<<

Lawrence Berkeley National Laboratory Recent

Title Quantum Theory and the Place of Mind in Nature

Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/34m6076z

Author Stapp, H.P.

Publication Date 1993

eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California LBL-33552 UC-414

·t Lawrence Berkeley Laboratory UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Division

To be published as a chapter in and Contempory Philosophy, J. Faye and H.J. Folse, Eds., K.luwer, Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1993

Quantum Theory and the Place of Mind in Nature

H.P. Stapp

January 1993

.. U1 d ~ A~~------~------~1 t"4 t"4 l:xl 1-'· t"4 0"' C"l I 11 0 w Prepared for the U.S. Department of under Contract Number DE-AC03-76SF00098 Ill 'tl w 11 '< U1 '< U1 1\.) DISCLAIMER

This document was prepared as an account of work sponsored by the United States Government. Neither the United States Government nor any agency thereof, nor The Regents of the University of Califor­ nia, nor any of their employees, makes any warranty, express or im­ plied, or assumes any legal liability or responsibility for the accuracy, completeness, or usefulness of any , apparatus, product, or process disclosed, or represents that its use would not infringe pri­ vately owned rights. Reference herein to any specific commercial product, process, or service by its trade name, trademark, manufac­ turer, or otherwise, does not necessarily constitute or imply its en­ dorsement, recommendation, or favoring by the United States Gov­ ernment or any agency thereof, or The Regents of the University of California. The views and opinions of authors expressed herein do not necessarily state or reflect those of the United States Government or any agency thereof or The Regents of the University of California and shall not be used for advertising or product endorsement pur­ poses.

Lawrence Berkeley Laboratory is an equal opportunity employer.

.,.

This publication has been reproduced from the best available copy DISCLAIMER

This document was prepared as an account of work sponsored by the United States Government. While this document is believed to contain correct information, neither the United States Government nor any agency thereof, nor the Regents of the University of California, nor any of their employees, makes any warranty, express or implied, or assumes any legal responsibility for the accuracy, completeness, or usefulness of any information, apparatus, product, or process disclosed, or represents that its use would not infringe privately owned rights. Reference herein to any specific commercial product, process, or service by its trade name, trademark, manufacturer, or otherwise, does not necessarily constitute or imply its endorsement, recommendation, or favoring by the United States Government or any agency thereof, or the Regents of the University of California. The views and opinions of authors expressed herein do not necessarily state or reflect those of the United States Government or any agency thereof or the Regents of the University of California. \.

January 29, 1993 LBL-33552

Quantum Theory and the Place of Mind in Nature. •

Henry P. Stapp

Theoretical Physics Group Physics Division Lawrence Berkeley Laboratory 1 Cyclotron Road Berkeley, California 94720

Contribution to the vohune: Niels Bohr and Contemporary Philosophy. Editors: Jan Faye and Henry J.Folse.

*This work was supported by the Director, Office of Energy Research, Office of High Energy and , Division of High Energy Physics of the U.S. Department of Energy under Contract DE-AC03-76SF00098.

Classical physics can be viewed as a triumph of the idea that mind should be excluded from science, or at least from the physical sciences. Although the founders of modern science, such as Descartes and Newton, were not so rash as to proclaim that mind has nothing to do with the unfolding of nature, the of succeeding centuries, emboldened by the spectacular successes of the mechanical view of nature, were not so timid, and today we are seeing even in psychology a strong movement toward "materialism", i.e., toward the idea that "mind is brain". But while psychology has been moving toward the mechanical concepts of ninetieth-centUry physics, physics itself has moved in just the opposite. direction. The mentalistic bias of contemporary physics is perhaps best summarized in Heisenberg's statement that "we are finally led to believe that the laws of nature that we formulate mathematically in quantum theory deal no longer with the themselves but with our knowledge of the elementary particles. • .. The conception of the objective reality of the particles bas thus evaporated in a curious way, not into a fog of some new, obscure, or not yet understood reality concept, but into the transparent clarity of a mathematics that represents no longer the behavior of the elementary particles but rather our knowledge of this behavior." (Heisenberg 1958a, p. 99-100) This shift in the 's conception of nature, or at least in his con­ ception of his theory about nature, away from the mechanical and toward the experiential is expressed also by Bohr'~ statements: "In our description of na­ ture the purpose is not to disclose the real essence of phenomena but only to track down as far as possible relations between the multifold aspects of experi­ ence". (Bohr 1934, p. 18). "As the goal of science is to augment and order our experience... ." (Bohr 1958, p.88) Bohr and Heisenberg each sought to deflate the idea that either he, or quantum theory itself, was asserting that the character of nature herself was essentially mental. Bohr emphasized that quantum theory was merely a tool for making predictions about our experiences: "Strictly speaking, the mathematical formalism of quantum and electrodynamics merely offers rules· of calculation for the deduction of expectations about observations obtained under · well defined conditions specified by classical physical concepts." (Bohr 1963, ,. p.60) Heisenberg went even further: "If we want to describe what happens in

