1. Martin Heidegger, What Is a Thing? Trans. W.B. Barton, Jr., and Vera Deutsch, with an Analysis by Eugene T

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

1. Martin Heidegger, What Is a Thing? Trans. W.B. Barton, Jr., and Vera Deutsch, with an Analysis by Eugene T NOTES INTRODUCTION 1. Martin Heidegger, What Is a Thing? trans. W.B. Barton, Jr., and Vera Deutsch, with an analysis by Eugene T. Gendlin (Gateway ed.; Chicago: Henry Regnery Co., 1967). 2. Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. International Encyclopedia of Unified Science (2nd ed., enlarged; Chicago: The Univer­ sity of Chicago, 1970). 3. Ibid., p. 6. 4. Ibid., p. 10. 5. Ibid., p. 52. 6. Cf. esp. Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds., Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Proceedin~ of the International Colloquium in the Philos­ ophy of Science, London, 1965, vol. 4 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970). 7. Thomas S. Kuhn, The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought. Foreword by James M. Conant (Vintage Books; New York: Random House, 1959), pp. 129ff. 8. Owen C. Gingerich, "'Crisis' versus Aesthetic in Copernican Revolution," in Vistas in Astronomy, vol. 17, ed. Arthur Beer and K.Aa. Strand (New York: Pergamon Press, 1975), pp. 85-95. PART ONE 1. Sir Fred Hoyle, Astronomy: A History of Man's Investigation of the Universe (Crescent Books, Inc., 1962), p. 10. 2. Ludwig Feuerbach, The Essence of Christianity, trans. George Eliot (Torchbook ed.; New York: Harper and Brothers, Publishers, 1957), p. 5. 3. Cf. Hans Jonas, The Gnostic Religion (2nd ed.; Boston: Beacon Press, 1963), pp. 254ff. 4. Cf. R.S. Westfall, Force in Newton's Physics: The Science of !?ynamics in the Seventeenth Century (New York: American Elsevier, 1971), p. 284. 5. Gerd Buchdahl, The Image of Newton and Locke in the Age of Reason (London: Sheed and Ward, 1961), p. 4. 190 A RELATIONAL METAPHYSIC 6. Westfall, p. 323. 7. Sir Isaac Newton, Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, Great Books of the Western World, vol. 34 (Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc., 1952), p. 14. 8. For an excellent discussion of the conceptual struggle to understand "force," cf. Westfall. 9. Cited from an unrehearsed interview taped at The Institute of Theoretical Astronomy (now The Institute of Astronomy), Cambridge, England, in December of 1971. Professor Ovenden has kindly consented to this use of his remarks. 10. Max Jammer, Concepts of Space: The History of the Theories of Space in Physics (Harper Torchbook ed.; New York: Harper and Brothers, 1960), p.95. 11. Albert Einstein, "Autobiographical Notes," in Albert Einstein: Philos­ opher-Scientist, The library of living Philosophers, vol. 7, ed. Paul Arthur Schilpp (laSalle, Ill.: Open Court Publishing Co., 1970), p. 31. 12. Ibid. 13. Westfall, p. 509. 14. Ibid. 15. In the context of an extensive note on this question, Alexandre Koyre states his conclusion as follows: "I am, thus, morally certain that Clarke communicated to Newton both Leibniz's letters and his own replies to them." From the Gosed World to the Infinite Universe (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins Press, 1957), p. 301. 16. I. Bernard Cohen, ed., Sir IsaacNewton's Opticks (New York: Dover Publi- cations, Inc., 1952). p. xxviii. 17. Ibid. 18. Cited from Cohen, p. xxx. 19. Cf. also Koyre, pp. 174ff; and Westfall, pp. S06ff. 20. Cohen, p. xxxiii. 21. For further details, plus an illuminating discussion of the differences between the Principia and the Opticks, cf. ibid., pp. xxxivff. 22. Westfall, p. 466. 23. Ibid., pp. 337ff. 24. Jammer, p. 96. 25. Ibid., p. 103. 26. Westfall, p. 445f. 27. Jammer, p. 114. 28. Ibid., p. 99. 29. Westfall, p. 38S. 30. Cohen, p. 400. 31. Newton,Principia; cited from Jammer, p. lOS. 32. Jammer, p. 106. 33. Ibid. 34. Ibid., p. 107. 