An Account of Power and Possibility in Spinoza

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

An Account of Power and Possibility in Spinoza An Account of Power and Possibility in Spinoza Galen Barry Charlottesville, VA B.A. Philosophy, Oregon State University M.A. Philosophy, University of Virginia A Dissertation presented to the Graduate Faculty of the University of Virginia in Candidacy for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Virginia March, 2015 Acknowledgments I would like to thank my advisor, Antonia LoLordo, for her willingness to take me on as an advisee, as well as for her consistently prompt and frank advice. I would also like to thank Walter Ott, a co-advisor of sorts, for his sincere encouragement and for his careful readings of my chapter drafts. Thanks are also due to Dan Devereux and Asher Biemann for serving on my committee. I am grateful for my partner, McCailin Wunder, for her constant support and patience, and for my parents, Steven Barry and Kathleen McAuliffe, for the freedom they gave me to study philosophy and for the pride they always showed in me. Finally, I would like to thank my undergraduate professor, Joseph Orosco, for writing me a letter of recommendation seven years ago in exchange for this acknowledgment. 2 Table of Contents Introduction………..……………………………………………………………………………..5 Abbreviations ...………………………………………………………………………………...13 Chapter One: Spinoza’s Theory of Possibility………………………………………………...14 1.1 Error Theory……………………………………………………………………….....16 1.2 Dispositionalism……………………………………………………………………...20 1.3 Projection in Sensation……………………………………………………………….23 1.3.1 The Falsity Condition………………………………………………....……25 1.3.2 The Category Mistake Condition…………………………………………...27 1.3.3 The Phenomenology Condition…………………………………………….30 1.4 The Projection of Possibility………………………………….………………………34 1.4.1 The Falsity Condition………………………………………………………35 1.4.2 The Phenomenology Condition…………………………………………….36 1.4.3 The Category Mistake Condition……………………………….…………..41 1.5 Necessitarianism and Projectivism…………………………………………………...43 Bibliography …………....………………………………………………………………..45 Chapter Two: Spinoza on Modal Reasoning…………………………………………………..48 2.1 Examples from the Ethics…………………………………………………………….51 2.2 Initial Accounts…………………………………………………………… ……....…53 2.2.1 The Following-From Account……………………………………………...55 2.2.2. Per Se Accounts……………………………………………………………57 2.3 A Linguistic Account of Impossibility……………………………………………….62 2.3.1 The Phenomenon of Feigning………………………………………………62 2.3.2 The Linguistic Account of Impossibility…………………………………...64 2.3.3 The Context-Sensitivity of Philosophical Terms…………………………. 68 2.4 The Role of Definitions………………………………………………………………71 2.5 Conclusion……………………………………………………………………………77 Bibliography…………………………………………………………………………….. 80 Chapter Three: Spinoza’s Concept of Power………………………………………………… 82 3.1 The Meaning of Power……………………………………………………………….83 3.1.1 Obscurity……………………....…………………………………………...84 3.1.2 Stipulation……………………………. ...……………………... ………….85 3.2 The Causal Interpretation…………………………………………………………….87 3.3 A Dilemma for the Dynamicist Interpretation…………….. ..……………………….91 3.4 Arguments against the Conceptualist…………………………………………………94 3.4.1 The First Argument………………………………………………………...95 3.4.2 The Second Argument……………………………………………………...98 3.4.3 The Third Argument………………………………………………………102 3.5 Desiderata of a Theory of Power……………………………………………………103 Bibliography……………………………………………………………………… ……108 3 Chapter Four: Perfection in Spinoza’s Argument for Monism……………………………..111 4.1 The Power to Exist…………………………………….....………………………….113 4.2 The Principle of Perfection………………………………………………………….120 4.2.1 The Missing Premise…………………………………………………….. .122 4.3 God’s Greater Perfection……………………………………………………………128 4.3.1 Letter 36………………………………………………………………… ..129 4.3.2 Human Perfection…………………………………………………………130 4.3.3 Ethics 1p16………………………………………………………………..134 4.4 Two Competing Accounts…………………………………………………………..136 4.4.1 Garrett’s Argument………………………………………………………..137 4.4.2 Carriero’s Argument………………………………………………………138 4.5 Conclusion…………………………………………………………………………..140 Bibliography……………………………………………………………………… ……141 Chapter Five: The Problem of Diversity……………………………………………………..143 5.1 Three Problems……………………………………………………………………...145 5.1.1 Diversity and Possibility…………………………………………………..148 5.1.2 Diversity and Motion……………………………………………………...152 5.2 How God Grounds Possibility………………………………………………………154 5.3 God and the Cause of Motion……………………………………………………….160 5.3.1 More’s Argument…………………………………………………………160 5.3.2 Clarke’s Argument……. ..