Collingwood's Philosophy of Art As a Basis for Virtue Aesthetics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Collingwood's Philosophy of Art As a Basis for Virtue Aesthetics COLLINGWOOD’S PHILOSOPHY OF ART AS A BASIS FOR VIRTUE AESTHETICS by David Collins B.F.A., Film & Video, York University, 2002 M.F.A., Film & Video, York University, 2005 A thesis presented to Ryerson University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in the Program of Philosophy Toronto, Ontario, Canada, 2014 © (David Collins) 2014 AUTHOR’S DECLARATION FOR ELECTRONIC SUBMISSION OF A THESIS I hereby declare that I am the sole author of this thesis. This is a true copy of the thesis, including any required final revisions, as accepted by my examiners. I authorize Ryerson University to lend this thesis to other institutions or individuals for the purpose of scholarly research. I further authorize Ryerson University to reproduce this thesis by photocopying or by other means, in total or in part, at the request of other institutions or individuals for the purpose of scholarly research. I understand that my thesis may be made electronically available to the public. ii ABSTRACT In this thesis I show how Aristotle’s approach to ethics can be applied to aesthetics in order to address normative concerns relating to practices of artistic creation and spectatorship, and how R. G. Collingwood’s philosophy of art provides an understanding of these practices that works as a basis for such an approach. I begin by discussing the connection between aesthetic and ethical normativity as found in the thought of various prominent philosophers, and review the contemporary work done in the name of ‘virtue aesthetics’. I then explicate Aristotle’s ethics, with a particular focus on his definition of virtue and his discussion of practical wisdom, and give an overview of Collingwood’s understanding of art and the role of imagination in artistic expression and understanding, before synthesizing the structure of Aristotle’s ethics with the content of Collingwood’s philosophy of art in order to arrive at an outline of a Collingwoodian virtue aesthetics. iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I should like to thank Prof. Elizabeth (‘Betty’) Trott for her work in supervising this thesis, especially the amount of time she spent reading, re-reading and commenting on various drafts, and for the interest she showed in the connection of aesthetics and morality and in the practical applicability of philosophical ideas; Prof. R. Jo Kornegay for agreeing to act as second reader and for her detailed and rigorous feedback, especially on the sections dealing with Aristotle and contemporary virtue ethics; and Prof. R. Bruce Elder for stepping in at fairly short notice to act as my external examiner, and for the questions he posed during my defense. Thanks also go to the other Davids in the department: Prof. David Hunter, Graduate Program Director, for encouraging my desire to pursue the thesis option and for his support with scholarship applications and funding for conferences; Prof. David Checkland, for suggesting that I look at MacIntyre’s After Virtue in connection with this project; Prof. David Ciavatta, for reviewing the sections on Kant’s and Schiller’s aesthetics; and Prof. David Rondel of the University of Nevada, formerly of Ryerson, for discussions last year about the moral dimensions of art and for sharing his recent aesthetics-related paper with me before its publication. I should also like to thank Prof. Boris Hennig for discussing certain of Aristotle’s ideas with me, and for providing several translations of the original Greek; Prof. Glenn Parsons for clarifying which aspects of Collingwood’s thought I should focus on explaining in order to try to clear up the misunderstandings still prevalent among many contemporary analytic aestheticians; and Prof. Emeritus Evan Cameron of York University for numerous discussions about philosophy and film, and for introducing me to Collingwood in the first place. iv TABLE OF CONTENTS Abstract ………………………………………………………………………….. iii Acknowledgements ................................................................................................ iv INTRODUCTION Project Summary and Outline ......................................................................... 1 Historical Context and Current Motivation .................................................... 3 1. THE IDEA OF A VIRTUE APPROACH TO AESTHETICS 1.1 The Connection Between Aesthetics and Ethics ............................................... 10 Kant on Aesthetics and Morality ..................................................................... 11 Aristotle, Plato and Appropriateness .............................................................. 16 1.2 Two Approaches to ‘Virtue Aesthetics’ ............................................................ 19 The Moral-Centred Approach: Kant and Schiller .......................................... 19 The Structural Approach: Hume ..................................................................... 23 1.3 Woodruff’s Virtue Theory of Aesthetics ........................................................... 27 Problems in Woodruff’s Theory ..................................................................... 30 1.4 Goldie on the Virtues of Art .............................................................................. 34 Problems in Goldie’s Theory .......................................................................... 35 Strengths of Goldie’s Theory ........................................................................... 38 1.5 Kieran and Lopes on Virtue Aesthetics ............................................................ 