What's in a Name?: “Christian Hedonism”?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

What's in a Name?: “Christian Hedonism”? What’s in a Name?: “Christian Hedonism”? Though he slay me, yet will I trust in him. -Job 13:15a- After these things, the word of the LORD came unto Abram in a vision, saying; Fear not, Abram: I am thy shield, and thy exceeding great reward. -Genesis 15:1- John Piper’s “Christian Hedonism,”1 an increasing influence upon American Evangelical Christianity, demands careful review in light of Holy Scripture, and by comparison with the doctrinal position of Jonathan Edwards (1703-1758), renowned for the timelessness of his biblical/theological leadership. We applaud pastor-scholar-writer Dr. John Piper’s call for biblical study of the concept of pleasure as it relates to the knowledge of God. While hyperbole may have its place, any misrepresentation does not, whether of Immanuel Kant (1724-1804), allegedly at odds with Edwards, or of Jonathan Edwards himself, from whose theology “Christian Hedonism” is allegedly derived. Hedonism To be sure, God cannot deny himself2 by prescribing moral law for which obedience from the heart would not ultimately bring blessing. Yet because of universal human disobedience,3 a cross was interposed which excludes all boasting.4 Hedonism and Theism represent conflicting philosophical positions. Hedonism evokes images of Nero as depicted in the classic motion picture Quo Vadis, F. Scott Fitzgerald’s Great Gatsby, the Kardashian family, and the life of playwright Oscar Wilde. Hedonism, often a product of boredom5, identifies pleasure per se as the primary end or goal of life. As a philosophy, Hedonism has contempt for all boundaries to pleasure.6 “Life is too short to waste by spending it with unpleasant people!” a youth was heard to say. Paradoxically, the greatest pleasure or satisfaction may be subordinating one’s pleasure to the pleasure of others.7 Theism Theism is the philosophical category which includes the Judaeo-Christian world view. The Christian world view is God-centered, that is, theistic, and specifically trinitarian, rather than hedonistic, i.e., pleasure-centered. Biblical Theism both transcends and defines true human pleasure. The Old and New Testaments present the central theistic belief that God is personal, and knowable. Biblical Theism regards the hedonistic urge per se as something that needs to be brought into submission to God and his Word.8 The unchecked hedonistic urge brought catastrophe to Eden, separating all humankind from Eden’s divinely-provided pleasures.9 By God’s infinite grace, however, pleasure can be redeemed, refined, and redefined. Bane and blessing, pain and pleasure, By the cross are sanctified; Joys have I beyond all measure, Joys that through all time abide.10 The Song of Solomon is a paradigm of rapturous progressive pleasure which Christ takes in his redeemed people, the church, as the church yields to him: 1. “My beloved is mine, and I am his” (2:16). 2. “I am my beloved’s, and my beloved is mine” (6:3). 3. “I am my beloved’s, and his desire is towards me” (7:10). Objectivism Trumps Hedonism A friend in Virginia commented, “Jesus began as a carpenter, and later entered the ministry. By the way, was there anything Jesus made that still exists?” This writer asked, “Is there anything that exists that Jesus did not make?” The friend responded,“Now you are getting into metaphysics!” On more than one occasion, Jonathan Edwards, “America’s first philosopher,” 11 defended his own engagement in “metaphysics.” If any should find fault with this reasoning, that it is going a great length into metaphysical niceties and subtilties; I answer, the objection to which they are a reply, is a metaphysical subtilty, and must be treated according to the nature of it. 12 If Edwards, had lived another forty years, he might well have found Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) quite conversant with his own metaphysical perspective. The inimitable Kant, who dominated the eighteenth-century philosophical world,13 depicted morality in the following terms: . although for its application to man morality has need of anthropology, yet, in the first Kant insisted that “there is instance, we must treat it [morality] independently as pure therefore but one categorical philosophy, i.e., as metaphysics, imperative, namely this: Act complete in itself.14 only on that maxim whereby Kant distinguished his Categorical Imperative thou canst at the same time will from hypothetical imperatives which are that it should become a universal based upon prudence with the end of law.” Edwards, no doubt, happiness in view. Since men are not omniscient, Kant reasoned, they cannot would simply have identified guarantee that happiness will result.15 Kant’s “maxim” as the embodiment of the two greatest The categorical imperative would be that which represented