Abigail Modaff 1 WILLIAM JAMES's SOCIAL

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Abigail Modaff 1 WILLIAM JAMES's SOCIAL Abigail Modaff WILLIAM JAMES’S SOCIAL ETHICS This essay seeks to re-center the study of James’s ethics on his published works of the 1890s, especially “The Moral Philosopher and the Moral Life” (1891), “On a Certain Blindness in Human Beings” (1899), “What Makes a Life Significant?” (1899), and “Human Immortality: Two Supposed Objections to the Doctrine” (1898). Whether by the scope of James’s writings, or the allure of his vulnerable and compassionate character, or the flights of his poetic style, interpretations of James’s moral theory have been drawn to various corners of his oeuvre and the intellectual-historical world. They are unified only by their tendency to reduce James’s ethics to familiar categories, whether deontological, existentialist, religious, pluralistic, or utilitarian. But James’s moral works of the 1890s defy easy reduction: they presented a genuinely innovative via media between utilitarian and deontological approaches to ethics, informed by the pragmatic theory of truth and the Romantic and Emersonian traditions. The key to James’s ethics, and the focus of this essay, is his pragmatic account of obligation, first developed in 1891 and underscored in his works of the late 1890s. An immediate consequence of this pragmatic conception of obligation was the importance that sympathy assumed in James’s moral works – a move that rendered “William James’s social ethics” not only a category of philosophiZing, but an apt description of a moral theory which demanded interpersonality at every juncture. Thus, overall, James’s ethics collapsed into a plurality of positive obligations to the realization – not just the toleration – of others’ demands and ideals. This pluralism formed the basis for a moral life focused around sympathetic communication and the cooperative integration of disparate desires. James’s pragmatic conception of obligation has largely been overlooked in secondary literature. While most accounts of James’s ethics either focus upon interrogating his limited activism, 1 rendering him a defender of freedom, 2 1 Gerald E. Myers, William James: His Life and Thought (New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1986), 422-45; James Campbell, “William James and the Ethics of Fulfillment,” Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 17, no. 3 (Summer, 1981): entire, accessed February 13, 2013, www.jstor.org/stable/40319924; Ralph Barton Perry, The Thought and Character of William James (Nashville and London: Vanderbilt University Press, 1996), 216-52. 2 John K. Roth, Freedom and the Moral Life: The Ethics of William James (Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1969), entire, especially 7, 14-19, 36-49, 56-8, 62-3, 72-7; John Wild, The 1 Abigail Modaff elevating the role of religion in his moral universe,3 asserting his “individualism” and “toleration” to the detriment of his interpersonal ethics,4 or, most often, squaring James’s deontological allusions with their own utilitarian interpretations,5 this essay locates a clear and cohesive moral vision in James’s own language when it is placed in its pragmatic context. Utilitarian readings, while not baseless – especially given James’s dedication of Pragmatism (1907) to John Stuart Mill – do not specifically explore the Millian connection, and their resulting gloss of James as a generic desire-satisfaction utilitarian obscures his pragmatic naturaliZation6 of ethical terms and the authenticity that he accorded to obligation and duty. 7 This essay thus focuses upon the pragmatic and Emersonian contexts of James’s 1890s work not necessarily to the exclusion of utilitarianism, but in order to provide a firmer basis for future explorations of James’s utilitarian aspects. This reading is supported by the content of James’s letters, lectures, and publications during the 1890s. Following the success of The Principles of Psychology (1890), James’s time was occupied with teaching, lecturing, and an Radical Empiricism of William James (Garden City, New York: Doubleday & Company, Inc., 1969), 266-92, especially 270, 275-84, 289-92. 3 Wild, The Radical Empiricism, 293-329; Michael R. Slater, William James on Ethics and Faith (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), entire, especially 2-3, 5-16, 26-9, 45, 55-9, 65- 93. 4 Campbell, “William James,” entire; Perry, The Thought and Character, 216-7, 221, 223-4, 226-9, despite allowing some latitude for sympathy. 5 Slater, William James, 70-1, 74-5, 78-82; Richard M. Gale, The Divided Self of William James (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 10-12, 25-49; Graham Bird, William James (London and New York: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1986), 154-6. John Roth takes this line regarding “Moral Philosopher,” though he feels that essay is unrepresentative of James’s ethics as a whole: Roth, Freedom and the Moral, 59-71. Arguing against such readings is Wesley Cooper, The Unity of William James’s Thought (Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press, 2002), 222-39. 