Proceedings of ADG 2016 Julien Narboux, Pascal Schreck, Ileana Streinu

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Proceedings of ADG 2016 Julien Narboux, Pascal Schreck, Ileana Streinu Proceedings of ADG 2016 Julien Narboux, Pascal Schreck, Ileana Streinu To cite this version: Julien Narboux, Pascal Schreck, Ileana Streinu. Proceedings of ADG 2016: Eleventh International Workshop on Automated Deduction in Geometry. Jun 2016, Strasbourg, France. pp.224, 2016. hal- 01334334 HAL Id: hal-01334334 https://hal.inria.fr/hal-01334334 Submitted on 20 Jun 2016 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Julien Narboux Pascal Schreck Ileana Streinu (Eds.) 2016 ADGEleventh International Workshop on Automated Deduction in Geometry University of Strasbourg, France, June 27-29, 2016 Julien Narboux Pascal Schreck Ileana Streinu (Eds.) Automated Deduction in Geometry 11th International Workshop, ADG 2016 Strasbourg, France, June 27-29, 2016 Preface This volume contains the 14 papers and 3 invited talks presented at ADG 2016: Eleventh International Work- shop on Automated Deduction in Geometry held on June 26-28, 2016 in Strasbourg, France. ADG is a forum facilitating the exchange of ideas, presentation of new research results and demonstrations of software tools lying at the intersection of geometry and automated deduction. The selected papers, reviewed by an international Program Committee, cover diverse topics ranging from polynomial algebra, invariant and coordinate-free methods, synthetic and logic approaches, techniques for automated geometric reasoning from dis- crete mathematics, symbolic and numeric methods for geometric computation, geometric algorithms, geometric constraint solving, experimental studies with automated theorem provers, applications to mechanics, origami and geometric modeling. The previous ten workshops were held in Coimbra 2014, Edinburgh 2012, Munich 2010, Shangha¨ı2008, Ponteve- dra 2006, Gainesville 2004, Linz 2002, Zurich 2000, Bei- jing 1998, and Toulouse 1996. The conference was organized by the Computer Graph- ics and Geometry Group of ICube Laboratory (CNRS / Universit´ede Strasbourg). We would like to thank the invited speakers and au- thors for their contributions. We are very grateful to the program committee members and referees for their exper- tise which ensures the high scientific standard of ADG. We also warmly thank all the local organizers for con- tributing to the practical organisation so that the meet- ing can be held smoothly. We thank the IGG team and the ICube laboratory for helping us by sponsoring this conference. Support from EasyChair is also gratefully ac- knowledged. June 13, 2016 Julien Narboux Strasbourg Pascal Schreck Ileana Streinu Program Committee Michael Beeson San Jose State University Francisco Botana University of Vigo John Bowers James Madison University Xiaoyu Chen Beihang University Xiao-Shan Gao Academia Sinica Tetsuo Ida University of Tsukuba Filip Mari´c University of Belgrade Pascal Mathis University of Strasbourg Julien Narboux University of Strasbourg Pavel Pech University of South Bohemia Pedro Quaresma University of Coimbra Tomas Recio Universidad de Cantabria Pascal Schreck University of Strasbourg Meera Sitharam University of Florida Ileana Streinu Smith College Dongming Wang Beihang University and CNRS Bican Xia Peking University Additional Reviewers Fadoua Ghourabi Wenping Wang Menghan Wang Jeremy Youngquist Organizers Pierre Boutry Pascal Mathis David Braun Julien Narboux Gabriel Braun Pascal Schreck Nicolas Magaud Dan Song Table of Contents Invited Speakers Geometrisation of Geometry ................... 1 Predrag Janiˇci´c Solving With Or Without Equations ............ 15 Dominique Michelucci Dependence of Axioms for Weak Geometries Proved Syntactically .......................... 21 Victor Pambuccian Contributed Papers Implementing Automatic Discovery in GeoGebra . 23 Miguel A. Ab´anades,Francisco Botana, Zolt´an Kov´acs,Tom´asRecio and Csilla S´olyom-Gecse Geodesic Star Unfolding ...................... 32 Md. Ashraful Alam and Ileana Streinu Geometric Deformations of Sodalite Frameworks . 44 Ciprian Borcea and Ileana Streinu Computing the Straight Skeleton of a Simple Polygon from its Motorcycle Graph in Deterministic O(n.logn) Time ................. 54 John C. Bowers An Equivalence Proof Between Rank Theory and Incidence Projective Geometry ............. 62 David Braun, Nicolas Magaud and Pascal Schreck From Hilbert to Tarski ........................ 78 Gabriel Braun, Pierre Boutry and Julien Nar- boux Massic points, B´ezierCurves and Conics: a Survey 97 Lionel Garnier and Jean-Paul B´ecar A New Formalization of Origami in Geometric Algebra ..................................... 