Husserl's Conception of Experiential Justification: What It Is and Why It

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Husserl's Conception of Experiential Justification: What It Is and Why It Husserl Stud https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-018-9225-8 Husserl’s Conception of Experiential Justification: What It Is and Why It Matters Philipp Berghofer1 Ó The Author(s) 2018. This article is an open access publication Abstract The aim of this paper is twofold. The first is an interpretative one as I wish to provide a detailed account of Husserl’s conception of experiential justifi- cation. Here Ideas I and Introduction to Logic and Theory of Knowledge: Lectures 1906/07 will be my main resources. My second aim is to demonstrate the currency and relevance of Husserl’s conception. This means two things: Firstly, I will show that in current debates in analytic epistemology there is a movement sharing with Husserl the basic idea that certain experiences gain their justificatory force simply from their distinctive phenomenal character. Secondly, I shall reveal the benefits of Husserl’s specific version of this view. Thus, one of my aims is to show that debates in current analytic epistemology could profit from adopting certain Husserlian elements. More precisely, I will defend Husserl’s claim that perceptual experiences are justifiers due to their self-giving phenomenal character as opposed to the cur- rently popular view that it is the phenomenology of pushiness that makes them justifiers. To put it differently, what matters is what is originally given within experience and not how you feel about what is given. 1 Husserl’s Notion of Intuition and Some Epistemological Principles Thanks to the works of phenomenologists such as Dan Zahavi, David Woodruff Smith, and John Drummond, Husserl’s phenomenology plays a considerable role in current philosophy of mind. In current epistemology, however, the situation is quite different. Although Husserl’s phenomenology, especially his conception of intuition, offers a lot to enrich current debates on, for instance, epistemic & Philipp Berghofer [email protected] 1 Department for Philosophy, University of Graz, Heinrichstraße 26/6, 8010 Graz, Austria 123 Husserl Stud justification, evidence, moral perception, and moral intuition, there is, unfortunately, no noticeable Husserlian impact on the treatment of these issues in current analytic philosophy. It is one of the aims of this paper to serve as a starting point for changing this situation and for re-evaluating the relevance of Husserl for current analytic epistemology. The purpose of this paper, to be sure, is not to convince someone who champions a view radically different from Husserl’s to become a Husserlian-style epistemologist. Rather, the purpose is (1) to give a detailed account of Husserl’s conception of experiential justification, (2) to show that in current analytic epistemology there is a movement sharing with Husserl the basic idea that certain experiences gain their justificatory force simply from their distinctive phenomenal character, and (3) to highlight the advantages of Husserl’s specific version of such a phenomenological conception of experiential justification. Between phenomenology and current analytic epistemology, there is a great potential of rich and mutually beneficial synergies, which is why phenomenologists should engage in current debates. Thus, in a nutshell, the objective of this paper is to reveal what a phenomenological conception of experiential justification looks like and how Husserl’s specific version of such a conception is in some aspects superior to current alternative versions. Husserl’s phenomenological conception of experiential justification offers a novel and promising approach towards epistemic justification whose ingenuity, unfortunately, is often overlooked by commentators. By closely connecting epistemology and philosophy of mind, Husserl argues for the following four theses which might be regarded as the cornerstones of a Husserlian conception of experiential justification. E1: Justification-conferring experiences such as perceptual experiences exhibit the phenomenal character of originary givenness. E2: Originary presentive intuitions are a source of immediate justification. E3: Originary presentive intuitions are the ultimate source of justification. E4: Originary presentive intuitions are a source of justification precisely in virtue of their phenomenal character of originary givenness. That epistemology and philosophy of mind are intertwined in the sense that the fundamental epistemic principles are phenomenological principles in the spirit of E1-E4, expressing the basic idea that epistemic justification is determined by the phenomenal character of experiences, is a distinctively phenomenological claim and has been largely ignored or dismissed by contemporary analytic epistemology.1 Only very recently have certain philosophers in this tradition picked up this idea, as we shall see at the end of this paper.2 Especially E4 is a rather strong claim and it is the aim of this paper to show (1) that Husserl subscribes to E4 and (2) that current 1 To be fair, however, phenomenologists have also largely failed to make claims such as E1-E4 explicit, to develop them systematically, and to highlight their benefits by engaging with rival views. One of the rare occasions of a current phenomenologist explicitly interpreting Husserl as subscribing to E4 is Erhard (2012, p. 56, fn 25). 