42 Kieran .............................................................................................................. 42 Lopes ................................................................................................................ 44 1.6 The General Shape of a Virtue Approach to Aesthetics ................................... 48 2. THE STRUCTURE OF A VIRTUE APPROACH 2.1 Aristotle’s Account of the Ethical Virtues …..................................................... 51 Eudaimonia and Goodness .............................................................................. 53 Virtue, ‘The Mean’ and Appropriateness ........................................................ 57 2.2 Practical Wisdom, Imagination and the Unity of the Virtues ............................ 63 Intuition, Comprehension, Discernment and Deliberation ............................. 65 The Imagination’s Role in Practical Wisdom ................................................. 69 The (Limited) Unity of the Virtues .................................................................. 73 2.3 MacIntyre on Virtues and Practices ................................................................... 74 Oakley as a Supplement to MacIntyre ............................................................. 78 2.4 The General Structure of a Neo-Aristotelian Virtue Approach ......................... 81 v 3. COLLINGWOOD’S PHILOSOPHY OF ART 3.1 Distinguishing Art from Craft ........................................................................... 84 Representation, Magic and Amusement .......................................................... 89 3.2 Art Proper, Expression and Imagination ........................................................... 95 Art as the Expression of Feeling ..................................................................... 95 Art as Imaginative Creation ............................................................................ 97 Collingwood’s Theory of the Imagination ....................................................... 99 The Imagination as a Process ......................................................................... 103 Imagination, Aspect Perception and Conceptualization ................................. 105 Imagination, Creation and Art ......................................................................... 108 3.3 The Normative Dimensions of Collingwood’s Aesthetics ................................ 113 Good and Bad Art ............................................................................................ 114 The Corruption of Consciousness .................................................................... 118 The Dangers of Amusement ............................................................................. 125 4. OUTLINE OF A COLLINGWOODIAN VIRTUE AESTHETICS 4.1 Why Collingwood’s Theory of Art Suits a Virtue Approach ............................ 129 Why a Virtue Approach Fits Aesthetics ........................................................... 130 The Compatibility of Collingwood’s Aesthetics with Aristotle’s Approach to Ethics ........................................................................................... 132 4.2 Virtues Internal to Aesthetic Practices ............................................................... 137 Aesthetic Activity, Moral Character and Well-Being ...................................... 139 Aesthetic Virtue …………….....................................………………............... 144 Aesthetic Practical Wisdom ............................................................................. 146 Virtues of Creation ........................................................................................... 150 The Spectator’s Virtues of Reception …........................………..…................ 157 The Relation Between Aesthetic and Ethical Virtue ........................................ 164 4.3 Aesthetic Normativity ........................................................................................ 166 Judging Artworks ............................................................................................
Recommended publications
  • Retrieving Kant's Aesthetics for Art Theory After
    8 Retrieving Kant’s Aesthetics for Art Theory After Greenberg Some Remarks on Arthur C. Danto and Thierry de Duve Diarmuid Costello The Fate of Aesthetics in Contemporary Art Theory In art theory since the early 1980s the discourse of aesthetics has been notable by its absence. Th is suggests that the majority of art theorists believe that the historical or conceptual limits of aesthetic theory have been breached by the internal development of art after modernism. But why would art theorists believe this? I n a n s w e r t o t h i s q u e s t i o n I s u g g e s t — I t a k e i t n o n c o n t r o v e r s i a l l y — t h a t the widespread marginalization of aesthetics in postmodern art theory may be attributed to the success of the art critic and theorist Clement Greenberg. In co- opting the discourse of (particularly Kantian) aesthetics to underwrite modernist theory, Greenberg mediated the art world’s sub- sequent rejection of both aesthetics in general and Immanuel Kant’s aes- thetics in par tic u lar. But one need only refl ect on the centrality for postmodern theory of anti- aesthetic fi gures like Marcel Duchamp or of movements (such as surrealism), marginalized in Greenberg’s account of “the best modern art,” to see that for all their antipathy to Greenberg, many postmodernist art theorists continue to operate with a broadly Greenbergian view of aesthetics—which is why, of course, they are forced to reject it.
