Stoicism and the Good Life 1

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Stoicism and the Good Life 1 Running head: STOICISM AND THE GOOD LIFE 1 1 Stoicism and the good life 1 1 2 Johannes Alfons Karl & Ronald Fischer 1 3 Victoria University of Wellington 4 Author Note 5 The pre-registration, material, and analytical code for this study can be found on the 6 OSF (https://osf.io/bkqgs/?view_only=0bdc04bf606b41b9a1ac4ba0c7658990) 7 Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Johannes Alfons Karl, 8 Kelburn Parade. E-mail: [email protected] STOICISM AND THE GOOD LIFE 2 9 Abstract 10 Ancient philosophy identified a wide range of possible approaches to life which are 11 supposed to enable wellbeing. The stoic approach to life focused on emotional restraint and 12 an overall orientation towards meaning in life. While few individuals are explicit adherents 13 to stoicism, individuals can also adopt an approach to life representing a naive stoic 14 ideology. While in the past this approach has been largely investigated in relation to ideals 15 of masculinity, recently the focus has widened to examine how stoic ideology might be 16 related to wellbeing across individuals. While initial research focusing on hedonic 17 conceptualizations of wellbeing has found substantial negative effects of stoic ideology, no 18 study so far has examined the differential effects that stoic ideology might have on 19 eudaimonic and hedonic wellbeing. In this pre-registered study, 636 participants reported 20 their stoic ideology, eudaimonic and hedonic wellbeing, as well as their orientations to 21 happiness. Overall, we found that the recently developed measure of stoic ideology showed 22 good measurement properties and we confirmed the negative effects of stoic beliefs on 23 hedonic wellbeing observed in previous studies. Additionally, we found that in contrast to 24 our hypothesis stoic ideology significantly negatively predicted eudaimonic wellbeing and 25 eudaimonic wellbeing orientation, as well as engagement in life. This indicates that a naive 26 endorsement of stoic ideology might be detrimental to individuals’ wellbeing independent 27 of the specific aspect. 28 Keywords: stoicism; wellbeing; orientations to happiness 29 Word count: 3952 STOICISM AND THE GOOD LIFE 3 30 Stoicism and the good life 31 What is a good life? Over the course of human history many different answers to this 32 question have been suggested. One school of thought that rose to answering this question 33 were the Stoics. Stoic philosophy, as most ancient Greek schools, lectured on a range of 34 topics from meta-physics to logic but is today possibly best known for their propositions in 35 the field of ethics. While few people explicitly follow stoic doctrine in modern times, stoic 36 ideology is still implicitly embraced by individuals (Pathak, Wieten, & Wheldon, 2017; 37 Sherman, 2011). For example, Stoic ideology has long been endorsed by military personnel 38 to reduce combat stress (Sherman, 2011). 39 Stoic Ideology. One of the reasons why stoicism might be so salient in the 40 military is due to the traditional gender skew of this field. Stoicism in the past has been 41 thought to be strongly tied to traditional conceptualizations of masculinity (Perry, Stacy, 42 & Pepper, 2019; Scoats & Robinson, 2020), with research indicating some support for this 43 view (Pathak et al., 2017), nevertheless, the differences between male and female 44 respondents was not as substantial as expected (Pathak et al., 2017). Currently it is 45 unclear whether these gender differences are by-products of measurement artifacts or 46 whether actual differences in stoic ideology are captured. Therefore, one of our aims is to 47 provide further information on differences between gender in our sample. 