……………………………………….. .……..162 5.4 Conclusion…………………………………………………………………………..165 Bibliography…………………………………………………... ………………………166 Chapter Six: Spinoza’s Solution to the Problem of Diversity………………………………169 6.1 God and Power……………………………………………………………………...170 6.1.1 Ethics 1p34………………………………………………………………..170 6.1.2 Attributes and Power……………………………………………………...173 6.2 Power and the Origin of Motion…………………………………………………….179 6.3 God and Possibility………………………………………………………………….182 6.3.1 Space…………………………………………………… ... ……………...183 6.3.2 Shape and Color………………... .………………………………………..185 6.4 Spinoza and Mechanism…………………………………………………………….188 6.5 God and Diversity………………………………………………….………………..190 6.5.1 The Role of Numbers……………………………………………………..191 6.5.2 God and Number………………………………………………………….193 Bibliography……………………………………….. ..…………………………………198 Conclusion……………………………. ...……………………………………………………..201 The Nature of Necessity………………………………………………………………...201 The General Problem of Error…………………………………………………………..204 The Nature of Inherence………………………………………………………………...205 Bibliography………………………………………… …………………………………207 4 Introduction One of Spinoza’s most famous theses is his necessitarianism. It claims that nothing—nothing— could have been otherwise than it actually is. God’s existence, the laws of physics, my decision to eat cereal this morning—it’s all as necessary as 2+2=4. Necessitarianism lends itself quite well to Spinoza’s rationalism. In its broadest aspirations, rationalism, as I use the term, is an attempt to explain everything. If something exists, there is a reason explaining why it exists. If a relation that holds, there is a reason explaining why it holds. Similarly for things that don’t exist and for relations that don’t hold—there are reasons for that too. If necessitarianism is true, then everything is sufficiently explained by its cause. Things exist because they were caused to exist and relations hold because they were caused to hold. So necessitarianism goes hand in hand with Spinoza’s rationalism. If there were any contingent or brute facts, then they would count as unexplained. In addition to cohering well with Spinoza’s general philosophical outlook, necessitarianism also provides his system with many benefits. Perhaps most importantly, it constitutes the backbone of his theory of well-being: we can gain control over our passions and reach beatitude only through a recognition of the necessity of all things. Necessitarianism faces a number of problems, however. Most famously, it seems to leave no room for traditional moral concepts like praise and blame. We blame people for immoral acts primarily because we think that they could have, and should have, done otherwise. If every action is necessary, then nobody could have done otherwise than she actually did and nobody is blameworthy. So necessitarianism cannot help but undermine traditional morality. But it also faces a number of problems unrelated to morality. First, it just seems false. For example, it seems fairly obvious that I might have had toast this morning rather than cereal. After all, I remember 5 deliberating about the choice and I didn’t feel compelled either way. Nothing about the way I woke up or the happenings of the previous night spoke in favor of any particular breakfast. Necessitarianism seems to leave this general feeling of contingency unexplained. Second, the concept of possibility plays an important, and plausibly indispensable, role in philosophical argumentation. Among other things, it undergirds the practice of using hypothetical cases as philosophical evidence. If nothing is merely possible, as necessitarianism claims, then it’s not obvious that there are any hypothetical cases. There are only actual cases. And if we cannot help ourselves to hypothetical cases, then the ways we can argue shrink considerably. The benefits of necessitarianism seem to come at a very high cost. My dissertation is an examination of several key issues pertaining to Spinoza’s necessitarianism. In the first two chapters, I aim to defend Spinoza against the two non-moral objections to necessitarianism mentioned above. First, I will offer an interpretation of his theory of possibility which aims to explain why so much of the world seems—in a robust sense—to be contingent. Things appear contingent