I. 1 an atomic event we have to realize that the word 'happens' ... applies to the physical not the psychical act of observation, and we may say that the transition . from the 'possible' to the·'actual' takes place as soon as the interaction between the [atomic] ·object a.il.d the measuring device, and thereby with the rest of the world has come into play; it is not connected with the act of registration of the result in the mind of the observer. The discontinuous change in the probability function, however, takes place with the act of registration, because it is the discontinuous change in our knowledge in the instant of registration that has its image in the discontinuous change in the probability function~ (Heisenberg 1958b, p.54) The final sentence affirms Heisenberg's position that the mathematical probability function of quantum theory represents "our knowledge". However, the statements that precede it affirm his belief that there are also some real "happenings" outside the minds of the human observers, and that these exter­ nal events have the character of transitions of the "possible" to the "actual". To describe these external events themselves in mathematical form one can introduce the idea of an objective function-- a wave function that is like the one of Bohr and Heisenberg with respect to it~ mathematical properties (i.e., evolution·via the Schrodinger equation etc.), but that represents the exter- . nal world itself, and changes when the transitions from "possible" to "actual" take place, rather than with the registration of a result in the mind of the ob­ server/. This procedur~ would seem to be a·,reason:able step toward providing a conceivable description nature herself, since it would allow the de- . . tailed and precise mathematical properties represented in quantum theory to be understood directly as mathematical characteristics of the world itself. This transformation can be termed the ontologicalization of quantum th~ry: it con­ verts that theory from a structure conceived to be a mere tool for scientists - a tool to be used for very limited purposes - to a putative description of nature herself. / If we follow this tack, and endeavor to construe the mathematical structure represented by quantum theory as a feature of the world itself, then we may ask: What is the nature of that world? What sort of world do we live in? The world represented by an ontogically interpreted quantum theory, with the quantum jumps representing transitions from "possible" to "actual", would .I 2 be a strange sort of beast. The evolving quantum st~te, although controlled in part by mathematical laws that are direct analogs of the laws that in govern the motion of "", no longer represents anything substan­ tive. Instead, this evolving quantum state would represent the "potentialities" and "probabilities" for actual events. Thus the "primal stuff" represented by the evolving quantum state would be idealike in character rather than matterlike, apart from its conformity to mathematical rules. On the other hand, mathemat­ ics has seemed, at least since the of Plato, t:<> be more a resident of a world ·. of ideas than a structure in the world of matter. Hence even this mathematical aspect of nature can be regarded as basically idealike. Indeed, quantum theory provides a detailed and explicit example of how an idealike primal stuff can be controlled in part by mathematical rules based in spacetime. The actual events in quantum theory are likewise idealike: each such hap­ pening is a choice that selects as "the actual", in a way not controlled by ~y 4 known or purported mechanical law, one of the potentialities generated by the . quantUm. mechanical law of evolution. . ,,'" In view of these uniformly idealike characteristics of the quantum· physical world, the proper answer our question "What sort of world do we live in?" would seem to be this:. "We live in an idealike world, not a matterlike world." The material aspects are exhausted in certain mathematical properties, and these mathematical features can be understood just as well (and irrfact better) as characteristics of an evolving idealike structure. There is, in fact, in the quantum universe no natural place for matter. This conclusion, curiously, is the exact reverse of the circumstance that in the classical physical universe there was no·natural place for mind. These remarks may appear to be nothing but a word game. But I think not. The change in our words indicates a change in our perception. By changing our perception of the kind of worid we live in we change our perception of the · possibilities. If some of the-possibilities. opened up by this altered perception of , the basic nature of the physical world can be actualized within science then this change of words and perceptions will certainly count for something. One possibility immediately opened up by this change is the possibility of integrating human consciousness into the physical sciences. This possibility was effectively blocked off when physical science meant, in the final analysis,