48 This is especially important as stoicism and the resulting lack in help seeking has 49 been identified as potential source of male health issues and low wellbeing. While stoicism 50 in males has been investigated in the past through the lens of illbeing, stoicism has also 51 been related to wellbeing. Stoic thought has profoundly influenced Cognitive Behavioral 52 Therapy (Robertson, 2016, 2019) and plays an important role in the treatment of anxiety 53 and depression (Watts, Turnell, Kladnitski, Newby, & Andrews, 2015). Stoic philosophy 54 has long influenced psychology, but little attention has been paid how individuals differ in 55 their endorsement of stoic ideologies (for a thorough review of ancient stoicism and modern STOICISM AND THE GOOD LIFE 4 56 revivals we recommend Becker, 2017). Initial scales measuring stoicism mostly focused on a 57 single dimensional construct assessed by past behaviors (for a review of past scales see 58 Pathak et al., 2017). Recently a scale of stoic ideology has been developed, the 59 Pathak-Wieten Stoicism Ideology Scale (PWSIS; Pathak et al., 2017), allowing for the 60 assessment of individuals implicit endorsement of stoic ideology. This scale assesses stoic 61 ideology comprised of four facets, Stoic Taciturnity (the belief that emotions should not be 62 expressed), Stoic Serenity (the belief that strong emotions should not be felt), Stoic 63 Endurance (the belief that physical suffering should be endured), and Death Acceptance 64 (accepting mortality, rather than fearing it). The PWSIS captures essential elements of 65 Stoic philosophy, mostly focusing on emotion expression. Importantly, the PWSIS captures 66 what could be called naive stoic ideologies, in the sense that it is not expected that 67 individuals scoring high on it have systematic knowledge of Stoicism as ordered school of 68 thought. The fact that the PWSIS measures these naive ideologies precludes the 69 investigation of some aspects of stoic thinking that are important in the philosophical 70 system, such as the emphasis on vices and virtues or emphasis on emotional control in 71 stressful situations (this was originally a facet of the PWSIS, but showed unfavorable 72 psychometric properties). So, what does this stoic ideology imply for individuals’ 73 wellbeing? Past research has shown negative relationship of stoicism and life satisfaction as 74 well as positive relationships between stoicism and depression (Bei et al., 2013; Murray et 75 al., 2008). Overall, this might lead to the conclusion that embracing stoic ideologies 76 reduces wellbeing. But what exactly is meant with wellbeing? 77 Eudaimonic and Hedonic Wellbeing. The two major dimensions of wellbeing 78 identified in philosophy and psychology are hedonia and eudaimonia (Ryan & Deci, 2001). 79 Hedonic wellbeing is defined by subjective happiness, positive feelings, and the absence of 80 negative feelings. Overall, hedonic wellbeing could be summarized as a life full of pleasure 81 and free of pain. This is contrasted by eudaimonic wellbeing which emphasizes on meaning 82 and purpose in life. The distinction of eudaimonic and hedonic wellbeing have been shown STOICISM AND THE GOOD LIFE 5 83 to differentiate between a wide range of validation variables such as long-term orientation 84 (Huta & Ryan, 2010; Joshanloo, Jovanović, & Park, 2020; Vittersø & Søholt, 2011). 85 Neverthless, eudaimonia and hedonia tend to be correlated at very high levels (see for 86 examples: Fowers, Mollica, & Procacci, 2010; Extremera, Ruiz-Aranda, Pineda-Galán, & 87 Salguero, 2011; Yoon et al., 2015). Taken together that while eudaimonic and hedonic 88 wellbeing are not necessarily opposite, they can be the results of different underlying 89 psychological processes (Huta, 2016). 90 Stoicism and Wellbeing. Viewed through a stoic lens, eudaimonia should be 91 preferred over hedonia. Late stoic writers such as Epictetus outlined a philosophy with the 92 telos (end) of eudaimonia (meaning, flourishing) which can be achieved by living a virtuous 93 life (Ierodiakonou, 2015; Long, 2002). A virtuous life was determined as a life following 94 reason, dedicated to fulfilling ones role in life. Based on this conceptualization of virtue, 95 Stoics divided everything into three categories: virtue (acts in accordance with reason), 96 vice (acts contrary to reason), and indifferents (all acts not classified as vice or virtue). 97 While there is no gradient from vice to virtue, Stoics differentiate indifferents in preferred 98 indifferents (enabling reason, such as health), disprefered indifferents (diminishing reasons, 99 such as pain), and absolute indifferents (the color of your wall) (for a discussion of 100 indifferents in stoic thought see Inwood, 2003; Becker, 2017). This division implied a rank 101 order of importance: virtues are preferable over indifferents, indifferents over vices 102 (Inwood, 2003). This leads to adherents of Stoicism sometimes prioritizing acts over 103 hedonic wellbeing or health if they enable reason and are beneficial to eudaimonic 104 wellbeing (Becker, 2003, 2017). While the stoic view of wellbeing has received substantial 105 discussion in philosophy (for an in-depth discussion see Inwood, 2003), it has received only 106 limited empirical attention in psychology. 