an commandments or “the law of action as necessary of itself faith”–that faith, of course, without reference to another end, i.e., as objectively necessary.16 “which worketh through love.” Kant insisted that “there is therefore but one categorical imperative, namely this: Act only on that maxim whereby thou canst at the same time will that it should become a universal law.”17 Edwards, no doubt, would simply have identified Kant’s “maxim” as the embodiment of the two greatest commandments18 or “the law of faith”19–that faith, of course, “which worketh through love.” 20 But it was not merely Kant’s engagement in metaphysics per se in order to establish the Categorical Imperative that would have piqued Edwards’s philosophical prowess, nor the fact that Scripture readily provided a universal maxim in the teaching of Jesus of Nazareth. Rather, it was the fact that Kant, in order to establish ethical objectivity, ruled out the motivation of reward thereby freeing the Imperative from self-interest. For this was precisely what Edwards himself had done in his Treatise on Religious Affections when he stated that the first objective ground of gracious affections is the transcendently excellent and amiable nature of divine things, as they are in and of them selves; and not any conceived relation they bear to self, or self-interest.21 It could seem that Immanuel Kant borrowed from Edwards in setting forth the Categorical Imperative! Clearly Kant’s ruling out “the motivation of reward” “in order to establish ethical objectivity” reflected Edwards’ “first objective ground of gracious affections.” Only in a secondary sense did Edwards Rather, it was the fact that recognize the role of personal pleasure or happiness as a motivating factor in the Christian life. Kant, in order to establish ethical objectivity, ruled out If after a man loves God, it will be a the motivation of reward consequence and fruit of this, that even love to his own happiness will cause him thereby freeing the to desire the glorifying and enjoying of Imperative from self- God; it will not thence follow, that the very exercise of self-love went before his interest. For this was love to God, and that his love to God precisely what Edwards was a consequence and fruit of that. Something else, entirely distinct from himself had done in his self-love, might be the cause of this, viz. Treatise on Religious a change made in the views of his mind, and relish of his heart; whereby he Affections . apprehends a beauty, glory, and supreme good, in God’s nature, as it is in itself. This may be the thing that first draws his heart to him, and causes his heart to be united to him, prior to all considerations of his own self-interest or happiness, although after this, and as a fruit of it, he necessarily seeks his own interest and happiness in God.22 Divine Sovereignty I asked God for strength, that I might achieve; I was made weak, that I might learn humbly to obey. I asked for health, that I might do greater things; I was given infirmity, that I might do better things. I asked for riches, that I might be happy; I was given poverty, that I might be wise. I asked for power, that I might have the praise of men; I was given weakness, that I might feel the need of God. I asked for all things, that I might enjoy life; I was given life, that I might enjoy all things. I got nothing that I asked for–but everything I had hoped for. Almost despite myself, my unspoken prayers were answered. I am among all men, most richly blessed. -Attributed to an anonymous Confederate soldier23 The term “Christian Hedonism,” however provocative, too readily lends itself to the notion that God exists for man’s pleasure rather than the fact that man was created for God’s glory. Thus, it turns things upside down! Those whose affection to God is founded first on his profitableness to them, begin at the wrong end.24 From the moment of his conversion, “Absolute sovereignty” was what Jonathan Edwards loved “to ascribe to God!”25 That is the high water mark of theological objectivism–albeit joyful objectivism. In the case of Saul of Tarsus, his motive was to destroy the church until the instant that God smote him with blindness knocking him from his horse and speaking, “Saul, Saul, why persecutest thou me?”26 Following Saul’s conversion to Christ, God said to Ananias, “I must show him what great things he must suffer for my Name’s sake.”27 This was not Christian “hedonism,” but rather divine sovereignty-- the divine sovereignty associated with Christian Theism. Jonathan Edwards recognized that the system of Christian doctrine which made man most dependent upon God in the matter of salvation was the system that most glorified God!28 That was the theme of his famous Thursday lecture in Boston entitled “God Glorified in Man’s Dependence.” Saul of Tarsus, the paradigm of grace,29 perfectly illustrates this theme.