to us because of the tendency of the mind to project its own features onto the world (in this case, its ignorance of causes). Second, I will argue that Spinoza’s necessitarianism can accommodate the use of hypothetical cases. It does so by construing hypothetical cases not as genuine possibilities, but as actually existing linguistic entities such as sentences. For the remainder of the dissertation, I will focus on a particularly important use of hypothetical cases that appears in one of Spinoza’s arguments for God’s existence. There Spinoza argues that God exists because God is more powerful than any other substance or substances would be, if they existed. I focus on this argument not merely as an illustration of Spinoza’s use of hypothetical cases. Rather, the concept of power is a concept traditionally tied to the concept of 6 possibility: a thing’s power tells
Recommended publications
  • Expressions of Mind/Body Dualism in Thinspiration
    MIND OVER MATTER: EXPRESSIONS OF MIND/BODY DUALISM IN THINSPIRATION Annamarie O’Brien A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate College of Bowling Green State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS August 2013 Committee: Dr. Marilyn Motz, Advisor Dr. Rebecca Kinney Dr. Jeremy Wallach © 2013 Annamarie O’Brien All Rights Reserved iii ABSTRACT Dr. Marilyn Motz, Advisor Thinspiration images, meant to inspire weight-loss, proliferate online through platforms that encourage the circulation of user-generated content. Despite numerous alarmist critiques in mass media about thinspiration and various academic studies investigating ‘pro-anorexia’ sites, surprisingly little attention has been given to the processes of creation and the symbolic potential of thinspiration. This thesis analyzes the formal hybridity of thinspiration, and its use as an expressive medium. The particularities of thinspiration (including its visual characteristics, creative processes, and exhibition) may be considered carefully constructed instances of self- representation, hinging on the expression of beliefs regarding the mind and body. While these beliefs are deeply entrenched in popular body management discourse, they also tend to rely on traditional dualist ideologies. Rather than simply emphasizing slenderness or reiterating standard assumptions about beauty, thinspiration often evokes pain and sadness, and employs truisms about the transcendence of flesh and rebellion against social constraints. By harnessing individualist discourse and the values of mind/body dualism, thinspiration becomes a space in which people struggling with disordered eating and body image issues may cast themselves as active agents—contrary to the image of eating disorders proffered by popular and medical discourse. iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS First, I would like to thank my thesis committee chair, Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • University of Groningen Spinoza's Theory of the Human Mind
    University of Groningen Spinoza’s Theory of the Human Mind: Consciousness, Memory, and Reason Marrama, Oberto IMPORTANT NOTE: You are advised to consult the publisher's version (publisher's PDF) if you wish to cite from it. Please check the document version below. Document Version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Publication date: 2019 Link to publication in University of Groningen/UMCG research database Citation for published version (APA): Marrama, O. (2019). Spinoza’s Theory of the Human Mind: Consciousness, Memory, and Reason. University of Groningen. Copyright Other than for strictly personal use, it is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). Take-down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Downloaded from the University of Groningen/UMCG research database (Pure): http://www.rug.nl/research/portal. For technical reasons the number of authors shown on this cover page is limited to 10 maximum. Download date: 27-09-2021 SPINOZA’S THEORY OF THE HUMAN MIND: CONSCIOUSNESS, MEMORY, AND REASON 1A_BW_Marrama .job © Oberto Marrama, 2019. All rights reserved. ISBN 978-94-034-1568-0 (printed version) ISBN 978-94-034-1569-7 (electronic version) 1B_BW_Marrama .job Spinoza’s Theory of the Human Mind: Consciousness, Memory, and Reason PhD thesis to obtain the degree of PhD at the University of Groningen on the authority of the Rector Magnificus Prof.