107 The link between stoicism and wellbeing has been largely investigated through a 108 hedonic lens (e.g, Murray et al., 2008) and was found to negatively relate to life satisfaction 109 and positively to depression (Bei et al., 2013; Murray et al., 2008). While this negative STOICISM AND THE GOOD LIFE 6 110 effect might be true for hedonic wellbeing, Stoicism is an explicitly eudaimonic theory of 111 wellbeing, prioritizing meaning over pleasure. For example, adherents to stoic philosophy, 112 naive or explicit, try to avoid strong emotions, positive as well as negative, but this
Recommended publications
  • Pursuing Eudaimonia LIVERPOOL HOPE UNIVERSITY STUDIES in ETHICS SERIES SERIES EDITOR: DR
    Pursuing Eudaimonia LIVERPOOL HOPE UNIVERSITY STUDIES IN ETHICS SERIES SERIES EDITOR: DR. DAVID TOREVELL SERIES DEPUTY EDITOR: DR. JACQUI MILLER VOLUME ONE: ENGAGING RELIGIOUS EDUCATION Editors: Joy Schmack, Matthew Thompson and David Torevell with Camilla Cole VOLUME TWO: RESERVOIRS OF HOPE: SUSTAINING SPIRITUALITY IN SCHOOL LEADERS Author: Alan Flintham VOLUME THREE: LITERATURE AND ETHICS: FROM THE GREEN KNIGHT TO THE DARK KNIGHT Editors: Steve Brie and William T. Rossiter VOLUME FOUR: POST-CONFLICT RECONSTRUCTION Editor: Neil Ferguson VOLUME FIVE: FROM CRITIQUE TO ACTION: THE PRACTICAL ETHICS OF THE ORGANIZATIONAL WORLD Editors: David Weir and Nabil Sultan VOLUME SIX: A LIFE OF ETHICS AND PERFORMANCE Editors: John Matthews and David Torevell VOLUME SEVEN: PROFESSIONAL ETHICS: EDUCATION FOR A HUMANE SOCIETY Editors: Feng Su and Bart McGettrick VOLUME EIGHT: CATHOLIC EDUCATION: UNIVERSAL PRINCIPLES, LOCALLY APPLIED Editor: Andrew B. Morris VOLUME NINE GENDERING CHRISTIAN ETHICS Editor: Jenny Daggers VOLUME TEN PURSUING EUDAIMONIA: RE-APPROPRIATING THE GREEK PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS OF THE CHRISTIAN APOPHATIC TRADITION Author: Brendan Cook Pursuing Eudaimonia: Re-appropriating the Greek Philosophical Foundations of the Christian Apophatic Tradition By Brendan Cook Pursuing Eudaimonia: Re-appropriating the Greek Philosophical Foundations of the Christian Apophatic Tradition, by Brendan Cook This book first published 2013 Cambridge Scholars Publishing 12 Back Chapman Street, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2XX, UK British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Copyright © 2013 by Brendan Cook All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy As a Path to Happiness
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Helsingin yliopiston digitaalinen arkisto Philosophy as a Path to Happiness Attainment of Happiness in Arabic Peripatetic and Ismaili Philosophy Janne Mattila ACADEMIC DISSERTATION To be publicly discussed, by due permission of the Faculty of Arts at the University of Helsinki in auditorium XII, University main building, on the 13th of June, 2011 at 12 o’clock. ISBN 978-952-92-9077-2 (paperback) ISBN 978-952-10-7001-3 (PDF) http://ethesis.helsinki.fi/ Helsinki University Print Helsinki 2011 2 Abstract The aim of this study is to explore the idea of philosophy as a path to happiness in medieval Arabic philosophy. The starting point is in comparison of two distinct currents within Arabic philosophy between the 10th and early 11th centuries, Peripatetic philosophy, represented by al-Fārābī and Ibn Sīnā, and Ismaili philosophy represented by al-Kirmānī and the Brethren of Purity. These two distinct groups of sources initially offer two contrasting views about philosophy. The attitude of the Peripatetic philosophers is rationalistic and secular in spirit, whereas for the Ismailis philosophy represents the esoteric truth behind revelation. Still, the two currents of thought converge in their view that the ultimate purpose of philosophy lies in its ability to lead man towards happiness. Moreover, they share a common concept of happiness as a contemplative ideal of human perfection, merged together with the Neoplatonic goal of the soul’s reascent to the spiritual world. Finally, for both happiness refers primarily to an otherworldly state thereby becoming a philosophical interpretation of the Quranic accounts of the afterlife.