Recommended publications
  • Tracing Kairos: the Modern Applicability of St. Augustine Kelly D
    Florida State University Libraries Electronic Theses, Treatises and Dissertations The Graduate School 2008 Tracing Kairos: The Modern Applicability of St. Augustine Kelly D. Israel Follow this and additional works at the FSU Digital Library. For more information, please contact [email protected] FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY COLLEGE OF ARTS AND SCIENCES TRACING KAIROS: THE MODERN APPLICABILITY OF ST. AUGUSTINE By KELLY D. ISRAEL A Thesis submitted to the Department of English in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Degree Awarded: Summer Semester, 2008 Copyright © 2008 Kelly D. Israel All Rights Reserved The members of the Committee approve the Thesis of Kelly D. Israel, defended on April 16, 2008. _____________________ Kristie S. Fleckenstein Professor Directing Thesis ____________________ Elaine Treharne Committee Member ____________________ Kathleen Blake Yancey Committee Member Approved: ____________________ R.M. Berry, Chair, English Department The Office of Graduate Studies has verified and approved the above named committee members. ii TABLE OF CONTENTS Abstract v 1. AN IMPOSSIBLE APPLICABILITY 6 2. A RHETORICAL SITUATION ACROSS TIME 14 The Modern Rhetorical Situation 14 A Redefinition 19 Synthesizing the Modern and Medieval: A Rhetorical Situation for All Times 26 Framework of Analysis 27 3. THE RHETORICAL SITUATION OF ON CHRISTIAN DOCTRINE 28 On Christian Doctrine 28 Exigence 30 Audience 33 Constraints 39 Rhetor 40 Ethics 43 Conclusion 45 4. THE RHETORICAL SITUATION OF JESUS AMONG OTHER GODS 46 Jesus Among Other Gods 48 Exigence 49 Audience 51 Constraints 53 Rhetor 55 iii Ethics 55 Conclusion 59 5. DETERMINING AN IMPOSSIBLE APPLICABILITY 60 Exigences 60 Audiences 62 Constraints 63 Rhetors 65 Ethics 65 Conclusions 66 WORKS CITED 68 BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH 71 iv ABSTRACT The purpose of this study is to test the applicability of ancient texts to contemporary concerns.
    [Show full text]
  • St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death
    The University of Akron IdeaExchange@UAkron Williams Honors College, Honors Research The Dr. Gary B. and Pamela S. Williams Honors Projects College Spring 2020 St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death Christopher Choma [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ideaexchange.uakron.edu/honors_research_projects Part of the Christianity Commons, Epistemology Commons, European History Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, History of Religion Commons, Metaphysics Commons, Philosophy of Mind Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Please take a moment to share how this work helps you through this survey. Your feedback will be important as we plan further development of our repository. Recommended Citation Choma, Christopher, "St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death" (2020). Williams Honors College, Honors Research Projects. 1048. https://ideaexchange.uakron.edu/honors_research_projects/1048 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by The Dr. Gary B. and Pamela S. Williams Honors College at IdeaExchange@UAkron, the institutional repository of The University of Akron in Akron, Ohio, USA. It has been accepted for inclusion in Williams Honors College, Honors Research Projects by an authorized administrator of IdeaExchange@UAkron. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. 1 St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death By: Christopher Choma Sponsored by: Dr. Joseph Li Vecchi Readers: Dr. Howard Ducharme Dr. Nathan Blackerby 2 Table of Contents Introduction p. 4 Section One: Three General Views of Human Nature p.