2 Among the few analytic philosophers who argue for closely connecting epistemology and philosophy of mind similarly to how it is proposed in the present paper is Declan Smithies whose (2014) convincingly highlights some of the benefits of such a close connection. 123 Husserl Stud debates in analytic epistemology could benefit from adopting E4. But first things first. So, what are originary presentive intuitions? Originary presentive intuitions are intentional acts in which the object/content is presented as ‘‘bodily present’’ (Hua XVI, p. 14), is given in a ‘‘fleshed out’’ manner (Hua XIX/1 1984, p. 458). These acts are contrasted with empty, signitive acts in which what is given to us is not the object in its actual presence but the object as something that is meant only (cf. especially Husserl’s Sixth Logical Investigation). The prime example of originary presentive acts are perceptual acts in which we are perceptually aware of the object in question.3 If you believe that there is a table in the room next to you, this belief is a signitive act. If you go and check and see the table, this perceptual experience is an intuitive act. Two clarifications are in order. First, Husserl uses the term ‘‘originary intuition’’ in a remarkably broad sense. Straightforward sense experiences of physical objects, categorial intuitions of states of affairs, essential intuitions of logical, or mathematical, or phenomenological truths, and introspective intuitions of one’s own mental states are all originary presentive intuitions.4 In his mature theory of value, Husserl insists that even value-ceptions (Wertnehmungen) are originary presentive acts (Hua XXX 1996, p. 287).5 Secondly, according to my reading, hallucinations and illusions can also be originary intuitions.6 This is important because if you have a perfect hallucination of a table in front of you, you are plausibly justified in believing that there is a table. In his ‘‘Principle of all Principles’’ (Ideas I, §24) Husserl leaves no doubt about the central role of intuition7: No conceivable theory can make us err with respect to the principle of all principles: that every originary presentive intuition is a legitimizing source of cognition, that everything originarily (so to speak, in its ‘‘personal’’ actuality) offered to us in ‘‘intuition’’ is to be accepted simply as what it is presented as being, but also only within the limits in which it is presented there. (Hua III/1, p. 51; 1982, p. 44) 3 An anonymous referee of this journal has rightfully pointed out that while it is true that for Husserl perceptual acts are the prime examples of originary presentive acts, this by no means implies that there is only one type of evidence. In his doctrine of the correlational a priori, Husserl links different types of evidence to different types of objects. Husserl distinguishes between inadequate, adequate, and apodictic evidence. According to my understanding, different types of evidence correspond to different types of originary givenness. We will briefly discuss this at the end of the paper. 4 There are different types of originary intuition and these different types of intuition correspond to different types of objects. This means that ‘‘the precise nature of the intuitive evidence at issue varies in dependence on the respective types of objects or states of affairs that the relating acts are directed towards.’’ (Rinofner-Kreidl 2014, p. 37). 5 Which means that the present paper has also crucial implications for meta-ethics. For the details and significance of a phenomenological intuitionism cf. Rinofner-Kreidl (2015). 6 For the claim that hallucinations also are (originary) intuitions cf. Erhard (2012, p. 57), who confirms this by referring to Hua XVI, p. 15. 7 In the present paper, whenever I use the term ‘‘intuition’’ what I mean is ‘‘originary presentive intuition.’’ This means that, in contrast to Husserl’s terminology, imaginative acts, for instance, do not count as intuitions. Imaginative acts are not originary presentive intuitions because, when I imagine an object O, O is not given in its actual presence. Note that this is only a terminological issue. 123 Husserl Stud While this passage unambiguously reveals the importance of intuition, it seems problematic that Husserl here talks about ‘‘cognition’’
Recommended publications
  • Taieb Review of Antonelli on Benussi