    [Show full text]
  • Neoplatonism: the Last Ten Years
    The International Journal The International Journal of the of the Platonic Tradition 9 (2015) 205-220 Platonic Tradition brill.com/jpt Critical Notice ∵ Neoplatonism: The Last Ten Years The past decade or so has been an exciting time for scholarship on Neo­ platonism. I ought to know, because during my stint as the author of the “Book Notes” on Neoplatonism for the journal Phronesis, I read most of what was published in the field during this time. Having just handed the Book Notes over to George Boys­Stones, I thought it might be worthwhile to set down my overall impressions of the state of research into Neoplatonism. I cannot claim to have read all the books published on this topic in the last ten years, and I am here going to talk about certain themes and developments in the field rather than trying to list everything that has appeared. So if you are an admirer, or indeed author, of a book that goes unmentioned, please do not be affronted by this silence—it does not necessarily imply a negative judgment on my part. I hope that the survey will nonetheless be wide­ranging and comprehensive enough to be useful. I’ll start with an observation made by Richard Goulet,1 which I have been repeating to students ever since I read it. Goulet conducted a statistical analy­ sis of the philosophical literature preserved in the original Greek, and discov­ ered that almost three­quarters of it (71%) was written by Neoplatonists and commentators on Aristotle. In a sense this should come as no surprise.
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]
  • Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece
    Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything You Always Wanted to Know About Ancient Greek Philosophy but didn’t Know Who to Ask Edited by Patricia F. O’Grady MEET THE PHILOSOPHERS OF ANCIENT GREECE Dedicated to the memory of Panagiotis, a humble man, who found pleasure when reading about the philosophers of Ancient Greece Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything you always wanted to know about Ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask Edited by PATRICIA F. O’GRADY Flinders University of South Australia © Patricia F. O’Grady 2005 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise without the prior permission of the publisher. Patricia F. O’Grady has asserted her right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identi.ed as the editor of this work. Published by Ashgate Publishing Limited Ashgate Publishing Company Wey Court East Suite 420 Union Road 101 Cherry Street Farnham Burlington Surrey, GU9 7PT VT 05401-4405 England USA Ashgate website: http://www.ashgate.com British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask 1. Philosophy, Ancient 2. Philosophers – Greece 3. Greece – Intellectual life – To 146 B.C. I. O’Grady, Patricia F. 180 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask / Patricia F.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ancient Greek Philosophers, Motivated
    The ancient Greek philosophers and coaching In the pursue of Eudemonia (flouring life) The ancient Greek philosophers, motivated by their love of knowledge (the actual word “philosopher” derives from the Greek words “filos” and “Sophia” which mean “friend” and “wisdom” respectively) have been preoccupied with the investigation of the reasons for human existence and the way we should live, so as to be consistent with our reason for being. Their views widely appealed to the western world and formed the foundation for western philosophy and psychology, influencing the philosophers who followed, from the oldest to the most contemporary ones and inspiring passionate support but not without also being questioned. Today, most of their views seem to have lost nothing of their lustre and stand out like shining beacons, especially now that the western world is desperately seeking answers in order to relight its fires!!! In the text below, I refer to Aristotle and Socrates, the principles and practices they bequeathed us, so as to prove that these have a lot in common with the principles and practices of coaching. In addition, I will attempt to prove that Socrates is the first ever coach!!! Aristotle, a student of Socrates and Plato, the most important philosopher according to some and teacher of Great Alexander, clearly stated why and how men should live. According to Aristotle we should pursue happiness, well-being or in other words eudaimonia. And a happy life is a life full of virtue! o A coach urges us to lead a happy life. According to Aristotle, true happiness is permanent and timeless; it is achieved when people develop and leverage all their capabilities.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Compatibility of Augustine's Formal Account of Eudaimonia With