3S. Cohen, p. 403. NOTES 191 36. Jammer, p. 115. 37. Ibid., pp. 62, 66. 38. Cf. Thomas F. Torrance, Space, Time and Incarnation (London: Oxford University Press, 1969), esp. pp. 3f., 3lf., 37f. 39. Ian Hacking, "Individual Substance," in Leibniz: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Harry G. Frankfurt (Anchor Book; New York: Doubleday and Company, 1972), p. 144. 40. Leroy E. Loemker, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz: Philosophical Papers and Letters (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1956), p. 22. 41. Lewis White Beck, Early German Philosophy: Kant and his Predecessors (Cambridge, Mass.: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1969), p.222f. 42. Ibid., p. 230. 43. Gottfried Martin, Kant's Metaphysics and Theory of Science, trans. P.G. Lucas (Manchester: University Press, 1953), p. 4f; cf.Monatioiogy, par. 87. 44. Beck, p. 231. 45. Loemker, p. 37. 46. Martin, p. 7; italics mine. 47. Ivor Leclerc, The Nature of Physical Existence, Muirhead Philosophical Library (New York: The Humanities Press, Inc., 1972), p. 243. 48. Ibid., p. 247. 49. Ibid., p. 245. 50. Ibid., p. 246. 51. Ibid., p. 247. 52. Cited from Leclerc, p. 250; for his source, cf. Loemker, p. 583. 53. Alfred North Whitehead, Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology (Harper Torchbook ed., New York: Harper and Brothers, 1960), p. 108f. [cor. ed., p. 70] (See also Torrance, pp. 38ff., and Beck, p. 231). I am taking the liberty of supplying the page numbers from the new, contro­ versial edition of Process and Reality, ed. David Ray Griffm and Donald W. Sherburne (New York: The Free Press, 1978), even though no passages I cite from Process and Reality differ in the Corrected Edition. 54. H.G. Alexander, ed., The Leibniz-Garke Correspondence (Manchester: University Press, 1956), p. 26. 55. Ibid., p. 36. 56. Ibid., p. 43f. 57. Cohen, p. 402. 58. From his "Essay on Dynamics," New Essays; cited from Westfall, p. 288. 59. Alexander, p. 43. 60. Ibid., p. 92. 61. Ibid., p. 118. 62. On this idea, cf. infra p. 45. 63. Leibniz, "Principles of Nature and Grace"; cited from Westfall, p. 312. 64. KoynS, p. 274. 65. Ibid. 66. Einstein, p. 31. 192 A RELATIONAL METAPHYSIC 67. Ibid. 68. Jammer, p. xiv. 69. Westfall, p. 505. 70. Karl Popper, Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge (3rd ed.; London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1969), p. 94. 71. Ibid. 72. Ibid., p.I77. 73. Ibid., p. 180. 74. Ibid., p. 180, n. 17. 75. Ibid., p. 94. 76. Ibid., pp. 184ff. 77. Ibid., p. 184. 78. Ibid. 79. Ibid. 80. Ibid., p. 191. 81. Ibid. 82. Cf. Beck, p. 432.: often called "the silent decade," it is "the period in Kant's life about which there is the least evidence and the most dispute, since we have large amounts of undatable writings presumably done during this decade, but few hard facts to guide us in tracing the course of his thought." 83. Letter toC. Garvie, 21st September 1798; cited from Popper, p. 177, n.lO. 84. Martin, p. 1. 85. Ibid., p. 16. 86. Ibid., p. 90. 87. Leclerc, p. 280. 88. In the exposition of Kant's pre-critical thought I am following Leclerc, pp.276ff. 89. Ibid., p. 277. 90. Kant's Monad%gia physica, sec. III, Prop. 12; cited from Leclerc, p. 278 91. Leclerc, p. 279. 92. Martin, p. 28. 93. Beck, pp. 44lff. 94. Ibid., cf. Table 2. 95. Ibid., p. 446. 96. Ibid., p. 447. 97. Ibid., p. 457, and n. 86. 98. This position was stressed recently by Martin, p. 44. 99. Norman Kemp Smith, ed., Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (London: Macmillan and Co., Ltd., 1963 reprint of 2nd impression with corrections, 1933), p. 78 [A35--36, B52]. 100. Ibid., p. 72 [A28, B44]. 101. Martin, p. 38. 102. Ibid. 103. Ibid., p. 41. NOTES 193 104. Ibid., p. 11. 105. Ibid., p:38. 106. Ibid., p. 92. 107. Ibid., p. 97. 108. Ibid., p. 95. 109. Ibid. 110. Ibid., p. 67. 