6 “Naturalization” is a difficult word to manage (see Gale, The Divided Self, 335-6). I intend it in the most general sense: as the rendering of moral qualities, concepts, and truths into the experienced, concrete, phenomenal world. No implication of scientific or social-scientific measurability is intended. 7 William James, “Pragmatism,” in William James: Pragmatism and Other Writings, ed. Giles Gunn (New York: Penguin Books, 2000), 4. On James and obligation, in addition to the discussion below, see Edward H. Madden, Introduction to The Works of William James, Volume 6: The Will to Believe, ed. Frederick H. Burkhardt (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1979), xxxii, on the fact that Dewey was inspired by “Moral Philosopher” to insert obligation into his own ethics; James’s 1900 letter to Francis R. Morse criticizing Oliver Wendell Holmes for ignoring duty, quoted in Perry, The Thought and Character, 216; and William James, “Is Life Worth Living?”, in William James: Pragmatism and Other Writings, ed. Giles Gunn (New York: Penguin Books, 2000), 232. 2 Abigail Modaff increasing distaste for psychological research. 8 In the decade his son characterized as “Turning to Philosophy,” James finally broke with Josiah Royce’s absolutism, admitted the philosophical nature of his psychology, assumed the mantle of pragmatism, and by most accounts reached his “mature” views.9 The roots of these new commitments, however, ran deep. Though he would not write Pragmatism until 1907, James had been steeped in a generally pragmatic viewpoint since the Metaphysical Club, and he traced the core of his own pragmatism to an 1884 essay that he republished in The Meaning of Truth (1909).10 It was in the 1890s that he attracted his two foremost disciples, Oxford’s F.C.S. Schiller and Chicago’s John Dewey, to the pragmatist approach, and he wrote to Schiller in 1897 that “we must fly a banner and start a school”; in addition, James always attributed the foundation of pragmatism to an 1878 article by Charles Peirce, to whom he dedicated the 1897 volume, The Will to Believe, that contained the republished “The Moral Philosopher and the Moral Life.”11 James’s son wrote that “if his time and energy had not been otherwise 8 Robert D. Richardson, William James in the Maelstrom of American Modernism (Boston & New York: Houghton Mifflin Company, 2006), 301-9, 341, 373-87; Perry, The Thought and Character, 221; Bruce Kuklick, The Rise of American Philosophy: Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1860-1930 (New Haven & London: Yale University Press, 1977), 180-1, 186. See also both the letters and the editorial material for chapters 10-13 in The Letters of William James, ed. Henry James (London: Longmans, Green and Co. Ltd, 1926), vol. I: 300-334 and vol. II: 2-127. Hereafter this collection will be referenced as “Letters,” with the proper volume noted. 9 Henry James, editorial materials in Letters, vol. II, 2; William James to Dickinson S. Miller, November 19, 1893, in Letters, vol. II, 18; James, “Pragmatism,” 25-6; Kuklick, The Rise, 181-3, 264-7; Wild, The Radical Empiricism, 277; David Lamberth, William James and the Metaphysics of Experience (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 5; H.S. Thayer, Introduction to The Works of William James, Volume 2: The Meaning of Truth, ed. Frederick H. Burkhardt (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1975), xxi-xxii; William James to Josiah Royce, December 18, 1892, in Letters, vol. I, 333: “I am just beginning to wake up from the sort of mental palsy that has been over me for the past year, and to take a little ‘notice’ in matters philosophical.” 10 Kuklick, The Rise, 47-54; William James, The Meaning of Truth, volume 2 of The Works of William James, ed. Frederick H. Burkhardt (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1975), 32. Thayer echoes James’s assessment of pragmatism’s source: Thayer, Introduction, xxi. 11 William James to F.C.S. Schiller, October 23, 1897, in Letters, vol. II, 66; Cooper, The Unity, 31; Richardson, William James in the Maelstrom, 304, 367. For James’s closeness to Dewey and Schiller, see William James, “The Chicago School,” in The Works of William James, Volume 5: Essays in Philosophy, ed. Frederick H. Burkhardt (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1978), entire; James, Meaning of Truth, 4, 37-60, 70-7, 93; James, “Pragmatism,” 5, 30. By 1903, Schiller already felt confident enough to proclaim in the preface to his Humanism: Philosophical Essays that pragmatism and humanism were the future of philosophy and James’s Will to Believe was at their center: F.C.S. Schiller, Humanism: Philosophical Essays (London: Macmillan & Co., Limited, 1903), viii-xxiii, especially xv-xvi, and ix where he traced pragmatism back to an 1879 essay of James’s. 3 Abigail Modaff consumed, the nineties might well have witnessed the appearance of papers which were not written until the next decade.”12 In this decade of transformation and continuity, moral issues were on the fifty-year-old James’s mind.