    Forthcoming in Dialectica. Mauro Antonelli. 2018. Vittorio Benussi in the History of Psychology: New Ideas of a Century Ago. Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind 21. Cham: Springer, 377 + xi pp. Hamid Taieb The history of phenomenology has not been a peaceful and autonomous process taking place independently of any competitors. On the contrary, from the very beginning of their inquiries, phenomenologists had to struggle with several rival explanatory schemes in psychology. The most important among them were physiological psychology (of various sorts) and psychoanalysis. Both of these scientific projects tried to minimize the importance of consciousness in the explanation of the mind, the first by treating consciousness as some sort of epiphenomenal outcome of brain and other nervous processes, the second by describing it as a blind domain, driven by underlying mental acts to which consciousness itself has no access. Interestingly, however, phenomenology did not ignore these two competing explanatory schemes; on the contrary, it entered into manifold discussion with them, trying to establish more and more precisely the division of (scientific) labour among these three approaches. Evidence of this engagement is plentiful. With respect to physiological psychology, the discussion goes as far back as Franz Brentano, who tried to combine his “descriptive psychology”, also called “descriptive phenomenology”, with “genetic psychology”, that is, physiological psychology; and it has had a long and complex history, up to the most recent papers published in the journal Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. With respect to psychoanalysis, phenomenologists such as Merleau-Ponty and Ricœur engaged in detail with the thought of Freud (who, by the way, had been a student of Brentano); there have also been more recent attempts to combine these two traditions, for example by Dieter Lohmar and Jagna Brudzinska in Founding Psychoanalysis Phenomenologically.
    [Show full text]
  • Erfahrung Und Analyse Experience and Analysis
    Erfahrung und Analyse Experience and Analysis Abstracts 27. Internationales Wittgenstein Symposium 8. – 14. August 2004 Kirchberg am Wechsel 27th International Wittgenstein Symposium August 8 – 14, 2004 Kirchberg am Wechsel Distributors Die Österreichische Ludwig Wittgenstein Gesellschaft The Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society Markt 63, A-2880 Kirchberg am Wechsel Österreich/Austria Gedruckt mit Unterstützung der Abteilung Kultur und Wissenschaft des Amtes der NÖ Landesregierung Redaktion: Maria Elisabeth Reicher und Johann Christian Marek Visuelle Gestaltung: Sascha Windholz Druck: Druckwerker, 1050 Wien 2 Abstracts IS EVERYTHING NAMEABLE? ANALYSIS AS THE VANISHING OF VALUE? C. Anthony Anderson, Santa Barbara, California Brian Armstrong, University Park, Pennsylvania Seeking a foundation for intensional logic, arguments Although the Tractarian notion of value has recently begun bearing on whether everything is nameable are examined to receive more scholarly attention, there is still no clear and all are found to be without force. These include Fre- account of this notion. While I can hardly offer such an ge’s on unsaturated functions, an Intuitionistic argument, a account here, I do believe that our theme of experience Leibnizian argument, and Graham Priest’s Berkelian ar- and analysis can be used to shed new light on the issue. gument. The reasoning of the Zermelo-König paradox This new light results from the interesting paradox that leading to the conclusion that all ordinals are nameable is opens up in the Tractatus with respect to value and our stated within a theory of possible languages and found theme: the value that we experience seems to vanish upon wanting. It is concluded that the question is entirely open.
    [Show full text]
  • A Sociological History of Lie Detection
    Ctmrhusf San Franeista "OtntnitW The Hidden Truth: A Sociological History of Lie D etection Susanne Weber, MSc London School of Economics and Political Science Thesis submitted in fulfilment of the Ph.D. in Sociology 1 UMI Number: U61BB79 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Dissertation Publishing UMI U613379 Published by ProQuest LLC 2014. Copyright in the Dissertation held by the Author. Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code. ProQuest LLC 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346 TJfeses F m z txary ot Potncai 114523 i I, Susanne Weber, hereby confirm that the work presented in this thesis is my own. Where information has been derived from other sources, I confirm that this has been indicated in the thesis. Signed: Susanne Weber Abstract Drawing on Foucault and the sociology of science and technology, this thesis traces the curious attempt that has been made over the last century to capture one of the most elusive social acts - the lie. This endeavour was made possible by the emergence of the human sciences, whose guiding belief was that the subject’s inner life could be made apparent by means of physiological measurements and therefore be controlled.