    [Show full text]
  • Outline of a Sociological Theory of Art Perception∗
    From: Pierre Bordieu The Field of Cultural Production: Essays on Art and Literature ©1984, Columbia University Press Part III: The Pure Gaze: Essays on Art, Chapter 8 Outline of a Sociological Theory of Art Perception∗ PIERRE BOURDIEU 1 Any art perception involves a conscious or unconscious deciphering operation. 1.1 An act of deciphering unrecognized as such, immediate and adequate ‘comprehension’, is possible and effective only in the special case in which the cultural code which makes the act of deciphering possible is immediately and completely mastered by the observer (in the form of cultivated ability or inclination) and merges with the cultural code which has rendered the work perceived possible. Erwin Panofsky observes that in Rogier van der Weyden’s painting The Three Magi we immediately perceive the representation of an apparition’ that of a child in whom we recognize ‘the Infant Jesus’. How do we know that this is an apparition? The halo of golden rays surrounding the child would not in itself be sufficient proof, because it is also found in representations of the nativity in which the Infant Jesus is ‘real’. We come to this conclusion because the child is hovering in mid-air without visible support, and we do so although the representation would scarcely have been different had the child been sitting on a pillow (as in the case of the model which Rogier van der Weyden probably used). But one can think of hundreds of pictures in which human beings, animals or inanimate objects appear to be hovering in mid-air, contrary to the law of gravity, yet without giving the impression of being apparitions.
    [Show full text]
  • Rethinking Plato's Theory of Art: Aesthetics and the Timaeus
    Rethinking Plato’s Theory of Art: Aesthetics and the Timaeus Omid Tofighian Introduction The Timaeus presents a fascinating account of the cosmos. It includes a creation myth that introduces the figure known as the ‘Demiurge’, who, despite the fact that he is the cause of the sensible world, is reverently attributed with reason, and whose creation – the cosmos – is actually beautiful and good. In this dialogue Plato offers his readers a panorama of the universe. But just what are his intentions for this? Is his approach a precursor to the methods of natural science,1 or does the Timaeus fall under the category of theology? This paper will discuss Plato’s cosmological treatise and certain consequences that can be drawn, that is, how the methods used to analyse the origins and structure of the universe reveal a more existential attitude towards aesthetics. In the Timaeus Plato explores the complexities of mimesis and entertains the possibility that imitation could actually exhibit ideal qualities. These considerations have repercussions for the status of the material world in Plato’s cosmology, but they may also be extended to rethink his theory of art. I wish to analyse a number of salient themes in the Timaeus such as ontology, mythic symbols and the use of rhetoric. I will demonstrate how Plato’s view towards these themes in the Timaeus can be extrapolated to reassess his aesthetics. My critical analysis will provoke the question – ‘What evaluation of art would Plato have offered in accordance with the positions explicated in the Timaeus?’ Upon investigating a number of dialogues, searching specifically for references to art or representation, I realised that certain views I had thought to be exclusive to the Timaeus, or other late dialogues, also featured in works as early as the Ion.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant, Art, and Art History
    Kant, Art, and Art History Moments of Discipline mark a. cheetham University of Toronto published by the press syndicate of the university of cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom cambridge university press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb2 2ru, uk 40 West 20th Street, New York, ny 10011-4211, usa 10 Stamford Road, Oakleigh, vic 3166, Australia Ruiz de Alarcon ´ 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town 8001, South Africa http://www.cambridge.org Mark A. Cheetham 2001 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 2001 Printed in the United States of America Typeface Concorde 9.75/13 pt. System MagnaType [ag] A catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Cheetham, Mark A. (Mark Arthur), 1954– Kant, Art, and Art History: moments of discipline / Mark A. Cheetham. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. isbn 0-521-80018-8 1. Kant, Immanuel, 1724–1804–Contributions in aesthetics. 2. Aesthetics, Modern. 3. Art–Philosophy. I. Title. b2799.A4 c48 2001 111′.85′092–dc21 00-063029 isbn 0 521 80018 8 hardback Contents Acknowledgments page ix 1 Introduction: Bo(a)rders 1 Why (Not) Kant? 7 Moments and Places of Discipline 11 Plasmatics 24 2 Place and Time: Kant in Rome, c. 1800 38 Kant in Rome 41 The Concurrency of Reception 45 The Politics of Beauty 52 3 The Genealogy of Authority: Kant and Art’s History in the Twentieth Century 67 “Immanent Meaning” and the Historicity of Art: 68 Panofsky and Kant Kant and Cubism Revisited 78 Clement Greenberg’s Strategic Formalism 87 4 The Sublime Is Now (Again): French Theory / International Art 101 Derrida’s Sublime 103 The Sublime Is Now (Again) 114 Scapes 124 The Limits of Pointing 130 Intimations of a Countersublime 136 vii contents 5 Kant’s Skull: Portraits and the Image of Philosophy, c.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant Expressive Theory Music