111. Ibid., p. 89. 112. Ibid., p. 124. 113. Heidegger, p. 56. 114. Ibid., p. 77. 115. Ibid., p. 55. 116. Ibid., p. 104. 117. Ibid., p. 104f. 118. Ibid., p. 128. 119. Ibid., pp. 139ff. 120. Cf. also Heidegger, p. 140, for the following schema: "Now summarizing Kant's basic interpretation of knowledge, we say: 1 Knowledge for Kant is human knowledge. 2. Human knowledge is essentially experience. 3. Ex­ perience realizes itself in the form of mathematical physical science. 4. Kant sees this science and with it the essence of real human knowledge in the historical form of Newtonian physics, which today one still calls 'classical.' " 121. Ibid., p. 164. 122. Ibid., p. 163. 123. Ibid., p. 178. 124. Ibid., p.182f. 125. Ibid., p. 180. 126. Caption in Heidegger, p. 184. 127. Ibid., p. 194. 128. Smith, p. 238 [A216, B267]. 129. Heidegger, p. 204. 130. Ibid., p. 206. 131. Ibid., p. 223. 132. From d' Alembert's Elements ofPhilosophy; cited from Buchdahl, p. 7. 133. Ibid., p. II. 134. W.C. Dampier, A History of Science and its Relations with Philosophy and Religion, Postscript by I. Bernard Cohen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1st paperback ed., 1966), p.18lf. 135. Ibid., p. 3. 136. Ibid., p. 198. 137. Beck, p. SOL 138. J.D. North, The Measure of the Universe: A History of Modem Cos­ mology (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1965), pp. 16-50. 139. Ibid., p. 19. 140. Cf. ibid., p. 24. 194 A RELATIONAL METAPHYSIC 141. H.A. Lorentz, A. Einstein, H. Minkowski, and H. Weyl, The Principle of Relativity: A Collection of Original Memoirs on the Special and General Theory ofRelativity (New York: Dover Publications, Inc., 1952), p. 37. 142. The Quixotic effort of Herman Dingle to discredit it continues, but without devotees; cf. "The Case against Special Relativity," Nature 216 (1967): 119-122. 143. Lorentz et aI., p. 75. 144. Ibid., p. 76. 145. A. d' Abro, The Rise of the New Physics: Its Mathematical and Physical Theories, vol. 1 (New York: Dover Publications, Inc., 1951), p. 80. 146. Also in the Annalen der Physik; cf.
Recommended publications
  • Depopulation: on the Logic of Heidegger's Volk
    Research research in phenomenology 47 (2017) 297–330 in Phenomenology brill.com/rp Depopulation: On the Logic of Heidegger’s Volk Nicolai Krejberg Knudsen Aarhus University [email protected] Abstract This article provides a detailed analysis of the function of the notion of Volk in Martin Heidegger’s philosophy. At first glance, this term is an appeal to the revolutionary mass- es of the National Socialist revolution in a way that demarcates a distinction between the rootedness of the German People (capital “P”) and the rootlessness of the modern rabble (or people). But this distinction is not a sufficient explanation of Heidegger’s position, because Heidegger simultaneously seems to hold that even the Germans are characterized by a lack of identity. What is required is a further appropriation of the proper. My suggestion is that this logic of the Volk is not only useful for understanding Heidegger’s thought during the war, but also an indication of what happened after he lost faith in the National Socialist movement and thus had to make the lack of the People the basis of his thought. Keywords Heidegger – Nazism – Schwarze Hefte – Black Notebooks – Volk – people Introduction In § 74 of Sein und Zeit, Heidegger introduces the notorious term “the People” [das Volk]. For Heidegger, this term functions as the intersection between phi- losophy and politics and, consequently, it preoccupies him throughout the turbulent years from the National Socialist revolution in 1933 to the end of WWII in 1945. The shift from individual Dasein to the Dasein of the German People has often been noted as the very point at which Heidegger’s fundamen- tal ontology intersects with his disastrous political views.
