 10671 Athens, Greece www.atiner.gr ©Copyright 2009 by the Athens Institute for Education and Research. The individual essays remain the intellectual properties of the contributors. 4 Variety in Mass Communication Research: An Introduction Table of Contents List of Contributors 1. Introduction 1 Patricia Hanna Part 1: History of Philosophy Ancient and Medieval 2.
    [Show full text]
  • SAGP SSIPS Abstracts 2013
    Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 10-2013 SAGP SSIPS Abstracts 2013 Anthony Preus Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Preus, Anthony, "SAGP SSIPS Abstracts 2013" (2013). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 427. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/427 This Announcement is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. Draft, September 15 The 31st annual joint meeting of The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy (SAGP) with The Society for the Study of Islamic Philosophy and Science (SSIPS) Abstracts Vishwa Adluri, [email protected] “Gita, Greek philosophy, and Arendt” This paper examines the interface between Greek and Indian notions of action. My starting point however will be Arendt’s notion of thinking as the paradigmatic activity. Through showing how the life of thought is not opposed to the life of action in Arendt I will introduce an important nuance into the Bhagavadgītā’s notion of action (karma). As in Arendt, the Indian text makes a distinction between mere work or labor and action in the true sense. A recovery of this notion of action is essential not only for understanding the Bhagavadgītā, but also for addressing our contemporary political context.
    [Show full text]