117 Tetsuo Ida, Jacques Fleuriot and Fadoua Ghourabi Automatic Rewrites of Input Expressions in Complex Algebraic Geometry Provers ........... 137 Zolt´anKov´acs,Tom´asRecio and Csilla S´olyom- Gecse Two ways of using Rabinowitsch trick for imposing non-degeneracy conditions ............ 144 Manuel Ladra, Pilar P´aez-Guill´anand Tom´as Recio Portfolio Methods in Theorem Proving for Elementary Geometry ........................ 152 Vesna Marinkovi´c,Mladen Nikoli´c,Zolt´anKov´acs and Predrag Janiˇci´c On a Certain Class of Cubic Surfaces Related to the Simson–Wallace Theorem .................. 162 Pavel Pech Automated Generation of Keywords from Images for Geometric Information Search ........ 172 Dan Song and Xiaoyu Chen Formalization of a Surface Subdivision Allowing a Region with Holes without Coordinates ........ 190 Kazuko Takahashi, Sosuke Moriguchi and Mizuki Goto Geometrisation of Geometry? Predrag Janiˇci´c1 Faculty of Mathematics, University of Belgrade, Serbia Abstract. Coherent logic (CL) is a fragment of first-order logic suitable for automation of proving process and also for formalization of various mathematical theories, including geometry. This paper gives an overview of several developments based on CL with geometry as the domain: au- tomated theorem provers for CL, CL-based formalizations of geometry, CL-based proof representation, links between CL and geometry construc- tion problems, links between CL and geometrical illustrations, etc. 1 Introduction Automated deduction in geometry has been around for more than sixty years now and it still attracts a lot of attention for several reasons: it requires paradigmatic reasoning that is very difficult to automate, progress in automated reasoning in geometry often leads to ideas that influence other fields, there are practical appli- cations in areas such as robotics, ... and, of course, it is very beautiful. Over the decades, there were several ingenious insights into geometrical reasoning and also links to algebra that led to new methods capable of solving many hard geometry problems [9,10,22]. Still, after all that years and methods, there are no computer programs capable of routinely solving all geometry problems explored in high- school Euclidean geometry. Like in other related domains, there are important issues and challenges concerning scope and efficiency, but in geometry it is also readability of solutions that matters. While algebraic theorem provers for geom- etry proved that they can efficiently solve a wide scope of geometry problems, they cannot provide readable, understandable solutions in terms of synthetic geometry. The same holds for resolution-based approaches. Some semi-synthetic approaches (such as the area method or the full-angle method) provide proofs that can be concise and intuitive, but not always (often their outputs involve enormously large expressions). In this paper, coherent logic, denoted by CL, is discussed. A number of theories and theorems can be formulated directly and simply in CL, for in- stance group theory, ring theory, category theory, the theory of fields, lattice theory, a range of geometries, etc. Several authors independently point to CL or similar fragments of first order logic as suitable for expressing (sometimes – also automating) portions of standard mathematics, for instance, Ganesalingam and Gowers in the context of automated generation of readable proofs [18], Tarski in the context of his geometry [37], Avigad et.al. in the context of a ? Partly supported by the grant 174021 of the Ministry of Science of Serbia. 2 Predrag Janiˇci´c new diagram-based axiomatic foundations of geometry [1], etc. In contrast to resolution-based theorem proving, in CL the conjecture being proved is kept un- changed and proved without using refutation, Skolemization and clausal form. Thanks to this, CL can serve as a vehicle for producing, at least in some cases and to some extent, human-readable synthetic geometry proofs (in the style of forward reasoning) [4] with ”structure of ordinary mathematical arguments bet- ter retained“ [16]. Moreover, since it allows (limited) existential quantification, it allows building theorem provers with the scope that goes beyond universally quantified fragment, typical for most available proving methods in geometry. CL proofs can also be easily translated into input language of different proof assistants and in a natural language form. 2 Coherent and Geometric Logic A formula of first-order logic is said to be coherent if it has the following form: A (x)
Recommended publications
  • Relevant Implication and Ordered Geometry