    [Show full text]
  • 52 Philosophy in a Dark Time: Martin Heidegger and the Third Reich
    52 Philosophy in a Dark Time: Martin Heidegger and the Third Reich TIMOTHY O’HAGAN Like Oscar Wilde I can resist everything except temptation. So when I re- ceived Anne Meylan’s tempting invitation to contribute to this Festschrift for Pascal Engel I accepted without hesitation, before I had time to think whether I had anything for the occasion. Finally I suggested to Anne the text of a pub- lic lecture which I delivered in 2008 and which I had shown to Pascal, who responded to it with his customary enthusiasm and barrage of papers of his own on similar topics. But when I re-read it, I realized that it had been written for the general public rather than the professional philosophers who would be likely to read this collection of essays. So what was I to do with it? I’ve decided to present it in two parts. In Part One I reproduce the original lecture, unchanged except for a few minor corrections. In Part Two I engage with a tiny fraction of the vast secondary literature which has built up over the years and which shows no sign of abating. 1. Part One: The 2008 Lecture Curtain-Raiser Let us start with two dates, 1927 and 1933. In 1927 Adolf Hitler’s Mein Kampf (volume II) was published. So too was Martin Heidegger’s magnum opus Being and Time. In 1933 two appointments were made: Hitler as Chancellor of the German Reich and Heidegger as Rector of Freiburg University. In 1927 it was a case of sheer coincidence; in 1933 the two events were closely linked.
    [Show full text]
  • Temporality and Historicality of Dasein at Martin Heidegger
    Sincronía ISSN: 1562-384X [email protected] Universidad de Guadalajara México Temporality and historicality of dasein at martin heidegger. Javorská, Andrea Temporality and historicality of dasein at martin heidegger. Sincronía, no. 69, 2016 Universidad de Guadalajara, México Available in: https://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=513852378011 This work is licensed under Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International. PDF generated from XML JATS4R by Redalyc Project academic non-profit, developed under the open access initiative Filosofía Temporality and historicality of dasein at martin heidegger. Andrea Javorská [email protected] Constantine the Philosopher University in Nitra, Eslovaquia Abstract: Analysis of Heidegger's work around historicity as an ontological problem through the existential analytic of Being Dasein. It seeks to find the significant structure of temporality represented by the historicity of Dasein. Keywords: Heidegger, Existentialism, Dasein, Temporality. Resumen: Análisis de la obra de Heidegger en tornoa la historicidad como problema ontológico a través de la analítica existencial del Ser Dasein. Se pretende encontrar la estructura significativa de temporalidad representada por la historicidad del Dasein. Palabras clave: Heidegger, Existencialismo, Dasein, Temporalidad. Sincronía, no. 69, 2016 Universidad de Guadalajara, México Martin Heidegger and his fundamental ontology shows that the question Received: 03 August 2015 Revised: 28 August 2015 of history belongs among the most fundamental questions of human Accepted:
    [Show full text]
  • Martin Heidegger's Phenomenology and the Science of Mind
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Master's Theses Graduate School 2005 Martin Heidegger's phenomenology and the science of mind Charles Dale Hollingsworth Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons Recommended Citation Hollingsworth, Charles Dale, "Martin Heidegger's phenomenology and the science of mind" (2005). LSU Master's Theses. 2713. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses/2713 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Master's Theses by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. MARTIN HEIDEGGER’S PHENOMENOLOGY AND THE SCIENCE OF MIND A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts In The Department of Philosophy by Charles Dale Hollingsworth B.A., Mississippi State University, 2003 May 2005 TABLE OF CONTENTS Abstract.......................................................................................iii Chapter 1 The Computational Model of Mind and its Critics..........1 2 One Attempt at a Heideggerean Approach to Cognitive Science...........................................................................14 3 Heidegger on Scientific
    [Show full text]
  • Required Readings