Recommended publications
  • Nineteenth Century Cracks in the Concept of Determinism
    !"#$%$$#%&'($#%)*+'(*,-./'"#'%&$'(0#-$1%'02'3$%$*4"#"/4 5)%&0*6/78'9,#':,-."#; <$="$>$?'>0*.6/78 @0)*-$8'A0)*#,B'02'%&$':"/%0*+'02'9?$,/C'D0BE'FFC'!0E'G'6A)BE'H'@$1EC'IJKG7C'11E'FLLHFML N)OB"/&$?'O+8'University of Pennsylvania Press @%,OB$'P<Q8'http://www.jstor.org/stable/2709176 . 5--$//$?8'IIRIIRSTII'IK8TT Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. University of Pennsylvania Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of the History of Ideas. http://www.jstor.org NINETEENTH CENTURY CRACKS IN THE CONCEPT OF DETERMINISM BY IAN HACKING Deterministe: Nom d'une secte peu connue en Allemagne et qui y a peu d'influence. Determinisme: Systeme, principes, doctrine des deterministes.1 Duringthe nineteenth century we witness an event that I call the erosion of determinism. At the start of the period we read Laplace, confident that all the world is ruled with the same exact necessity as is found in celestial mechanics. At the end we find C.S. Peirce (1839-1914) asserting there is no ground for believing either such a doctrine of necessity or for holding that the laws of natureare rightly represented by precise numerical constants.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy of William James As Related to Charles Renouvier, Henri Bergson, Maurice Blondel and Emile Boutroux
    Portland State University PDXScholar Dissertations and Theses Dissertations and Theses 1987 The philosophy of William James as related to Charles Renouvier, Henri Bergson, Maurice Blondel and Emile Boutroux Peggy Lyne Hurtado Portland State University Follow this and additional works at: https://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/open_access_etds Part of the Intellectual History Commons, and the Philosophy Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Hurtado, Peggy Lyne, "The philosophy of William James as related to Charles Renouvier, Henri Bergson, Maurice Blondel and Emile Boutroux" (1987). Dissertations and Theses. Paper 3713. https://doi.org/10.15760/etd.5597 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of PDXScholar. Please contact us if we can make this document more accessible: [email protected]. ---- l I AN ABSTRACT OF THE THESIS OF Peggy Lyne Hurtado for the Master of Arts in History presented June 10, 1987. Title: The Philosophy of William James as Related to Charles Renouvier, Henri Bergson, Maurice Blondel and Emile Boutroux. APPROVED BY MEMBERS OF THE THESIS COMMITTEE: Michael F. Reard~n, Chairman Guin~ David Joh This thesis argues two issues: William James' philosophy was-to a great extent derived from his interaction with the French philosophers, Charles Renouvier, Henri Bergson, Maurice Blondel and Emile Boutroux. Correlative to the fact that these five figures have an intellectual 2 relationship with one another, I also argue that in order to understand James, he must be placed within the context of these relations.
    [Show full text]
  • Immanuel Kant and the Development of Modern Psychology David E
    University of Richmond UR Scholarship Repository Psychology Faculty Publications Psychology 1982 Immanuel Kant and the Development of Modern Psychology David E. Leary University of Richmond, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.richmond.edu/psychology-faculty- publications Part of the Theory and Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Leary, David E. "Immanuel Kant and the Development of Modern Psychology." In The Problematic Science: Psychology in Nineteenth- Century Thought, edited by William Ray Woodward and Mitchell G. Ash, 17-42. New York, NY: Praeger, 1982. This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the Psychology at UR Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Psychology Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UR Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 1 Immanuel Kant and the Development of Modern Psychology David E. Leary Few thinkers in the history of Western civilization have had as broad and lasting an impact as Immanuel Kant (1724-1804). This "Sage of Konigsberg" spent his entire life within the confines of East Prussia, but his thoughts traveled freely across Europe and, in time, to America, where their effects are still apparent. An untold number of analyses and commentaries have established Kant as a preeminent epistemologist, philosopher of science, moral philosopher, aestheti­ cian, and metaphysician. He is even recognized as a natural historian and cosmologist: the author of the so-called Kant-Laplace hypothesis regarding the origin of the universe. He is less often credited as a "psychologist," "anthropologist," or "philosopher of mind," to Work on this essay was supported by the National Science Foundation (Grant No.