    Kant’s Expressive Theory of Music Samantha Matherne Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism (2014, pre-print) Abstract: Several prominent philosophers of art (e.g., Kivy, Dahlhaus, Schueller) have worried whether Kant has a coherent theory of music on account of two perceived tensions in his view. First, there appears to be a conflict between his formalist and expressive commitments. Second (and even worse), Kant defends seemingly contradictory claims about music being beautiful and merely agreeable, i.e., not beautiful. Against these critics, I show that Kant has a consistent view of music that reconciles these tensions. I argue that, for Kant, music can be experienced as either agreeable or beautiful depending upon the attitude we take towards it. Though we might be tempted to think he argues that we experience music as agreeable when we attend to its expressive qualities and as beautiful when we attend to its formal properties, I demonstrate that he actually claims that we are able to judge music as beautiful only if we are sensitive to the expression of emotion through musical form. With this revised understanding of Kant’s theory of music in place, I conclude by sketching a Kantian solution to a central problem in the philosophy of music: given that music is not sentient, how can it express emotion? §1. Introduction As philosophers like Peter Kivy and Stephen Davies have emphasized, one of the central issues in the philosophy of music is the problem of expression.1 Frequently when we hear a piece of instrumental music, we describe it as expressing an emotion, e.g., Beethoven’s ‘Eroica’ symphony sounds triumphant or Chopin’s Étude in E Major (Op.
    [Show full text]
  • Final Thesis
    A DEFENSE OF AESTHETIC ANTIESSENTIALISM: MORRIS WEITZ AND THE POSSIBLITY OF DEFINING ‘ART’ _____________________________ A Thesis Presented to The Honors Tutorial College Ohio University _____________________________ In Partial Fulfillment Of the Requirements for Graduation from the Honors Tutorial College with the degree of Bachelor of Arts in Philosophy and Art History _____________________________ By Jordan Mills Pleasant June, 2010 ii This thesis has been approved by The Honors Tutorial College and the Department of Philosophy ___________________________ Dr. Arthur Zucker Chair, Department of Philosophy Thesis Advisor ___________________________ Dr. Scott Carson Honors Tutorial College, Director of Studies Philosophy ___________________________ Jeremy Webster Dean, Honors Tutorial College iii This thesis has been approved by The Honors Tutorial College and the Department of Art History ___________________________ Dr. Jennie Klein Chair, Department of Art History Thesis Advisor ___________________________ Dr. Jennie Klein Honors Tutorial College, Director of Studies Art History ___________________________ Jeremy Webster Dean, Honors Tutorial College iv Dedicated to Professor Arthur Zucker, without whom this work would have been impossible. v Table Of Contents Thesis Approval Pages Page ii Introduction: A Brief History of the Role of Definitions in Art Page 1 Chapter I: Morris Weitz’s “The Role of Theory in Aesthetics” Page 8 Chapter II: Lewis K. Zerby’s “A Reconsideration of the Role of the Theory in Aesthetics. A Reply to Morris Weitz”
    [Show full text]
  • Religion and the Arts in America
    Religion and the Arts in America CAMILLE PAGLIA At this moment in America, religion and pol- itics are at a flash point. Conservative Christians deplore the left-wing bias of the mainstream media and the saturation of popular culture by sex and violence and are promoting strate- gies such as faith-based home-schooling to protect children from the chaotic moral relativism of a secular society. Liberals in turn condemn the meddling by Christian fundamentalists in politics, notably in regard to abortion and gay civil rights or the Mideast, where biblical assumptions, it is claimed, have shaped us policy. There is vicious mutual recrimination, with believers caricatured as paranoid, apocalyptic crusaders who view America’s global mission as divinely inspired, while lib- erals are portrayed as narcissistic hedonists and godless elit- ists, relics of the unpatriotic, permissive 1960s. A primary arena for the conservative-liberal wars has been the arts. While leading conservative voices defend the tradi- tional Anglo-American literary canon, which has been under challenge and in flux for forty years, American conservatives on the whole, outside of the New Criterion magazine, have shown little interest in the arts, except to promulgate a didac- tic theory of art as moral improvement that was discarded with the Victorian era at the birth of modernism. Liberals, on the other hand, have been too content with the high visibility of the arts in metropolitan centers, which comprise only a fraction of America. Furthermore, liberals have been compla- cent about the viability of secular humanism as a sustaining A lecture delivered on 6 February 2007 as the 2007 Cornerstone Arts Lecture at Colorado College.