    HPS/PHIL 93872 Spring 2006 Historical Foundations of the Quantum Theory Don Howard, Instructor Required Readings: Topic: Readings: Planck and black-body radiation. Martin Klein. “Planck, Entropy, and Quanta, 19011906.” The Natural Philosopher 1 (1963), 83-108. Martin Klein. “Einstein’s First Paper on Quanta.” The Natural Einstein and the photo-electric effect. Philosopher 2 (1963), 59-86. Max Jammer. “Regularities in Line Spectra”; “Bohr’s Theory The Bohr model of the atom and spectral of the Hydrogen Atom.” In The Conceptual Development of series. Quantum Mechanics. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1966, pp. 62- 88. The Bohr-Sommerfeld “old” quantum Max Jammer. “The Older Quantum Theory.” In The Conceptual theory; Einstein on transition Development of Quantum Mechanics. New York: McGraw-Hill, probabilities. 1966, pp. 89-156. The Bohr-Kramers-Slater theory. Max Jammer. “The Transition to Quantum Mechanics.” In The Conceptual Development of Quantum Mechanics. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1966, pp. 157-195. Bose-Einstein statistics. Don Howard. “‘Nicht sein kann was nicht sein darf,’ or the Prehistory of EPR, 1909-1935: Einstein’s Early Worries about the Quantum Mechanics of Composite Systems.” In Sixty-Two Years of Uncertainty: Historical, Philosophical, and Physical Inquiries into the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Arthur Miller, ed. New York: Plenum, 1990, pp. 61-111. Max Jammer. “The Formation of Quantum Mechanics.” In The Schrödinger and wave mechanics; Conceptual Development of Quantum Mechanics. New York: Heisenberg and matrix mechanics. McGraw-Hill, 1966, pp. 196-280. James T. Cushing. “Early Attempts at Causal Theories: A De Broglie and the origins of pilot-wave Stillborn Program.” In Quantum Mechanics: Historical theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Imre Lakatos's Philosophy of Mathematics
    Imre Lakatos’s Philosophy of Mathematics Gábor Kutrovátz Eötvös Loránd University, Budapest e-mail: [email protected] Introduction Imre Lakatos (1922-1974) is known world-wide by at least two different groups of philosophers. For the philosophers of science, he was a great defender of scientific rationality: he gave up the idea of ‘instant’ methodological rationality and substituted it with the historiographical methodology based on the notion of ‘rational reconstruction’. For the philosophers of mathematics, he was a great attacker at the formalist school, and instead of the formal-axiomatic features of mathematics he put the emphasis on heuristics, the historical processes of theory building and conceptualisation. These two ‘incarnations’ of Lakatos are rarely discussed within a unique philosophical framework, and not without reason: Lakatos himself never really tried to harmonise these two fields of interest. There are signs showing that he intended to build a common ground for them, but perhaps this project could not even take a very definite shape before his early death. In this paper I shall concentrate on only one of these topics: his philosophy of mathematics; and my primary aim is to give a brief and coherent summary of his ideas concerning this field. It should be noted, however, that his philosophy of mathematics and that of science obviously have some characteristics in common, since they were contrived by the same man, and not at a great temporal distance in his academic life, when he was under very similar intellectual influences. My secondary purpose therefore is to build this summary in a way that is in accordance with his general philosophical theory of science, that is, to give a mild ‘rational reconstruction’ of his ideas.1 The context of Lakatos’s philosophy of mathematics In the Acknowledgements of his doctoral thesis wrote on the philosophy of mathematics, Lakatos mentions three authors as the most influential sources for his philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • John Von Neumann's “Impossibility Proof” in a Historical Perspective’, Physis 32 (1995), Pp
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by SAS-SPACE Published: Louis Caruana, ‘John von Neumann's “Impossibility Proof” in a Historical Perspective’, Physis 32 (1995), pp. 109-124. JOHN VON NEUMANN'S ‘IMPOSSIBILITY PROOF’ IN A HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE ABSTRACT John von Neumann's proof that quantum mechanics is logically incompatible with hidden varibales has been the object of extensive study both by physicists and by historians. The latter have concentrated mainly on the way the proof was interpreted, accepted and rejected between 1932, when it was published, and 1966, when J.S. Bell published the first explicit identification of the mistake it involved. What is proposed in this paper is an investigation into the origins of the proof rather than the aftermath. In the first section, a brief overview of the his personal life and his proof is given to set the scene. There follows a discussion on the merits of using here the historical method employed elsewhere by Andrew Warwick. It will be argued that a study of the origins of von Neumann's proof shows how there is an interaction between the following factors: the broad issues within a specific culture, the learning process of the theoretical physicist concerned, and the conceptual techniques available. In our case, the ‘conceptual technology’ employed by von Neumann is identified as the method of axiomatisation. 1. INTRODUCTION A full biography of John von Neumann is not yet available. Moreover, it seems that there is a lack of extended historical work on the origin of his contributions to quantum mechanics.