,_ 3 classical physics. For there is an enormous conceptual gulf between the clas­ sical physicist's conceptualization of the physical world and the psychologist's conceptualization of the mental world. The ~ce of the classical physicist's conception of matter is its locaJ.:...reductionistic nature: the idea that the physi­ cal world can be decomposed into elementary iocaJ. quantities that interact only with immediately adjacent neighbors. But conscious thoughts appear to be com:­ plex wholes, not merely at the functional level but also as directly experienced. Insofar as the experienced of a conscious .thought constitutes its essence it is not possible to conceptualize a thought as a resident of the physical world, as that world was conceived of in classical physics. To bring a human conscious thought into the physicist's conception of the physical world one needs, within that conception, something having, in its essence, the integrity and complexity of that thought. ·The world as it is conceived of in clas8ical. physics is essentially reductive and therefore admits no essentially complex wholes. This problem of unity is brought into clear focus by Daniel Dennett's recent book Consciousness Explained (1991). The thesis of the book is that brain processes proceed in "parallel pandemonium", with each of the processing units doing its own thing. , The problem is then to bring the outputs of all these processes together into the integrated forms that we seem to experience in our stream of conscious thoughts. Dennett argues that this integration is, in fact, . not possible, and hence that our thoughts cannot be u;hat they seem to be. This conclusion may indeed by what would emerge from a classical concep­ tion of what is going on in

4 Yet neither of these problems seems to .be in, principle beyond the bounds of rational explanation, within the quantum framework, which as explained earlier ,. provides an intricate tapestry of idealike qualities. The line of thinking described above has led to a serious attempt (Stapp 1993) to bring human conscious experience into the quantum mechanical de­ scription of natur~. This endeavor, though hardly eomplete, is, I believe, suffi­ ciently successful to warrant considerable optimism as regards the prospects of ultimate success: a great deal of empirical information that had seemed very puzzling from a classical point ofview now falls neatly into place.

In view of these developments I believe that th~ verdict of history will .be that the Copenhagen interpretation was a half-way house: it was a right face that was the first step of an about face. The scientific commUnity has, rightly, a considerable amount of intertia. A complete turn around on the basic classical idea that mind shotdd be rigorously excluded from the the6ry of the workings of the material universe was neither possible nor warranted during the twenties and thirties. Any attempt to corre­ late the revolutionary findings in the domain of atomic physics to the subtleties of the connection between mind and brain would have been extravagantly pre­ mature in view of the then-prevailing ruditrtentary state of our understanding of the workings of the brain. The appropriate course of action was first to see how far the new quantum ideas would carry us in domains that were, under better empirical control. During the past twenty years, however, the Copenhagen interpretation has lost a good deal of its hold on the minds of . The words of Murray Gell.., Mann (1979, p.29) give an indication of this shift: "Niels Bohr brain-washed a whole generation of physicists into believing that the problem had been solved fifty years ago". The reasons for this change in attitude are many and diverse. One impor­ tant reason is the expansion of the scope of quantum theory. The theory was originally designed to cover the domain of atomic physics, and was therefore con­ . cerned things with that were far beyond the range of our direct observation, and were thus approachable only indirectly with the aid of sophisticated measuring devices. Now, however, a problem that looms large in the minds of physicists is \.

5 quantwn , which deals with quantum effects at the creation of the uni­ verse, and in the evolution of black holes. These phenomena are quite unlike the laboratory experiments in atomic physics that physicists were focussing on during the beginning of the century. The atomic-physics fo~at of preparation­ then-measurement fails to apply these new problems. On the other hand, the ontological approach is far more demanding in terms of logical cohesion. The additional constraints imposed by the demand for a coherent ontology can pro­ vide guidance in our attempts to extend physical theory into the interesting new . domains. A second reason for the loosening of the grip of the Copenhagen interpreta­ tion is the fall out from the 1964 paper of John Bell. The startling ch~ of Bell's results caused physicists to take a careful look at the whole Bohr-Einstein controversy, and this left many of them with an uneasy sense that something important was perhaps being obscured by Bohr's subtle epistemological reason­ ings, which did not clearly do justice to the arguments of. Einstein pertaining to locality. A third reason for the fading influence of the Copenhagen interpretation is the construction by David Bohm (1952) of a thoroughly realistic model that reproduces all. of the predictions of quantum theory. This model laid to rest an opinion that was in the background of Copenhagen thinking, namely the idea that it was simply impossible to understand atomic phenomena in a realistic way. Although mcist physicists did not accept the idea that Bohm's simple model describes the way things really work, they were nonetheless quickly disabused of the impression that Bohr (or von Neumann) had showed that all realistic approaches were necessarily doomed to fail. A fourth reason lies in the philosopJ:Ycal climate of the . During the early part of this century physicists were reeling from the ~pact of the loss of the "either" and "absolute time". The whole idea that the universe could be underStood in a completely clear mechanical way had been shattered. How could there be in a void: waves in a devoid of a medium? How cocld one·understand.the unfolding of our thoughts if there were no similar unfolding of nature hei:-self; i.e., if the whole of spacetime history already "exists", as relativity theory seemed to require. The swallowing of such mysteries seemed to condition physicists not to balk at the even greater mysteries that quantum