    [Show full text]
  • The Rise and Fall of the Graz School
    THE RISE AND FALL OF THE GRAZ SCHOOL Geert-Jan A. Boudewijnse1 The gestalt movement is generally considered to have begun with EHRENFELS’ (1890) seminal article On ‘Gestalt Qualities’ (see ASH, 1982, 1995; BOUDEW IJNSE, 1996; HARRINGTON, 1996; MACNAMARA & BOUDEWIJNSE, 1995). Thirty years later, in 1920, Wolfgang KÖHLER published Die physischen Gestalten in Ruhe und in stationären Zustand [The Physical Gestalten in Rest and in Immobile Condi- tion]. The gestalt notion, with its implications, was by then well thought out. Gener- ally, the Berlin gestalt school of Max WERTHEIMER, Kurt KOFFKA and Wolfgang KÖHLER was painted as the successor of EHRENFELS’ thought. The works of the Graz school - Alexius MEINONG, Stephan WITASEK and Vittorio BENUSSI - how- ever, pre-date those of the Berlin school by about 10 years. Furthermore, the first ar- ticle in which a member of the Berlin school clearly articulated his own position was written by KOFFKA in 1915, and it gave a detailed exposition and a well-thought-out criticism of the Graz school. The Berlin school developed, or at least presented itself, partly in contrast to the Graz school. This warrants a discussion of the Graz school, which also has an interesting lineage. BENUSSI was not an Austrian citizen; he car- ried an Italian passport. After World War I, therefore, he was forced to leave Austria for Italy, where Cesare MUSATTI became his principal student. MUSATTI, in turn, taught Fabio METELLI and Gaetano KANIZSA. KANIZSA, like BENUSSI, would propose a theory of perception in which two levels of processing are identified and which recognizes that the organism adds to the perceptual data.
    [Show full text]
  • TEN YEARS of ITALIAN HISTORIOGRAPHY of PSYCHOLOGY: a Field in Progress
    History of Psychology © 2010 American Psychological Association 2010, Vol. 13, No. 3, 215–249 1093-4510/10/$12.00 DOI: 10.1037/a0020093 TEN YEARS OF ITALIAN HISTORIOGRAPHY OF PSYCHOLOGY: A Field in Progress Glauco Ceccarelli Guido Cimino and Renato Foschi University of Urbino “Sapienza” University of Rome This article briefly outlines a picture of the activities and research conducted in Italy on the history of psychology during the last 10 years, focusing its attention on institutions, scholars, conferences, archives, journals, and so forth. At the dawn of the 21st century, the tradition of historical-psychological studies that developed in the last quarter of the 20th century has led to a renewed situation in teaching organization and research, with the emergence of several groups, especially at the universities of Rome “Sapienza,” Bari, Milan-Bicocca, and Urbino, and of a second generation of young historians increasingly engaged on an international level. After a general survey conducted with historiometric method on the principal areas of research cultivated and on the themes dealt with, we mention a change that has occurred in the historiographical approach, a transition from a historiography addressed prevalently to the “history of ideas” to one that, pursuing the approach of a new and critical “multifactorial” history, proves to be more attentive to the social and institutional history, in correspondence with established international trends. Keywords: Italian historiography of psychology, historiometry, old history, new history, multifactorial history An article published in this same journal in 2003 traced the itinerary of the historiography of psychology in Italy from the 1970s up to the threshold of the 21st century (Cimino & Dazzi, 2003).