    [Show full text]
  • Descartes and Spinoza
    OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Thu Dec 29 2016, NEWGEN 229 chapter nine Descartes and Spinoza Two Approaches to Embodiment Alison Peterman 1. Introduction Descartes1 (1596– 1650) and Spinoza (1632– 1677) each gave us interest- ing and infuential approaches to answering what I’ll call “embodiment question”: what is the relationship between a mind and its body— the one that it seems to inhabit, feel, control or otherwise be uniquely involved with?2 In Spinoza we fnd (at least) three diferent answers, the ingenuity of all of which is attested to by their long reception in the philosophical tradition. Descartes was an important infuence on Spinoza, but on many others, too, ushering in the era of the “mind- body 1 I am grateful to Colin Chamberlain, Michael Della Rocca, Keota Fields, Kristin Primus, and Alison Simmons for discussion, and also to the other contributors to this volume. 2 Tis question is broader than one than one about the constitutive or essential relationship between a mind and its body. 229 02_acprof-9780190490447_Ch7-11.indd 229 12/29/2016 2:13:15 AM OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Thu Dec 29 2016, NEWGEN 230 230 Embodiment problem” in the form that many philosophers still grapple with. Here, I’ll by no means attempt a comprehensive treatment of their contribu- tions. Instead I will try to uncover an unnoticed similarity between the two, and apply it to understanding the coherence of Spinoza’s account of embodiment. I’ll argue that Descartes and Spinoza both approach the embodiment question in two diferent ways: one approach starts with some metaphysical commitments about the kinds of entities, properties, and interactions there are in the world, and the other starts by attending to the experience of an embodied subject.
    [Show full text]
  • Of Gods and Kings: Natural Philosophy and Politics in the Leibniz-Clarke Disputes Steven Shapin Isis, Vol. 72, No. 2. (Jun., 1981), Pp
    Of Gods and Kings: Natural Philosophy and Politics in the Leibniz-Clarke Disputes Steven Shapin Isis, Vol. 72, No. 2. (Jun., 1981), pp. 187-215. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-1753%28198106%2972%3A2%3C187%3AOGAKNP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-C Isis is currently published by The University of Chicago Press. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/ucpress.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Mon Aug 20 10:29:37 2007 Of Gods and Kings: Natural Philosophy and Politics in the Leibniz-Clarke Disputes By Steven Shapin* FTER TWO AND A HALF CENTURIES the Newton-Leibniz disputes A continue to inflame the passions.
    [Show full text]
  • Caroline, Leibniz, and Clarke Author(S): D. Bertoloni Meli Source: Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol
    Caroline, Leibniz, and Clarke Author(s): D. Bertoloni Meli Source: Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. 60, No. 3 (Jul., 1999), pp. 469-486 Published by: University of Pennsylvania Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3654014 . Accessed: 22/02/2011 14:57 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at . http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=upenn. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. University of Pennsylvania Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of the History of Ideas. http://www.jstor.org Caroline, Leibniz, and Clarke D. Bertoloni Meli The papers which passed between Leibniz and Clarke from 1715 to 1716 have long been considered classics in the history of science and philosophy, attractinga largenumber of scholarlyworks.
    [Show full text]
  • University of Pennsylvania Press
    University of Pennsylvania Press Newtonian Science, Miracles, and the Laws of Nature Author(s): Peter Harrison Source: Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. 56, No. 4 (Oct., 1995), pp. 531-553 Published by: University of Pennsylvania Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2709991 Accessed: 30-10-2015 01:34 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. University of Pennsylvania Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of the History of Ideas. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 130.102.42.98 on Fri, 30 Oct 2015 01:34:15 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions NewtonianScience, Miracles, andthe Laws ofNature PeterHarrison Introduction "Newton,"writes Richard Westfall, "both believed in and did not believe in miracles."It can onlybe concluded,Westfall continues, that the greatscientist, unwilling to relinquishhis beliefin a providentialand inter- posingDeity, "abandoned himself to ambiguitiesand inconsistencies,which gave theappearance of divine participation in nature,but not the substance."' Newton'sapparent ambivalence
    [Show full text]
  • Idealism: Problematic, Visionary, Critical
    Kant | Prolegomena 11 Idealism: problematic, visionary, critical There are many passages in the Prolegomena where Kant distances himself from a particular variety of idealism (e.g., Notes II and III, §32, Appendix), even though he is explicitly defending a version of idealism himself. In broadest outline, realism is the view that things in the external world are independent of human cogition; their nature and existence is unrelated to us. (This is how Kant charcterises ‘transcendental realism’ in CPR A368–9.) In contrast, idealism is the view that reality is mind-dependent or mind-correlative. An onto- logical reading suggests that there are no mind-independent things, that there is no ‘ready-made’ world out there; or it is the view that the external world exists only as an object of the mind. But it can also be the view that the fundamental entities are ideas (as opposed to matter), and thus something that is essentially mental or non-material. This is Berkeley’s ‘dogmatic’ idealism (cf. the sheet with extracts). An epistemic reading suggests that what we can know about reality is largely due to our cognitive faculties, and hence our grasp of reality is shaped not by the things themselves, but by the way in which we cognise that reality. This is Kant’s ideal- ism, which thus by no means rejects the claim that there is a world out there, for it plays a role in making possible experience as we have it. But we lack epistemic access to it: we do not have insight into ‘the inner [das Innere, roughly, the intrinsic nature] of things’ (CPR A277/B333), regardless of our cognition of them.