    [Show full text]
  • Ravi Zacharias Interview.Indd
    KNOWING & DOING A Teaching Quarterly for Discipleship of Heart and Mind This article originally appeared in the Summer 2002 issue of Knowing & Doing. C.S. LEWIS INSTITUTE A Conversation with: RAVI ZACHARIAS Reprinted by permission from Decision magazine, March 2002 RECENT EVENTS HAVE FOCUSED A GREAT DEAL OF to raise the dead, a power they do not attribute to ATTENTION ON WORLD RELIGIONS. HOW DO ADHERENTS Mohammed, so that’s a conflicting response. OF OTHER RELIGIONS VIEW CHRISTIANITY? As a Christian apologist, I present a defense of the Christian faith in various settings around the Every culture is basically an expression of its world- globe. I have found that if you build a proper foun- view and its religion. Theologian Paul Tillich said, dation for what the Christian faith is all about, as “Religion is the substance of culture, culture is the you lead up to the cross, the listeners sit in stunned form of religion.”1 In most countries religion has silence. They immediately recognize that Christian- worked itself into the fabric of the culture. There- ity stands in stark contrast to everything that other fore, when people view Christianity, it is inescap- worldviews affirm and assert. They know that true able that they will view it within the framework of power is being expressed in the cross—restraint, their historical experience. mercy, forgiveness—all when the very One who is In India, for example, many people find it impos- offering those things had the capacity to counter sible to separate Christianity from the days of the instead with force and with domination.
    [Show full text]
  • Read Book the Real Face of Atheism Kindle
    THE REAL FACE OF ATHEISM PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Ravi Zacharias | 185 pages | 09 Sep 2004 | Baker Publishing Group | 9780801065118 | English | Ada, MI, United States The Real Face of Atheism PDF Book How does this influence my existence? They discuss the nature of argument and worldview. Zacharia practically states that when there is no objective morality or Moral Law , we mess everything up because we are not able to grasp what is right or wrong without a God telling us what is right or wrong. Average rating 4. Paperback , pages. Shelves: philosophy , christian , apologetics. It falls flat for several reasons not least of which is Euthyphro's dilemma. Living Without God. You would do yourself and your friends a favor by reading this book and passing one on to them. He confidently refutes Harris's claims that God is nothing more than a figment of one's imagination and that Christians regularly practice intolerance and hatred around the globe. Why are we presented with the curious choice between either committing to peculiar concepts about immaterial deities or letting go entirely of a host of consoling, subtle and effective rituals and practices for which there is no equivalent in secular society? In much of the Muslim world, religion is the central foundation upon which family, community, morality, and identity are built. A Reasonable God. In America, and elsewhere, a vigorous dispute between 'intelligent design' and Darwinism is seriously undermining and restricting the teaching of science. If you had infinite knowledge, then you would be the very god that you are saying does not exist.
    [Show full text]
  • Just Thinking
    VOLUME 20.3 I WWW.RZIM.ORG JTHUE MAGS AZINET OF RATVI ZAHCHARIIASN INTERNKATIONIALN MINISG TRIES The Heart of Ap olog etics PAGE 14 + ENGAGING THE HAPPY THINKING PAGAN PAGE 2 IS RELIGION A CRUTCH? PAGE 10 Just Thinking is a teaching resource of Ravi Zacharias International Ministries and exists to engender thoughtful engagement with apologetics, Scripture, and the whole of life. Danielle DuRant Editor Ravi Zacharias International Ministries 4725 Peachtree Corners Circle Suite 250 Norcross, Georgia 30092 770.449.6766 WWW.RZIM.ORG HELPING THE THINKER BELIEVE. HELPING THE BELIEVER THINK. TABLE of CONTENTS VOLUME 20.3 2 Engaging the Happy 14 The Heart of Apologetics Thinking Pagan As Alister McGrath points out in his What does it mean when people book Mere Apologetics , apologetics are content with life without is not a set of techniques for winning bothering about the question of God? people to Christ or a set of argumen - Recently Ravi Zacharias sat down tative templates designed to win with Danielle DuRant to discuss the debates. Rather, it is a willingness idea of the “happy thinking pagan.” to work with God in helping people discover and turn to his glory. We are to “follow Him” by casting our 10 Is Religion a Crutch? nets out to everyone and pointing Believers are often caricatured as them to the greater reality of God being weak and naïve—the kind and the risen Christ. of people who need their faith as a crutch just to get them through life. But as Simon Wenham notes, the 26 Think Again truth of the matter is that Jesus never offered a crutch, only a cross.