    1 The Compatibility of Augustine’s Formal Account of Eudaimonia with his Neoplatonic Metaphysics of Goodness. Abstract: Augustine’s moral philosophy follows the general pattern of ancient moral theory by distinguishing between the formal and substantive conceptions of ethical eudaimonism. In this paper, I develop Augustine’s ethical theory, demonstrating its grounding in both eudaimonism and Christian Neo- Platonism: the former provides its formal structure, the latter its substance or content, consisting in its metaphysical grounding and teleological end. In the first section, I consider the formal structure of Augustine’s ethics. Second, I argue God’s role as the summum bonum is grounded in Augustine’s Neo- Platonic metaphysics of goodness. Finally, I explore a puzzle raised by Augustine’s ethics: is loving God for His own sake compatible with loving God because it makes us happy? In other words, is Augustine’s formal account of eudaimonia compatible with the substance of his ethics informed by Christian Neoplatonism? 2 In De Moribus Ecclesiae Catholicae, Augustine makes two significant claims that summarize his moral philosophy. First, everyone desires happiness and this consists in loving man’s highest good. Second, since this highest good is identified with God himself, man’s happiness is only found in God.1 This pair of principles encapsulate two streams of ethical thought converging together to form Augustine’s moral philosophy, following the general pattern of ancient moral theory by distinguishing between the formal and substantive conceptions of ethical eudaimonism. In what follows, I develop Augustine’s moral philosophy, demonstrating its grounding in both eudaimonism and Christian Neoplatonism: the former provides its formal structure, the latter its substance or content, consisting in its metaphysical grounding and teleological end.
    [Show full text]
  • Sextus Empiricus and the Scientific Scepticism
    ENCEPHALOS 50, 62-74, 2013 SEXTUS EMPIRICUS AND THE SCIENTIFIC SCEPTI- CISM STAVROS J.BALOYANNIS* Summary philosophical books, which survived, but remained for long in obscurity, been rediscovered in the late Renaissance. Two Sextus Empiricus is the most eminent representative of these works on the title, “Adversus Mathematikus”, include of the ancient sceptisism, which is a Post-Classical, Hellenis- large number of strong arguments against the Logicians, the tic philosophy based on the criterion of life, the experience Physicists and the Ethicists. The third and most important of and the analysis of phenomena, aiming to provide a straight the books on the title “Outlines of Pyrrhonism” provides an out- and practical way of life, leading to interior peace and mental line of Pyrrhonian scepticism, incorporating at the same time tranquility, sharply opposed to a purely theoretical pursuit of his own philosophical doctrines. Sextus offers thoroughly a dogmatic philosophy. The term “sceptic” is a derivative of the general overview of scepticism, describing and explaining the noun, skepsis (σκέψις), which means thought, examination, meaning of the sceptical investigation, the value of suspen- inquiry, consideration, meditation and investigation. The scep- sion of judgment and the importance of the sceptical dialectics. tical school was connected for a long period of time with the Sextus insists that the skepticism does not accept or reject any Empirical school of physicians, who based the good medical impression and substantially does not affirm or deny anything. practice on the clinical experience rather than on the theoret- Sextus claims that appearances (φαινόμενα) are the practical ical erudition, dedicating themselves to observation, memory criteria of approaching to the truth and by the continuous inves- and continuous clinical practice.
    [Show full text]
  • Happiness in Ancient Philosophy
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Helsingin yliopiston digitaalinen arkisto Happiness in Ancient Philosophy Juha Sihvola Helsinki Collegium for Advanced Studies The article discusses the conceptions of eudaimonia in the philosophy of Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics and argues against the growing tendency to make a sharp distinction between the ancient notion of eudaimonia and the modern notion of happiness. On the contrary, the traditional translation of eudaimonia as happiness is defended because it emphasizes the powerfulness of the challenge that the ancient eudaimonistic theories of ethics provide for our contemporary ways of thinking. Comparison with the ancient views encourages us to reject a purely subjective conception of happiness, defined with a reference to beliefs that one is getting the important things one wants and accompanying pleasant affects. The paradigm of happiness as subjective desire-satisfaction is shown to disregard the notion’s more objective aspects which can be uncovered by philosophical reflection. At the beginning of his famous Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle states that his aim is to determine what the ultimate end or good is that human beings aim at in their lives (I 2, 1094a18–28). He spells out certain formal criteria that this final end should fulfill: it is something complete and self-sufficient, something we aim at for its own sake and not for the sake of anything else. When we have reached this end, our lives are as good as they can possibly become; nothing further can improve our lives in any way.