    [Show full text]
  • ACTA UNIVERSITATIS UPSALIENSIS Skrifter Utgivna Av Statsvetenskapliga Föreningen I Uppsala 196
    ACTA UNIVERSITATIS UPSALIENSIS Skrifter utgivna av Statsvetenskapliga föreningen i Uppsala 196 Svante Nycander The History of Western Liberalism Front cover portraits: Thomas Jefferson, Baruch de Spinoza, Adam Smith, Alexis de Tocqueville, Oliver Wendell Holmes, Joseph Schumpeter, Woodrow Wilson, Niccoló Machiavelli, Karl Staaff, John Stuart Mill, François-Marie Arouet dit Voltaire, Mary Wollstonecraft, John Locke, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Immanuel Kant, Ludwig Joseph Brentano, John Dewey, Wilhelm von Humboldt, Charles-Louis de Secondat Montesquieu, Ayn Rand © Svante Nycander 2016 English translation: Peter Mayers Published in Swedish as Liberalismens idéhistoria. Frihet och modernitet © Svante Nycander and SNS Förlag 2009 Second edition 2013 © Svante Nycander and Studentlitteratur ISSN 0346-7538 ISBN 978-91-554-9569-5 Printed in Sweden by TMG Tabergs AB, 2016 Contents Preface ....................................................................................................... 11 1. Concepts of Freedom before the French Revolution .............. 13 Rights and Liberties under Feudalism and Absolutism ......................... 14 New Ways of Thinking in the Renaissance ........................................... 16 Calvinism and Civil Society .................................................................. 18 Reason as a Gift from God .................................................................... 21 The First Philosopher to Be Both Liberal and Democratic ................... 23 Political Models during the Enlightenment ..........................................
    [Show full text]
  • Kant on Human Dignity: a Conversation Among Scholars
    Kant on Human Dignity: A Conversation among Scholars Author: John Victor Enslin Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/3807 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2014 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Philosophy KANT ON HUMAN DIGNITY: A CONVERSATION AMONG SCHOLARS a dissertation by JOHN VICTOR ENSLIN, S.J. submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy May 2014 © copyright by JOHN VICTOR ENSLIN, S.J. 2014 Kant on Human Dignity: A Conversation among Scholars John V. Enslin, S.J. Dissertation Director: Prof. Ronald Tacelli, S.J. Abstract This dissertation aims to examine the notion of ‘human dignity’ in Kant by means of a conversation with three Kantian scholars. One cannot understand Kant’s notion of human dignity without placing it in the context of his moral thought. For this reason we look in Chapter One at the philosopher Roger Sullivan. His major work Immanuel Kant’s moral theory includes a highly detailed treatment of human dignity. I shall present an analysis of his understanding within the context of his methodology and his general approach to Kant’s moral philosophy. We look in Chapter Two at Susan Shell’s ‘Kant on Human Dignity.’ In addition to this, we consider Shell’s methodology and some of her work on the early Kant where we find the roots of Kant’s conception of dignity. Chapter Three addresses Oliver Sensen’s novel interpretation of Kant’s use of the term ‘dignity.’ Utilizing the tools of Analytical Philosophy, he enters into dialogue with Kantian interpreters, suggesting that their understanding of dignity in Kant harbours elements at odds with Kant’s thought and that they thus fail to grasp the radical nature of Kant’s notion.