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 in the UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT for the NORTHERN DISTRICT of GEORGIA ATLANTA DIVISION COMPLAINT Plaintiffs Derek Carrier A
    Case 1:21-cv-03161-TWT Document 1 Filed 08/04/21 Page 1 of 30 IN THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT FOR THE NORTHERN DISTRICT OF GEORGIA ATLANTA DIVISION DEREK CARRIER and DORA Case No.: CARRIER, individually, and on behalf of all others similarly situated; CLASS ACTION COMPLAINT Plaintiffs, DEMAND FOR JURY TRIAL vs. RAVI ZACHARIAS INTERNATIONAL MINISTRIES, INC., a 501(c)(3) Corporation; RZIM PRODUCTIONS, INC., a Georgia Non-Profit Corporation; MARGARET ZACHARIAS, in her Capacity as ADMINISTRATOR OF THE ESTATE OF RAVI KUMAR ZACHARIAS, Defendants. COMPLAINT Plaintiffs Derek Carrier and Dora Carrier (“Plaintiffs”), on their own behalf and on behalf of all others similarly situated (“Class Members”), bring this class action against Ravi Zacharias International Ministries, Inc., RZIM Productions, Inc. (together, “RZIM”), and Margaret Zacharias, in her capacity as the Administrator of the Estate of Ravi Kumar Zacharias (“Estate”) (collectively 1 Case 1:21-cv-03161-TWT Document 1 Filed 08/04/21 Page 2 of 30 “Defendants”) and complain and allege the following upon personal knowledge as to their own experiences, and based upon on information and belief as to other matters: INTRODUCTION 1. This is a class action lawsuit brought against Defendants by Plaintiffs on behalf of themselves and similarly situated donors and consumers who donated funds to Defendants to support Defendants’ Christian apologetic ministry, outreach, training, and other programming. 2. Since at least 2004, RZIM, led by Zacharias, has deceived faithful Christians, soliciting their financial support for its purported mission of Christian evangelism, apologetic defense of Christianity, and humanitarian efforts. Defendants bilked tens—if not hundreds—of millions of dollars from well- meaning donors who believed RZIM and Zacharias to be faith-filled Christian leaders.
    [Show full text]
  • The End of Reason Copyright © 2008 by Ravi Zacharias Requests for Information Should Be Addressed To: Zondervan, Grand Rapids, Michigan 49530
    The End of Reason Copyright © 2008 by Ravi Zacharias Requests for information should be addressed to: Zondervan, Grand Rapids, Michigan 49530 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Zacharias, Ravi K. The end of reason : a response to the new atheists / Ravi Zacharias. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-310-28251-8 (hardcover) 1. Apologetics. 2. Chris tian ity and atheism. I. Title. BT1103. Z34 2008 239'.7 — dc22 2007039358 All Scripture quotations, unless otherwise indicated, are taken from the Holy Bible: New International Version®. NIV®. Copyright © 1973, 1978, 1984 by International Bible Society. Used by permission of Zondervan. All rights reserved. Internet addresses printed in this book are offered as a resource to you. These are not intended in any way to be or imply an endorsement on the part of Zondervan, nor do we vouch for the content of these sites for the life of this book. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means — elec- tronic, mechanical, photocopy, recording, or any other — except for brief quotations in printed reviews, without the prior permission of the publisher. Published in association with the literary agency of Wolgemuth and Asso- ciates, Inc. Interior design by Beth Shagene Printed in the United States of America 08 09 10 11 12 13 • 19 18 17 16 15 14 13 12 11 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 0310282519_endreason_hc.indd 4 1/31/08 1:31:29 PM CONTENTS Foreword / 7 Prologue / 13 The End of Reason / 21 Notes / 129 Subject Index / 137 0310282519_endreason_hc.indd 5 1/31/08 1:31:29 PM FOREWORD hortly after Sam Harris published his first poi- Sson pen letter against religion, The End of Faith, I invited him to debate a Chris tian on my televi- sion show.