    [Show full text]
  • The Leibnizian-Newtonian Debates: Natural Philosophy and Social Psychology
    The British Society for the History of Science !"#$%#&'(&)&*(+,#-./(&*($0#'*.#12$,*.34*5$6"&5/1/7"8$*(9$:/;&*5$618;"/5/<8 =3."/4>1?2$@*4/58($A5.&1 :/34;#2$!"#$B4&.&1"$C/34(*5$D/4$."#$E&1./48$/D$:;&#(;#F$G/5H$IF$,/H$J$>0#;HF$KLMN?F$77H$NJN+NMM 63'5&1"#9$'82$@*O'4&9<#$P(&Q#41&.8$64#11$/($'#"*5D$/D$!"#$B4&.&1"$:/;&#.8$D/4$."#$E&1./48 /D$:;&#(;# :.*'5#$PR%2$http://www.jstor.org/stable/4025501 =;;#11#92$KSTUITVUKU$VV2WS Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cup. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is a Mode Account of Collective Intentionality? Michael Schmitz
    What is a mode account of collective intentionality? Michael Schmitz (Penultimate draft; final version published in Gerhard Preyer & Georg Peter (eds.), Social Ontology and Collective Intentionality: Critical Essays on the Philosophy of Raimo Tuomela with his Responses; Springer 2017, pp. 37-70; please refer to the published version.) 1. Mode vs. content and subject approaches to collective intentionality Many attempts to understand collective intentionality have tried to steer between two extremes. We want to understand how the members of a group are bound together, what turns them into a group, so we don’t want to think of the group as a mere sum of individuals. At the same time, we don’t want the group to be free-floating with regard to the members. It should not come out as just another individual, as an additional person as it were, nor should it be emergent in a radical sense. It’s useful to distinguish attempts to accomplish this balancing act in terms of where they solely or predominantly locate collectivity: in the content of relevant intentional states (or speech acts), in their mode, or in their subject(s) (Schweikard and Schmid 2012). A content approach tries to understand collectivity in terms of the contents of the subjects’ intentionality, where content is understood in the standard fashion, namely as what the subjects believe, intend, hope, feel, and so on. So on this kind of view, collectivity is just a matter of certain kinds of things that individuals believe, intend, and feel with regard to each other. On this perspective, the best- known representative of which is Michael Bratman (1992; 2014), there may be a ‘we’ of joint action as represented in the content of intentions, but these intentions are always of the form ‘I intend that we J’, so that no collective ‘we’-subject of intentional states is represented.1 Now, this kind of approach is in danger of erring on the side of being too individualistic.