6 theory left unresolved. Fuithermore, the parallel behav_ioristic movement in psychology, which also focussed on measurable quantities at the expense of any understanding of the unfolding stream of conscious thoughts, seemed to place all of science on the same operational track. Now, however, the behaviorist approach to psychology seems to have failed, for technical reasons (Baars, 1986). In psychology as in physics scientists are finding that increasingly complex models are needed to account for the complex­ ity of the empirical data. But in the search for suitable complex models some orientation is needed. The data alone is insufficient: one needs some philosophy, and not merely an austere philosophy that reci:>mmends exclusive focussing upon the empirical facts obtained in a single narrow discipline. The insufficiency of the data in the various narrow disciplines, taken separately, is forcing scientists to bring into their theorizing information from an increasingly broad band of fields. Now in physics; for example,· the problem of the innermost structure of the is intertwined with the problem of the birth of the entire wiiverse. physics, , and have merged into one field, at least at the level of theory. Bold conceptions of large scope are needed to tie all these things together. The epistemological formulation of the Oopenhagen interpretation seems, in the face of this complex situation, insufficiently helpful. Einstein's {1951) words in this conneCtion are worth recalling: "It is my opinion that the contemporary quantum theory by IDea.J;lS of certain definitely laid down basic concepts, which on the whole are taken over from classical physics, constitutes an optimum formulation of (certain] connections. I believe, however, that this theory offers no useful point of departure for future development." H what Eins~in was judging to be insufficient was a science based upon the Separation of the world into an ineffable nonclassical reality, and a then­ unexplained classical character of our perceptions of that reality, then his judge­ ment probably accords with the contemporary developments in science. But if, on the other hand, the nonclassical mathematical regularities identified by quantum theory are accepted as characteristics of the world itself, a world whose primal stuff is therefore essentially idealike, and if, moreover, these mathematical properties account in a natural and understandable way for the classical charac­ teristic of our conscious perceptions,· as they seem to do (Stapp 1993), then we

'-' 7 appear to have found in quanttl.ffi theory the foundation for a science that may \ be able to deal successfully in a mathematically and logically coherent way with the full range of scientific thought, from atomic physics, to biology, to cosmol­ ogy, including also the area that had been so mysterious within the framework of classical physics, namely the connection between processes in human brains and the stream of human conscious experience.

Reference List

Baars, Bernard J. {1986) The Cognitive RevolUtion in Psychology. Ne~ York: Guilford Pr. Bohm, David {1952) "A suggested interpretation of quantum theory in terms of 'hidden' variables I." Physical Review 85:166-179. Bohr, Niels {1934) Atomic Physics and the Description of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Px:ess. Bohr, Niels (1958) Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge. New York: Wiley • Bohr, Niels (1963) Essays 1958/62 on Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge. · New York: Random House. Dennett, Daniel {1991) Consciousness El-j}lained. New York: Little, Brown and Co. Einstein, Albert {1951) in Philosopher-Sqentist, ed. P.A. Schilpp, New York: Thdor Publishing Co. Gell-Mann, Murray (1919) In The Nature of the Physical Universe, the 1976 Nobel Conference. New York: Wiley. Heisenberg, Werner {1958a) Daedalas 87 95-108 - (1985b) Physics and Philosophy. New York: Harper and Rowe. Stapp, Henry P. {1993) Mind, Matter, and . Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag.

8 --=-

~ -

LA~NCEBERKELEYLABORATORY -~ UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA 1ECHNICAL INFORMATION DEPARTMENT BERKELEY, CALIFORNIA 94720