    [Show full text]
  • March, 12. Utilitarianism 1. Ethical Utilitarianism = Consequentialism + Utilitarianism + Hedonism + Social Principle Consequent
    March, 12. Utilitarianism 1. Ethical utilitarianism = consequentialism + utilitarianism + hedonism + social principle Consequentialism: whether an act is morally right depends only on consequences (as opposed to the circumstances or the intrinsic nature of the act or anything that happens before the act). Utilitarianism: whether an consequence is valuable depends only on its utility Hedonic principle: a pleasure is the only value; whether an act is useful depends on its connection with pleasure (happiness consists in pleasures) Social principle: we must consider whether our action produces “social” happiness (not only happiness of some individuals) Utilitarianism (consequentialism) versus deontologism Deontologism: whether an act is morally good depends on its internal qualities (intention, purpose, compatibility with duty and obligation, compatibility with values) “Classic utilitarianism is consequentialist as opposed to deontological because of what it denies. It denies that moral rightness depends directly on anything other than consequences, such as whether the agent promised in the past to do the act now. Of course, the fact that the agent promised to do the act might indirectly affect the act's consequences if breaking the promise will make other people unhappy. Nonetheless, according to classic utilitarianism, what makes it morally wrong to break the promise is its future effects on those other people rather than the fact that the agent promised in the past.” SEP (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consequentialism) „Actual Consequentialism = whether an act is morally right depends only on the actual consequences (as opposed to foreseen, foreseeable, intended, or likely consequences). Direct Consequentialism = whether an act is morally right depends only on the consequences of that act itself (as opposed to the consequences of the agent's motive, of a rule or practice that covers other acts of the same kind, and so on).
    [Show full text]
  • The Legacy of Sovereign
    LegacySovereignJoy.48134.int.qxd 9/21/07 10:01 AM Page 1 T HE L EGACY OF S OVEREIGN J OY LegacySovereignJoy.48134.int.qxd 9/21/07 10:01 AM Page 2 OTHER BOOKS BY THE AUTHOR The Justification of God: An Exegetical and Theological Study of Romans 9:1–23 2nd Edition (Baker Book House, 1993, orig. 1983) The Supremacy of God in Preaching (Baker Book House, 1990) The Pleasures of God: Meditations on God’s Delight in Being God (Multnomah Press, 1991) Recovering Biblical Manhood and Womanhood: A Response to Evangelical Feminism (edited with Wayne Grudem, Crossway Books, 1991) What’s the Difference? Manhood and Womanhood Defined According to the Bible (Crossway Books, 1991) Let the Nations Be Glad: The Supremacy of God in Missions (Baker Book House, 1993) The Purifying Power of Living by Faith in Future Grace (Multnomah Press, 1995) Desiring God: Meditations of a Christian Hedonist (Multnomah Press, revised 1996) A Hunger for God: Desiring God through Fasting and Prayer (Crossway Books, 1997) A Godward Life: Savoring the Supremacy of God in All of Life (Multnomah Press, 1997) God’s Passion for His Glory: Living the Vision of Jonathan Edwards (Crossway Books, 1998) The Innkeeper (Crossway Books, 1998) A Godward Life, Book Two: Savoring the Supremacy of God in All of Life (Multnomah Press, 1999) LegacySovereignJoy.48134.int.qxd 9/21/07 10:01 AM Page 3 s a r e n a n o t w s s i l e e n h t t BOOK ONE LegTHEacy of Sovereign Joy God’s Triumphant Grace in the Lives of Augustine, Luther, and Calvin J OHN P IPER CROSSWAY BOOKS A PUBLISHING MINISTRY OF GOOD NEWS PUBLISHERS WHEAT O N , ILLINO IS LegacySovereignJoy.48134.int.qxd 9/21/07 10:01 AM Page 4 The Legacy of Sovereign Joy Copyright © 2000 by John Piper Published by Crossway Books a publishing ministry of Good News Publishers 1300 Crescent Street Wheaton, Illinois 60187 All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • The Existence of God in an Age of Reason Page 1 of 6 © 2011 by Craig B