    [Show full text]
  • Morris Weitz Aili W
    University of Dayton eCommons Philosophy Faculty Publications Department of Philosophy 2014 Morris Weitz Aili W. Bresnahan University of Dayton, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.udayton.edu/phl_fac_pub Part of the History of Philosophy Commons eCommons Citation Bresnahan, Aili W., "Morris Weitz" (2014). Philosophy Faculty Publications. 4. https://ecommons.udayton.edu/phl_fac_pub/4 This Encyclopedia Entry is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. Word Count: 2,494 [Main body text: 1,189; Bibliography: 1,305] Weitz, Morris (1916-1981), American philosopher of aesthetics who focused primarily on ontology, interpretation, and literary criticism. Weitz’ Initial Theory of Art. Morris Weitz’ initial theory of art was provided in his book, Philosophy of the Arts (Weitz 1950). Here Weitz calls his theory of art “empirical” and “organic,” and he defined “art” as “an organic complex or integration of expressive elements embodied in a sensuous medium” (51). By “empirical” he means that his theory answers to the evidence provided by actual works of art. “Organic,” for Weitz, means that each element is to be considered in relation to the others in a living and not merely mechanical way. Weitz also has a broad understanding of “expressive,” which refers to an artistic property that functions as a semiotic sign, either of a specific emotional feeling, an emotional quality, or another sign of an emotional feature.
    [Show full text]
  • TERRY SMITH, FAHA, CIHA, Is Andrew W. Mellon Professor Of
    TERRY SMITH at the Garage Museum of Art, Moscow, 2015. Photo: Denis Sinyakov. Courtesy of Terry Smith. ERRY SMITH, FAHA, CIHA, is Art and Director of the Power Institute, Ideas: On Conceptual Art and Concep‑ Andrew W. Mellon Professor of Foundation for Art and Visual Culture, tualism (Durham: Duke University Press, TContemporary Art History and University of Sydney. In the 1970s he was 2017), and Art to Come: Histories of Con‑ Theory in the Department of the His- a member of the Art & Language group temporary Art (Durham: Duke University tory of Art and Architecture at the (New York) and a founder of Union Me- Press, 2019). He is editor of many others University of Pittsburgh, and Profes- dia Services (Sydney). He is the author including Antinomies of Art and Culture: sor in the Division of Philosophy, Art, of a number of books, notably Making Modernity, postmodernity and contem‑ and Critical Thought at the European the Modern: Industry, Art and Design in poraneity (with Nancy Condee and Ok- Graduate School. He is also Lecturer at America (University of Chicago Press, wui Enwezor, Duke University Press, Large in the Curatorial Program of the 1993); Transformations in Australian Art 2008). A foundation Board member of School of Visual Arts, New York. In 2010 (Craftsman House, Sydney, 2002); The the Museum of Contemporary Art, Syd- he was named the Australia Council Vis- Architecture of Aftermath (University ney, he is currently a Board member of ual Arts Laureate, and won the Mather of Chicago Press, 2006), What is Con‑ the Carnegie Museum of Art, Pittsburgh, Award for art criticism conferred by the temporary Art? (University of Chicago and of the Biennial Foundation, New College Art Association (USA).