    [Show full text]
  • Kuhn Versus Lakatos, Or Paradigms Ver Su S Research Programmes in the History of Economics
    [HOPE Vol. 7 (1975) No. 41 Kuhn versus Lakatos, or paradigms ver su s research programmes in the history of economics Mark Blaug In the 1950’s and 1960’s economists learned their methodology from Popper. Not that many of them read Popper. Instead, they read Friedman, and perhaps few of them realized that Friedman is simply Popper-with-a-twist applied to economics. To be sure, Friedman was criticized, but the “Essay on the Methodology of Positive Economics” nevertheless survived to become the one arti- cle on methodology that virtually every economist has read at some stage in his career. The idea that unrealistic “assumptions” are nothing to worry about, provided that the theory deduced from them culminates in falsifiable predictions, carried conviction to economists long inclined by habit and tradition to take a purely instrumentalist view of their subject. All that is almost ancient history, however. The new wave is not Popper’s “falsifiability” but Kuhn’s “paradigms.” Again, it is un- likely that many economists read The Structure oj Scientific Revolu- tions (1962). Nevertheless, appeal to paradigmatic reasoning quickly became a regular feature of controversies in economics and “paradigm” is now the byword of every historian of economic thought.’ Recently, however, some commentators have expressed misgivings about Kuhnian methodology applied to economics, throw- ing doubt in particular on the view that “scientific revolutions” characterize the history of economic thought.* With these doubts I heartily concur. I will argue that the term “paradigm” ought to be banished from economic literature, unless surrounded by inverted commas. Suitably qualified, however, the term retains a function in the historical exposition of economic doctrines as a reminder of the Copyright 1976 by Mark Blaug MARKBLAUG is Head of the Research Unit in the Economics of Education at the University of London.
    [Show full text]
  • PHI230 Philosophy of Science
    Department of Philosophy Level 2 Module PHI230 Philosophy of Science LECTURER: George Botterill Office Hours Wed 12-1, Fri 1-2; external tel: (0114)2220580; email: [email protected] Lectures: Monday 2-3 in Hicks Building LT6 Friday 11-12 in Hicks Building LT5 Seminars: See MOLE unit to join: Monday 4-5 Jessop Building 215, Friday 12-1 Jessop Building 215 GENERAL OUTLINE This course will deal with major issues in the philosophy of science, with particular emphasis on the rationality of theory-change, explanation, the status of scientific laws, observation, and the structure of scientific theories. Most of the course will be devoted to the methodology of natural science, though we may also discuss some issues in the philosophy of the social sciences. Most of the issues presented revolve around two major debates in the philosophy of science: (1) the dispute between Kuhn and Popper about theory change (2) disagreements between positivist (or instrumentalist) and realist conceptions of science. Modern philosophy of science has become closely linked with the history of science. The course will reflect this by considering how well major developments in the history of science fit proposed methodological rules about how science ought to proceed. The Copernican Revolution in astronomy will be used as a case-study. 1 AIMS AND OBJECTIVES The main aims of this module are: • to introduce students to the debate about theory-change in science, deriving from the work of Popper, Kuhn, Feyerabend and Lakatos • to help students acquire an understanding of some important problems in the philosophy of science (concerning the topics of: explanation, observation, scientific realism, and the nature of laws) • to encourage students to enter into serious engagement with some of the major problems in the philosophy of science.