    [Show full text]
  • Levels of Discourse in Leibniz's Metaphysics the Ontological Status of Bodies
    Levels of Discourse in Leibniz's Metaphysics The Ontological Status of Bodies: A Study of the Levels of Discourse in Leibniz's Metaphysics By SCOTT STAPLEFORD, B.A. A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts McMaster University C> Copyright by Scott Stapleford, August 1998 MASTER OF ARTS (1998) McMaster University (Philosophy) Hamilton, Ontario TITLE: The Ontological Status of Bodies: A Study of the Levels of Discourse in Leibniz's Metaphysics AUTHOR: Scott Stapleford, B.A. (Brock University) SUPERVISOR: Professor Wilfrid Waluchow NUMBER OF PAGES: iv, 169 ii Table of Contents Introduction 1 The Problem 2 Collateral Issues 3 Procedure Part I 4 Some Working Deftnitions 5 Phenomenalism 5.1 Linguistic Phenomenalism 5.2 Berkeleian Phenomenalism 6 Leibniz and Phenomenalism 6.1 Macintosh's Interpretation 6.2 Jolley's Interpretation 6.3 Wilson's Interpretation 111 Part II 7 Recapitulation and Procedure 8 Athenian and Darwinian Approaches 8.1 Woolhouse's Interpretation 8.2 Adams' Interpretation 8.3 Hartz's Interpretation 8.4 Loeb's Interpretation 8.5 Rutherford's Interpretation 9 Psychology and Ontology 9.1 Mind and Matter in Descartes and Locke 9.2 Leibniz's Analysis of Mind and Matter 9.2.1 The Primary-Secondary Quality Distinction 9.2.2 Physical Considerations 9.2.3 Metaphysical Considerations 9.2.3.1 Substance as Unity 9.2.3.2 Substance as Activity 9.2.3.3 Substance as Subject 9.2.4 Psychological Considerations 10 Levels of Discourse 11 Leibniz's Epistemological Realism 11.1 Requirements of the System 11.2 The Contrary Proposition 11.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Mind
    Part Two Philosophy of Mind 9781350067301_txt_prf.indd 179 21-08-2018 11:42:33 9781350067301_txt_prf.indd 180 21-08-2018 11:42:33 6 Spinoza’s Two Claims about the Mind-Body Relation Alison Peterman Introduction How is a particular mind related to its body?1 There are many ways to understand this question, and many different answers for those different ways. Spinoza makes a number of claims about this relationship, all of which are independently interesting. But it is not clear that they are compatible. In this chapter, I would like to focus on two of those claims, and to argue that although Spinoza sometimes run these two claims together, in fact he does not succeed in making them compatible with one another. I suggest that the illusion that they are compatible comes from an equivocation between two ways of using the phrase “insofar as” [quatenus], and that this type of equivocation runs deep in Spinoza’s metaphysics. Those two claims are: (1) Parallelism: the mind is causally and structurally linked to other minds in the same way that its body is linked to other bodies; (2) Idea-of: the mind is the idea of its body; or, the body is the object [objectum] of its mind. In focusing on these two, I will ignore some of those other interesting things that Spinoza writes about the mind-body relationship. For example, I will for the most part ignore his account of it in the earlier Short Treatise, where he claims that love constitutes the union of the mind with the body.2 But I will also ignore another of Spinoza’s commitments that might look more relevant: that the mind and the body are “one and the same thing, understood in two different ways” (E2p7s).
    [Show full text]
  • Evaluating the Metaphysical Realism of Étienne Gilson
    Studia Gilsoniana 4:4 (October–December 2015): 363–380 | ISSN 2300–0066 Brian Kemple Center for Thomistic Studies University of St. Thomas, Houston Texas, USA EVALUATING THE METAPHYSICAL REALISM OF ÉTIENNE GILSON It is true to say that there would likely be far fewer students of Thomas Aquinas in North America today if not for the work of Étienne Gilson; it is equally true to say that Gilson’s work has made significant contributions both to the overcoming of modern philosophy and to the understanding of Thomas himself, particularly as regards the Angelic Doc- tor’s metaphysics and philosophy of knowledge. The resurgence of genu- ine Thomism—as opposed to the Suarezian impostor which had come to dominate—which followed Leo XIII’s Aeterni Patris had much to over- come, not the least of which was the preponderance of modernity’s idealist epistemology. Descartes’ mathematicism, the insistence that all things lacking the certitude of mathematics cannot truly be called “knowledge,”1 begot Cartesian idealism, which in turn launched a centuries-long quest, carried out by numerous philosophers, for an answer to what might be best described as “the wrong question,” namely: “How is it that we can know things outside the mind?” This question, particularly in the most thorough treatment among moderns given it by Kant, coursed through philosophy so strongly that even many Thomists were swept along by its current. Enter Gilson. By participating in the recovery of the thought of the scholastics, especially Thomas Aquinas, Gilson was able to formulate a theory of knowledge which, though aimed at answering the question of the moderns, avoided their fundamental errors.
    [Show full text]