    [Show full text]
  • Art and Thingness, Part I: Breton's Ball and Duchamp's Carrot
    In modern art, the increasing resemblance of art objects to everyday objects raised the threat of eroding of any real difference between works of art and other things. Barnett Newman railed against both Duchamp’s readymades and “Bauhaus screwdriver designers” who were elevated to the ranks of artists by the Museum of 01/09 Modern Art’s doctrine of “Good Design.”1 The danger for art was the same in both cases: the dissolving of the dividing line between works of art and everyday objects. Just as ancient art proper should never be confused with the craft of “women basket weavers,” modern art should never be confused with a screwdriver or urinal.2 In the 1960s, Clement Greenberg would also Sven Lütticken worry that a blank sheet of paper or a table would become readable as art, that the boundary between artworks and “arbitrary objects” was Art and eroding.3 While not evincing any Modernist anxieties about readymades, Paul Chan’s recent Thingness, Part assertion that “a work of art is both more and less than a thing” shows renewed concerns I: Breton’s Ball regarding such an assimilation – in a context marked, until quite recently, by an unprecedented market boom in which works of and Duchamp’s art seemed to be situated in a continuum of luxury goods spanning from Prada bags to luxury Carrot yachts.4 ÊÊÊÊÊÊÊÊÊÊBut what does it mean to say that an artwork is both more and less than a thing? The notion of the thing is prominent in contemporary theory, and one might say that the thing has emerged as something that is both more and less t o r than an object.
    [Show full text]
  • Concept, Sensation, Intensity: Deleuze's Theory of Art and Cinema
    Sociology and Anthropology 5(9): 792-797, 2017 http://www.hrpub.org DOI: 10.13189/sa.2017.050911 Concept, Sensation, Intensity: Deleuze's Theory of Art and Cinema Paolo Bertetto Department of Art History and Performing Arts, Sapienza University of Rome, Italy Copyright©2017 by authors, all rights reserved. Authors agree that this article remains permanently open access under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License 4.0 International License Abstract In What Is Philosophy?, Deleuze & Guattari After all, Deleuze’s theory of cinema is itself unusual in its consider art as a bloc of sensations, composed of percepts, features, as it is more concerned with the doing of cinema, affects and images. Such notions are also crucial to the with its operativeness, and less with its being. The understanding of Deleuze’s idea of cinema, as elaborated background of this history seems to be the idea of poiein, by the philosopher in his two books Cinema 1. The considered as the main substratum, the explicit and implicit Movement-Image and Cinema; 2. The Time-Image, and axis around which it revolves. What matters, for Deleuze, is further investigated in other essays and interviews. In not to look only at the being of cinema, at its einai, but also, Deleuze’s theory, concepts and sensations are forms of and most of all, to its doing, to what cinema produces. How intensity, and they are flows, rather than firm configurations. would it after all be possible to actually distinguish the being And cinema is, in an exemplary way, a flow of images, a from the doing? Only an essentialist theory could continuous variation of intensity.
    [Show full text]
  • New Work for Aesthetic Theory Of
    REMODELING AESTHETIC THEORY: PORTRAIT OF THE ARTIST AS AN AESTHETIC EXPERT CHRISTY MAG UIDHIR & CAMERON BUCKNER For the most part, the Aesthetic Theory of Art—any theory of art claiming that the aesthetic is a descriptively necessary feature of art—has been repudiated, especially in light of what are now considered traditional counterexamples. We argue that the Aesthetic Theory of Art can instead be far more plausibly recast by abandoning aesthetic-feature possession by the artwork for a claim about aesthetic-concept possession by the artist. This move productively re-frames and re-energizes the debate surrounding the relationship between art and the aesthetic. That is, we claim Aesthetic Theory so re-framed suggests that the aesthetic might have a central and substantial explanatory role to play within both traditional philosophical enquiries as well as recent and more empirical enquiries into the psychological and cognitive aspects of art and its practice. Finally, we discuss the directions this new work might take—by tying art theory to investigations of the distinctive sensorimotor capacities of expert artists, their specialized aesthetic conceptual schemata, and the ways these distinctive capacities and schemata contribute to the production of artworks. INTRODUCTION The aesthetic has fallen on hard art-theoretic times. Theories according to which possession of some distinctively aesthetic feature is substantively necessary for something’s being an artwork (Aesthetic Theories of Art), though once privileged, now are standardly considered to be more or less art- theoretically bankrupt. To be sure, aesthetic features still figure to varying degrees in philosophical enquiry into art and its associated relata.1 However, scant few think that such features must figure substantively in what it is to be art; even those who assign aesthetic features some purportedly essential role end up unloading the bulk of the explanatory burden onto the non-aesthetic features.2 Our own assessment of the Aesthetic Theory of Art in what follows is no different.
    [Show full text]