    Christian Apologetics Study Series: Lesson #2 (Student key) Additional Notes The Existence of God In an Age of Reason by Craig B. Esvelt, D.Min Introduction: North America, once considered Christian not only by itself but by other nations around the world, can no longer make that claim. So far "It is extremely dangerous in the presence have we moved from our Judeo-Christian moorings that in the 1960's a of God to discuss His existence." - Soren number of philosophers and liberal theologians popularized a "God is dead" Kierkegaard movement, the culmination of a spiritual repression which found impetus a century earlier in the writings of Friedrich Nietzsche, who provided atheism with a philosophical basis, and Charles Darwin, who offered a scientific rationale. Today atheism is implicitly taught throughout our public school systems because public education, in its attempt at being pluralistically "neutral" (an impossible task!), ignores God altogether. So God has become "dead" to most recent generations, not through atheistic propaganda but because of a perceived irrelevance to all academic disciplines--a vanishing character like the fading smile of Alice In Wonderland's Cheshire cat. Added to that has been a more aggressive and vindictive expression of atheism in recent years, in part, a backlash of the 911 terrorist attacks where religion in general and Christianity in particular were tarred along with religious extremism and held up as an oppressive threat to human welfare and social progress. How can a believer respond to such an assault on faith? The Human Dilemma Before proceeding further, it would be wise to note some biblical presuppositions that have a bearing on understanding why there is so much controversy over the issue of belief in God.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant and the Role of Pleasure in Moral Action
    Morrisson.1-25 7/11/08 9:02 AM Page 1 INTRODUCTION ............................... methodology and two kinds of ethics Kant’s theory of moral motivation is notoriously controversial. Indeed, few areas of Kant scholarship have drawn as much attention or prompted as much disagreement. Kant himself was so confounded by the issue of how the moral law can provide an incentive that moves the will to action that he refers to this problem as the “philosophers’ stone” (LE 27:1428). Unfortunately, Kant’s perplexity ultimately translates into an unusually elusive theory of moral motivation. As a result, the list of scholars who have presented divergent, often mutually exclusive interpre- tations of Kant’s account of moral motivation is long and distinguished.1 In this study, I want to contribute to the debate over how Kant thinks we are moved to act morally by approaching the issue in a new and, I argue, wholly enlightening way. The problem that is perhaps central to this debate is as follows: how can Kant account for moral motivation while divorcing the basis of morality from the pathological, and therefore motivational, side of human agents?2 To put this pivotal question another way: if Kant thinks that morality is not grounded in our sensuous and affective natures (as the British moral sense theorists suggest), then how does he think we are moved by moral considerations at all? Kant (notoriously) introduces the concept of respect (Achtung) as an answer to this question. On the face of it, his solution seems to be that respect is a moral feeling, and, as such, bridges the gap between the moral law and the capacity of hu- mans—as sensuously affected beings—to be motivated.
    [Show full text]
  • 6. Railton's “Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality”
    6. Railton’s “Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality” Martín Abreu Zavaleta July 14, 2015 Railton is addressing one kind of problem that we raised. In class, we discussed the case of a parent who is offered a choice between saving the life of her own child or saving the life of another child. Saving the life of the other child would produce overall more utility than saving the life of her own, so utilitarian consequentialism claims that she should save the life of the other child. To many people, this seems to be the wrong result: surely, they think, whatever duty she has to save the life of the other child is overridden by her duties and obligations to save the life of her own child. Samuel Scheffler presents us with a less tragic, but related problem for consequentialism. Schef- fler observes that consequentialism demands that we don’t buy new shoes if we can spend that money in ways that will help other people more, or that we don’t watch TV if instead we could be doing more utility maximizing things. These two cases point to one important problem for consequentialism (here, under the guise of utilitarianism). Consequentialism seems to alienate us from the people we love and from things that make our lives richer. By focusing solely on the maximization of utility, it seems to ignore the value that other things bring into our lives: things like friendship, the love for one’s family, entertainment, art appreciation, etc. A life lived in line with consequentialist demands seems to be a very impoverished life, enslaved to the maximization of utility.
    [Show full text]