    [Show full text]
  • Can an Ancient Greek Sceptic Be Eudaimôn (Or Happy)? and What Difference Does the Answer Make to Us?
    Journal of Ancient Philosophy Vol. VI 2012 Issue 1 Can an ancient Greek sceptic be eudaimôn (or happy)? And what difference does the answer make to us? Richard Bett (Johns Hopkins University) The paper explores how far the ancient Greek sceptics in fact accept, and how far they should accept, the central Greek ethical notion of eudaimonia , usually translated "happiness" - and what, if anything, the answers may tell us today. The first section shows that sceptics of both the Academic and Pyrrhonist traditions frequently employ the notion of eudaimonia , apparently without discomfort. The second section draws attention to a contrast within the relevant works of Sextus Empiricus - one of them being willing to speak of the sceptic's eudaimonia and the other entirely avoiding this - and considers some possible reasons why, at some point in his life, Sextus might have found the notion problematic. The answers suggested are, first, that the term eudaimonia , at least as normally used by non-sceptical philosophers, presupposes that it is possible to rank human lives objectively in terms of their levels of well-being, and second, that the term standardly carries with it a commitment to a certain kind of long-term structure in one's life; there is at least a serious question whether either of these is consistent with sceptical suspension of judgement. The third section examines how far a sceptic could aspire to happiness , where this is not assumed to be equivalent to eudaimonia , and touches on several modern philosophers who have focused on happiness or, more generally, on well- being.
    [Show full text]
  • Sextus Was No Eudaimonist
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 7-14-2008 Sextus was no Eudaimonist Joseph B. Bullock Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Bullock, Joseph B., "Sextus was no Eudaimonist." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2008. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/40 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. SEXTUS WAS NO EUDAIMONIST by JOSEPH B. BULLOCK Under the Direction of Dr. Tim O’Keefe ABSTRACT Ancient Greek philosophical schools are said to share a common structure in their ethical theories which is characterized by a eudaimonistic teleology based in an understanding of human nature. At first glance, the skepticism of Sextus Empiricus as described in the Outlines of Pyrrhonism seems to fit into this model insofar as he describes the end of the skeptic as ataraxia, a common account of the expression of human happiness. I argue that this is a misunderstanding of Sextus’s philosophy for several reasons. “The end of skepticism” cannot be eudaimonistic or teleological in the way that other ancient ethical theories are typically understood; moreover, ataraxia is not an end derived from a theory about human nature. For these reasons, the skeptical way of life is radically different than the ethical theories proposed by other schools. I argue that this difference is a result of the character of the skeptical enterprise which involves the implicit rejection of norms in both the epistemological and the ethical spheres.
    [Show full text]
  • A Study on Dikaiosune and Eudaimonia in Plato's Republic
    A STUDY ON DIKAIOSUNE AND EUDAIMONIA IN PLATO’S REPUBLIC A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES OF MIDDLE EAST TECHNICAL UNIVERSITY BY EYLÜL ŞENTUNA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF SCIENCE IN THE DEPARTMENT PHILOSOPHY FEBRUARY 2012 i Approval of the Graduate School of Social Sciences _____________________ Prof. Dr. Meliha Altunışık Director I certify that this thesis satisfies all the requirements as a thesis for the degree of Master of Science of Philosophy. _____________________ Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam Head of Department This is to certify that we have read this thesis and that in our opinion it is fully adequate, in scope and quality, as a thesis for the degree of Master of Science of Philosopy. _____________________ Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam Supervisor Examining Committee Members Assoc. Prof. Ertuğrul R. TURAN (AU,PHIL) _____________________ Prof. Dr. Ahmet İNAM (METU,PHIL) ______________________ Assist. Prof. Elif ÇIRAKMAN (METU,PHIL) ______________________ ii I hereby declare that all information in this document has been obtained and presented in accordance with academic rules and ethical conduct. I also declare that, as required by these rules and conduct, I have fully cited and referenced all material and results that are not original to this work. Name, Last name : Eylül Şentuna Signature : iii ABSTRACT A STUDY ON DIKAOSUNE AND EUDAIMONIA IN PLATO’S REPUBLIC Şentuna, Eylül M.S., Department of Philosophy Supervisor: Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam February 2012, 74 pages The aim of this study is to analyze the concept of dikaiosunê in Plato’s Republic with its main aspects.
    [Show full text]