    [Show full text]
  • Download Download
    SPRING 1991 85 Inbetweenness: Spatial Folds in Theatre Historiography Michal Kobialka Thought thinks its own history (the past), but in order to free itself from what it thinks (the present) and be able finally to "think otherwise" (the future). Gilles Deleuze, Foucault In his recent book, Soundings in Critical T7ieoryy Dominick LaCapra discusses the critical and self-critical nature of historiography. Noteworthy is a passage introducing the dialogic exchanges between the theoretical systems of Marx, Derrida, Foucault, and other contemporary theoreticians, in which LaCapra talks about the nature of criticism today: Any assembly of "critics" today will have representatives of various established departments who are uneasy with their own represent­ ative function and may find more to say, listen to, or at least argue about with other critics than with more securely "representative" members of their own department or field. Indeed contemporary critics are no longer content with interdisciplinary efforts that simply combine, compare, or synthetically unify the methods of existing academic disciplines. Their questioning of established disciplines both raises doubts about internal criteria of purity or autonomy and unsettles the boundaries and protocols of given fields. Criticism in this sense is a discursive agitation running across a variety of Michal Kobialka has published articles and reviews in Journal of Dramatic Theory and Criticism, Theatre History Studies, Medieval Perspectives, The Drama Review, Theatre Journal, Stages, Slavic and East European Journal, and Soviet and East-European Drama, Theatre and Film. He is currently working on a book on Taduesz Kantor and his Cricot 2 theatre. 86 Journal of Dramatic Theory and Criticism disciplines and having an uneasy relation to its own institutional­ ization.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz, Mysticism and Religion Archives Internationales D'histoire Des Idees
    LEIBNIZ, MYSTICISM AND RELIGION ARCHIVES INTERNATIONALES D'HISTOIRE DES IDEES INTERNATIONAL ARCHIVES OF THE HISTORY OF IDEAS 158 LEIBNIZ, MYSTICISM AND RELIGION edited by ALLISON P. COUDERT, RICHARD H. POPKIN and GORDON M. WEINER Founding Directors: P. Dibon t (Paris) and R.H. Popkin (Washington University, St. Louis & UCLA) Director: Sarah Hutton (The University of Hertfordshire, Uni ted Kingdom) Associate Directors: lE. Force (Lexington); lC. Laursen (Riverside) Editorial Board: J.F. Battail (Paris); F. Duchesneau (Montreal); A. Gabbey (New York); T. Gregory (Rome); J.D. North (Groningen); MJ. Petry (Rotterdam); J. Popkin (Lexington); G.A.J. Rogers (Keele); Th. Verbeek (Utrecht) Advisory Editorial Board: J. Aubin (Paris); B. Copenhaver (Los Angeles); A. Crombie (Oxford); H. Gadamer (Heidelberg); H. Gouhier (Paris); K. Hanada (Hokkaido University); W. Kirsop (Melbourne); P.O. Kristeller (Columbia University); E. Labrousse (Paris); A. Lossky (Los Angeles); J. Malarczyk (Lublin); J. Orcibal (Paris); W. Röd (München); G. Rousseau (Los Angeles); H. Rowen (Rutgers University, NJ.); J.P. Schobinger (Zürich); J. Tans (Groningen) LEIBNIZ, MYSTICISM AND RELIGION Edited by ALLISON P. COUDERT Arizona State University, Tempe, Arizona, U.S.A. RICHARD H. POPKIN University ofCalifornia, Los Angeles, California, U.S.A. and GORDON M. WEINER Arizona State University, Tempe, Arizona, U.s.A. Springer-Science+Business Media, B.V. A C.I.P. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 978-90-481-5088-5 ISBN 978-94-015-9052-5 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-015-9052-5 Printed on acid-free paper All Rights Reserved @1998 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1998.
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger's Will to Power and the Problem of Nietzsche's Nihilism
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School November 2019 Heidegger's Will to Power and the Problem of Nietzsche's Nihilism Megan Flocken University of South Florida Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons Scholar Commons Citation Flocken, Megan, "Heidegger's Will to Power and the Problem of Nietzsche's Nihilism" (2019). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/8098 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Heidegger's Will to Power and the Problem of Nietzsche's Nihilism by Megan Flocken A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: Lee Braver, Ph.D. Charles Guignon, Ph.D. Ofelia Schutte, Ph.D. Iain Thomson, Ph.D. Stephen Turner, Ph.D. Date of Approval: November 12, 2019 Keywords: continental philosophy, ontology, comparative philosophy, Kehre Copyright © 2019, Megan Flocken TABLE OF CONTENTS ABSTRACT .................................................................................................................................... ii CHAPTER ONE: HEIDEGGER’S WILL TO POWER AND THE PROBLEM OF NIETZSCHE’S
    [Show full text]