    [Show full text]
  • Download Download
    c:\users\kenneth\documents\type3401\rj 3401 196 red.docx 2014-05-17 9:24 AM NOTES AND CORRESPONDENCE FOR RUSSELL’S 1905 REVIEW OF MEINONG Bernard Linsky Philosophy / U. of Alberta Edmonton, ab, Canada t6g 2e5 [email protected] Bertrand Russell took fourteen pages of notes on Meinong’s Unter- suchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psychologie [Studies in object theory and psychology] in preparation for his review of the book in Mind. Translations of Russell’s letters from Alexius Meinong, Rudolf Ameseder and Ernst Mally discuss their contributions to the volume (with transcriptions of the German originals appended in this journal’s online edition). Together the notes and correspondence record the or- igin of Russell’s famous criticisms of Meinong’s theory of non-existent objects, which appeared in both “On Denoting” and the review in Mind in October 1905. ertrand Russell published a review in Mind 1905 of a collection of papers by Alexius Meinong and his students, Untersuchun- =gen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psychologie (1904).1 The review _appeared later in the same issue of Mind as Russell’s most famous paper from 1905, “On Denoting”, in which Meinong’s views are dis- cussed in passing. To prepare for writing the review Russell read through the book’s contents, making several comments in the mar- gins, and then wrote fourteen leaves of notes on the articles that figure in the review. Russell also corresponded with Meinong and two of his authors, Ernst Mally and Rudolf Ameseder, in early 1905.2 The read- ing notes are described in the prefatory notes to the edition of the 1 “Review of Meinong and Others, Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psychol- ogie”, Mind 14 (Oct.
    [Show full text]
  • Gestalt Theory: an Essay in Philosophy
    Barry Smith Gestalt Theory: An Essay in Philosophy §1. Introduction The Austrian philosopher Christian von Ehrenfels published his essay "On 'Gestalt Qualities'" in 1890. The essay initiated a current of thought which enjoyed a powerful position in the philosophy and psychology of the first half of this century and has more recently enjoyed a minor resurgence of interest in the area of cognitive science, above all in criticisms of the so-called 'strong programme' in artificial intelligence. 1 The theory of Gestalt is of course associated most specifically with psychologists of the Berlin school such as Max Wertheimer, Wolfgang Kohler and Kurt Koffka. We shall see in what follows, however, that an adequate philosophical understanding of the Gestalt idea and of Ehrenfels' achievement will require a close examination not merely of the work of the Berlin school but also of a much wider tradition in Austrian and German philosophy in general. Ehrenfels' essay of 1890 was published in the 'journal of scientific philosophy' [Vierteljahrsschrift fur wissenschaftliche Philosophie1 edited by the positivist philosopher Richard Avenarius, and we can assume that Ehrenfels' decision to publish in Avenarius' journal was influenced by the fact that his essay had been provoked by certain passages on perception in the writings of Ernst Mach, with whom Avenarius is commonly associated. The most important influence on Ehrenfels' thinking was however that of his own principal teacher Franz Brentano, and Ehrenfels belongs to an impressive list of gifted and original thinkers - including Alexius Meinong, Edmund Husserl, Carl Stumpf, Anton Marty and Kasimir Twardowski - whose philosophy was shaped decisively by that of Brentano.