    [Show full text]
  • William James and the Force of Habit
    William James and the Force of Habit by Peter Alexander Livingston A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Political Science University of Toronto © Copyright by Peter Alexander Livingston (2011) William James and the Force of Habit Peter Alexander Livingston Doctor of Philosophy Department of Political Science University of Toronto 2011 Abstract By paying attention to the habitual register of politics this dissertation has sought to contribute to the theoretical literature on democratic citizenship. More precisely, I offer a more complex account the moral psychology of political agency presumed by the turn to ethics within democratic theory. The central question of this dissertation is how do citizens come to feel empowered to act on their convictions in politics? Political theorists often celebrate civic action as spontaneity and willfulness, and at the same time lament the agency-foreclosing complexity and fragmentation of late-modern politics. Drawing out this tension in Michel Foucault’s analysis of docility and transgression I argue that a middle path between disembodied autonomy and docile passivity is articulated in the moral psychology found in William James’s account of habit. The study makes this case by looking at three episodes of the foreclosure and recovery of action in James’s thinking: his engagement with Darwinian science and his nervous breakdown in the 1870’s and 80’s; his critique of democratic docility and debate on strenuousness with Theodore Roosevelt during the Spanish-American war; and the cynical adaptation of James’s psychology by the democratic realism of Walter Lippmann in the 1920’s.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics Through Metaphors: Towards An
    METAPHYSICS THROUGH METAPHORS: TOWARDS AN UNDERSTANDING OF TIME IN PSYCHOLOGY WITH WILLIAM JAMES'S PRINCIPLES OF PSYCHOLOGY DANIEL A. NOEL A thesis subrnitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Graduate Programme in Psychoiogy York University North York, Ontario December, 1998 National Library Bibliothèque nationale I*I of Canada du Canada Acquisitions and Acquisitions et Bibliographie Setvices services bibliographiques 395 Wellington Street 395, rue Wellington Ottawa ON K1A ON4 Ottawa ON KIA ON4 Canada Canada Your hie Voire référence Our Lle Nolre réfdrence The author has granted a non- L'auteur a accordé une licence non exclusive licence allowing the exclusive permettant à la National Library of Canada to Bibliothèque nationale du Canada de reproduce, loan, distribute or seli reproduire, prêter, distribuer ou copies of this thesis in microfom, vendre des copies de cette îhèse sous paper or electronic formats. la forme de microfiche/fih, de reproduction sur papier ou sur format électronique. The author retains ownership of the L'auteur conserve la propriété du copyright in this thesis. Neither the droit d'auteur qui protège cette thèse. thesis nor substantial extracts from it Ni la thèse ni des extraits substantiels may be printed or otherwise de celle-ci ne doivent être imprimés reproduced without the author's ou autrement reproduits sans son permission. autorisation. Metaphysics through metaphors: Towards an understanding of Time with William James's Principles of Psychology by Daniel Allen Noel a thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies of York University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Permission has been granted to the LIBRARY OF YORK UNIVERSITY to lend or seIl copies of this thesis, to the NATIONAL LIBRARY OF CANADA to microfilm this thesis and to lend or sell copies of the film, and to UNIVERSITY MICROFILMS to publish an abstract of this thesis.
    [Show full text]
  • The Origin of Pragmatism in William James
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1947 The Origin of Pragmatism in William James Charles A. Nash Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Nash, Charles A., "The Origin of Pragmatism in William James" (1947). Master's Theses. 600. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/600 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1947 Charles A. Nash THE ORIGIN OF PRAGMATISM IN WILLIAM JAMES BY CHARLES A. NASH, s,J., A.B. A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULF'ILLMEbJT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS IN LOYOLA UNIVERSITY JUNE 1947 VITA AUCTORIS Charles A. Nash., S.J. was born in St. Louis, Missouri., March 2, 1920. He was graduated from William Cullen McBride High School, st. Louis, June 1938, and entered St. Louis University where he studied in the College of Liberal Arts for three years. He entered the Florissant Novitiate., Florissant, Missouri, August, 1941· In 1945 he received the Bachelor of Arts degree from st. Louis University. From 1945 to 1947 he studied philosophy at West Baden College of Loyola University • • TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER PAGE I. THE LIFE A.ND CHARACTER OF WIILIAM JAMES • ••• l II.