    [Show full text]
  • A Thesis Subrnitted to the Facuity of Graduate Studies and Research in Partial Fulfiiment of the Requirements of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy
    The gestalt line by Geert-Jan A. Boudewijnse Department of Psychology McGill University, Montreal A Thesis subrnitted to the Facuity of Graduate Studies and Research in partial fulfiiment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Al1 rights reserved Geert-Jan Adriaan Boudewijnse, 1996 National Library Bibliothèque nationale I*(of Canada du Canada Acquisitions and Acquisitions et Bibliographie Services services bibliographiques 395 Wellington Street 395. tue Wellington Ottawa ON KIA ON4 OttawaON KIA ON4 canada Canada The author has granted a non- L'auteur a accordé une licence non exclusive licence allowing the exclusive permettant à la National Library of Canada to Bibliothèque nationale du Canada de reproduce, loan, distribute or sell reproduire, prêter, distribuer ou copies of this thesis in microform, vendre des copies de cette thèse sous paper or electronic formats. la forme de rnicrofiche/~,de reproduction sur papier ou sur format électronique. The author retains ownership of the L'auteur conserve la propriété du copyright in this thesis. Neither the droit d'auteur qui protège cette thèse. thesis nor substantial extracts fkom it Ni la thèse ni des extraits substantiels may be prhted or otherwise de celle-ci ne doivent êeimprimés reproduced without the author's ou autrement reproduits sans son permission. autorisation. CONTENTS RES UME ACKNOWLEDGMENTS TRANSLATOR'S NOTE INTRODUCTION The lineage General Framework Previous work on the history of gestalt theory Overview FRANZ BRENTANO Aristotelean roots Unity of consciousness
    [Show full text]
  • Franz Brentano's Ontology - Selected Bibliography (A - K)
    Franz Brentano's Ontology - Selected bibliography (A - K) https://www.ontology.co/biblio/brentanof-biblio-one.htm Theory and History of Ontology by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] Selected Bibliography on Brentano's Contributions to Logic and Ontology. First Part: A - K BIBLIOGRAPHICAL RESOURCES 1. Paolo Gregoretti. 1983. Franz Brentano. Bibliografia completa (1862-1982), Trieste,:Università degli Studi. Contents: I. Works by Franz Brentano 7; II. Translations 21; III. Studies on Brentano 25; Index of Authors 81-87. 2. Wilhelm Baumgartner and F. P. Burkard. 1990. Franz Brentano Bibliographie in: International Bibliography of Austrian Philosophy 1982/83 - Internationale Bibliographie zur osterreichischen Philosophie - Compiled with assistance of Thomas Binder, Jutta Valent, Helmut Werba, Amsterdam: Rodopi. Contents: Teil I / Part I. 1. W. L. Gombocz: Vorwort 7; Literaturhinweis zur IBÖP / Bibliographical Notes 13; 2. Bildnis / Portrait: Franz Brentano 16; 3. W. Baumgartner, F.-P. Burkard: Franz Brentano. Eine Skizze seines Lebens und seiner Werke 17; 4. W. Baumgartner, F.-P. Burkard: Franz-Brentano- Bibliographie 54; 5. Hinweise für den Gebrauch der Bibliographie und register 161; 6. How to use Bibliography and Index 166-170. 3. Liliana Albertazzi. 2006. Immanent Realism. An Introduction to Brentano, Dordrecht: Springer. Bibliographic notes pp. 341-354. BIBLIOGRAPHY 1. "Die Philosophie Franz Brentanos." 1978. Grazer Philosophische Studien no. 5. Special Issue. Contributions to the Brentano-Konferenz Graz, 4-8 September 1977 (Edited
    [Show full text]
  • The Rise of the Brentano School
    The Rise of the Brentano School Arnaud Dewalque Franz Brentano’s works are not just full of deep and innovative insights into mind, world and values. His views also turned out to be highly influential upon several generations of students, who made them the basis of their own philosophical investigations, giving rise to what is known as the Brentano School (Albertazzi et al. 1996; Fisette & Fréchette 2007). In this chapter, I give a bird’s eye view of the Brentano School from a rather historical perspective. My leading hypothesis is that one crucial factor explaining the rise of the school is Brentano’s unique strategy, within the academic context of the time, to promote the revival of philosophy as a rigorous science. After a brief introduction, I reconstruct the three main phases in the school’s development, namely Brentano’s teaching in Würzburg (1866-73), his teaching in Vienna (1874-95), and Anton Marty’s teaching in Prague (1880-1913). 1. Introduction On a merely factual understanding, the ‘Brentano School’ encompasses all the philosophers who, at a certain stage of their academic path, were Brentano’s students or students’ students. There is evidence that the notion of “school” was used by Brentano and his students in a self-referential fashion at least from 1873 onwards. In his correspondence with Carl Stumpf, Brentano occasionally refers to what he calls “our overall philosophical orientation” or “our school” (Brentano 1989: 44, 128). It is not rare for his students themselves to talk about the ‘Brentano School’, be it to express their debt to Brentano’s teaching or to distance themselves from what they take to be sheer Brentanian orthodoxy.1 The question as to whether the phrase ‘Brentano School’ may be understood in a stronger sense, to name a group of authors whose ‘philosophical orientation’ was roughly the same, is disputable and is better left unanswered at the outset.