    [Show full text]
  • Maine De Biran's Leibniz
    This is a repository copy of A Universal and Absolute Spiritualism: Maine de Biran's Leibniz. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/97861/ Version: Accepted Version Book Section: Dunham, J. (2016) A Universal and Absolute Spiritualism: Maine de Biran's Leibniz. In: Meacham, D. and Spadola, J., (eds.) The Relationship between the Physical and the Moral in Man. Bloomsbury . ISBN 9781472579676 Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ A Universal and Absolute Spiritualism Maine de Biran’s Leibniz Jeremy Dunham (University of Sheffield) In France during the nineteenth century the production of new editions, interpretations, and expositions of early modern philosophical texts was a flourishing activity. However, it is important to recognise when examining the scholarly works of this period that such interpretation and exposition was almost never produced without an agenda. A favourable interpretation of one of the giants of early modern philosophy that shows them to be the natural ‘father’ of one’s own philosophical perspective could act as a significant legitimation of this view and, consequently, could become a weapon in philosophical combat.
    [Show full text]
  • How I Arrived at This Conclusion Introduction
    How I Arrived At This Conclusion Introduction If I have succeeded in persuading my reader of any truth, it must be this above all: that reason is personal in its determinations, from whatever common fund of intellect that it may have bor- rowed its subject matter. Charles Renouvier, How I Arrived at This Conclusion1 ome years ago, while looking over J. Alexander Gunn’s admi- rable study of the development of French philosophy, I was struck by the amount of space the author had devoted to the workS of Charles Renouvier and the high praise he had for him as a man and a philosopher. “Possessed of one of the most powerful minds of the 19th century,” Gunn writes, “Renouvier and Auguste Comte share the highest honors in French philosophy during that century.”2 My interest aroused, I read rapidly through the parts of the book dealing with Renouvier’s writings in such diverse ar- eas as philosophy, science, freedom, progress, ethics and religion. It was in the course of this reading that I came across mention of Renouvier’s philosophical memoir, entitled How I Arrived at This Conclusion. I eventually decided to translate this memoir, which Renouvier regarded as the first of its kind, and offer it for publication as the first of Renouvier’s works to be translated into English. ix x How I Arrived At This Conclusion Charles Renouvier is virtually unknown today in this country. There is evidence that the situation is no different in France, the country of his birth. This is not the place for a thorough examina- tion of why this is the case,3 but I shall attempt to suggest some of the reasons before moving on to the historical circumstances in which Renouvier’s memoir made its appearance.
    [Show full text]
  • The Concept of Virtue and Its Role in Political Life in the Writings of Yves Simon
    THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA The Concept of Virtue and its Role In Political Life in the Writings of Yves Simon A DISSERTATION Submitted to the Faculty of the School of Philosophy Of The Catholic University of America In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree Doctor of Philosophy © Copyright All Rights Reserved By Patrick Lafon Washington, DC. 2013 The Concept of Virtue and its Role In Political Life in the Writings of Yves R. Simon Patrick Lafon Ph.D. Director: Robert S. Sokolowski Yves R. Simon (1903-1961) gives a modern formulation for many classical philosophical concepts such as authority, the common good, and natural law. These topics have received extensive attention from scholars. Simon also discusses the nature of human virtue, moral and intellectual, but this topic has been less studied. Yet the idea of virtue, and in our case virtue in political life, runs through, and is fundamental to any understanding of Simon’s works. Through a close study of Simon’s works and the relevant secondary literature, this dissertation explores Simon’s definition of virtue in order to highlight its originality, and show how he weaves the need for it into the fabric of three facets of political life, namely, the common good, the virtue of the ruler and the ruled, and law. After indicating why modern substitutes for virtue—specifically the recourse to natural spontaneous goodness by Rousseau, Descartes and Emerson, the psycho-technology of Freud, and the social engineering of Charles Fourier—fail, Simon returns to classical sources in order to explain what virtue means and how it relates to politics.
    [Show full text]
  • William James and the Birth of Modern Teaching
    William James and the Birth of Modern Teaching William James and the Birth of Modern Teaching By Edward Vinski William James and the Birth of Modern Teaching By Edward Vinski This book first published 2019 Cambridge Scholars Publishing Lady Stephenson Library, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2PA, UK British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Copyright © 2019 by Edward Vinski All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner. ISBN (10): 1-5275-2122-2 ISBN (13): 978-1-5275-2122-3 TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgements ................................................................................... vii Prologue ...................................................................................................... ix Chapter One ................................................................................................. 1 Early Life and Education Chapter Two .............................................................................................. 17 Harvard 1891 Chapter Three ............................................................................................ 35 The Talks to Teachers Chapter Four .............................................................................................. 59 “Perplexed in the Extreme” Chapter Five .............................................................................................
    [Show full text]