    [Show full text]
  • Original Contributions - Originalbeiträge
    Original Contributions - Originalbeiträge MONA LISA’S SMILE: THE PLACE OF EXPERIMENTAL PHENOMENOLOGY WITHIN GESTALT THEORY Ian Verstegen In memory of Paolo Bozzi For years brilliant research has issued from the Italian school of Gestalt psychol- ogy.* Psychologists trained in the gestalt tradition and working outside of Italy, how- ever, may be puzzled by the recent occurrence of Italian research conducted under the banner of “experimental phenomenology” (fenomenologia sperimentale) (KANIZSA 1983; BOZZI 1989; MASSIRONI 1998). Indeed, most of the best experimental psychologists trained by Gaetano KANIZSA and Fabio METELLI, including Paolo BOZZI, Giovanni VICARIO, Manfredo MASSIRONI, Ugo SAVARDI and others have taken up this mantra, going so far as to establish the “Laboratory of the Experi- mental Phenomenology of Perception” [Laboratorio della fenomenologia sperimen- tale della percezione] in Verona (e.g., BIANCHI & SAVARDI 2002). At fi rst sight this appears to be an outright rejection of training in Gestalt psychol- ogy in the manner of Irvin ROCK’s famous move toward cognitive inferentialism. Indeed, there is complexly related to the rise of Experimental Phenomenology a move toward GIBSONian realism or Austrian (as opposed to classic Berlin) theorizing. It is the purpose of this article to examine the writings of the various practitioners of Experimental Phenomenology to see exactly what their theoretical commitments are. As we shall see, the hegemony of Gestalt psychology is taken for granted in Italy so the change of terminology is not as drastic as might at fi rst be thought. Instead, Experimental Phenomenology carries on many commitments with Gestalt psychol- ogy. This is the recent conclusion of Mario ZANFORLIN (2004) who sifts through the various writings of Italian psychologists to extract where things stand.
    [Show full text]
  • Psychologists—Italy—Florence— Biography
    Italian and Italian American Studies Stanislao G. Pugliese Hofstra University Series Editor This publishing initiative seeks to bring the latest scholarship in Italian and Italian American his- tory, literature, cinema, and cultural studies to a large audience of specialists, general readers, and students. The Italian and Italian American Series will feature works on modern Italy (Renaissance to the present) and Italian American culture and society by established scholars as well as new voices in the academy. This endeavor will help to shape the evolving fields of Italian and Italian American Studies by re-emphasizing the connection between the two. The following editorial board consists of esteemed senior scholars who act as advisers to the series editor. REBECCA WEST JOSEPHINE GATTUSO HENDIN University of Chicago New York University FRED GARDAPH É PHILIP V. CANNISTRARO † Queens College, CUNY Queens College and the Graduate School, CUNY ALESSANDRO PORTELLI Universit à di Roma “La Sapienza” Queer Italia: Same-Sex Desire in Italian Literature and Film edited by Gary P. Cestaro July 2004 Frank Sinatra: History, Identity, and Italian American Culture edited by Stanislao G. Pugliese October 2004 Th e Legacy of Primo Levi edited by Stanislao G. Pugliese December 2004 Italian Colonialism edited by Ruth Ben-Ghiat and Mia Fuller July 2005 Mussolini’s Rome: Rebuilding the Eternal City Borden W. Painter Jr. July 2005 Representing Sacco and Vanzetti edited by Jerome H. Delamater and Mary Anne Trasciatti September 2005 Carlo Tresca: Portrait of a Rebel Nunzio Pernicone October 2005 Italy in the Age of Pinocchio: Children and Danger in the Liberal Era Carl Ipsen April 2006 Th e Empire of Stereotypes: Germaine de Sta ë l and the Idea of Italy Robert Casillo May 2006 Race and the Nation in Liberal Italy, 1861–1911: Meridionalism, Empire, and Diaspora Aliza S.
    [Show full text]