    Australasian Journal of Logic Relevant Implication and Ordered Geometry Alasdair Urquhart Abstract This paper shows that model structures for R+, the system of positive relevant implication, can be constructed from ordered geometries. This ex- tends earlier results building such model structures from projective spaces. A final section shows how such models can be extended to models for the full system R. 1 Introduction This paper is a sequel to an earlier paper by the author [6] showing how to construct models for the logic KR from projective spaces. In that article, the logical relation Rabc is an extension of the relation Cabc, where a; b; c are points in a projective space and Cabc is read as \a; b; c are distinct and collinear." In the case of the projective construction, the relation Rabc is totally sym- metric. This is of course not the case in general in R models, where the first two points a and b can be permuted, but not the third. For the third point, we have only the implication Rabc ) Rac∗b∗. On the other hand, if we read Rabc as \c is between a and b", where we are operating in an ordered geometry, then we can permute a and b, but not b and c, just as in the case of R. Hence, these models are more natural than the ones constructed from projective spaces, from the point of view of relevance logic. In the remainder of the paper, we carry out the plan outlined here, by constructing models for R+ from ordered geometries.
    [Show full text]
  • Geometry in a Nutshell Notes for Math 3063
    GEOMETRY IN A NUTSHELL NOTES FOR MATH 3063 B. R. MONSON DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS & STATISTICS UNIVERSITY OF NEW BRUNSWICK Copyright °c Barry Monson February 7, 2005 One morning an acorn awoke beneath its mother and declared, \Gee, I'm a tree". Anon. (deservedly) 2 THE TREE OF EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRY 3 INTRODUCTION Mathematics is a vast, rich and strange subject. Indeed, it is so varied that it is considerably more di±cult to de¯ne than say chemistry, economics or psychology. Every individual of that strange species mathematician has a favorite description for his or her craft. Mine is that mathematics is the search for the patterns hidden in the ideas of space and number . This description is particularly apt for that rich and beautiful branch of mathematics called geometry. In fact, geometrical ideas and ways of thinking are crucial in many other branches of mathematics. One of the goals of these notes is to convince you that this search for pattern is continuing and thriving all the time, that mathematics is in some sense a living thing. At this very moment, mathematicians all over the world1 are discovering new and enchanting things, exploring new realms of the imagination. This thought is easily forgotten in the dreary routine of attending classes. Like other mathematical creatures, geometry has many faces. Let's look at some of these and, along the way, consider some advice about doing mathematics in general. Geometry is learned by doing: Ultimately, no one can really teach you mathe- matics | you must learn by doing it yourself. Naturally, your professor will show the way, give guidance (and also set a blistering pace).
    [Show full text]
  • The Axiomatics of Ordered Geometry I
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Expositiones Mathematicae 29 (2011) 24–66 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Expositiones Mathematicae journal homepage: www.elsevier.de/exmath The axiomatics of ordered geometry I. Ordered incidence spaces Victor Pambuccian Division of Mathematical and Natural Sciences, Arizona State University - West Campus, P. O. Box 37100, Phoenix, AZ 85069-7100, USA article info a b s t r a c t Article history: We present a survey of the rich theory of betweenness and Received 7 September 2009 separation, from its beginning with Pasch's 1882 Vorlesungen über Received in revised form neuere Geometrie to the present. 17 July 2010 ' 2010 Elsevier GmbH. All rights reserved. Keywords: Ordered geometry Axiom system Half-ordered geometry Somewhere there is some knowledge; under the stone A message perhaps; or hidden by strange signs In places only the stupid visit. Malcolm Lowry. Ein Zeichen sind wir, deutungslos, Schmerzlos sind wir und haben fast Die Sprache in der Fremde verloren. Friedrich Hölderlin, Mnemosyne. 1. Introduction Unlike most concepts of elementary geometry, whose origin is shrouded in the ineluctable fog of all cultural beginnings, the history of the notion of betweenness can be traced back to one person, one book, and one year: Moritz Pasch,1 Vorlesungen über neuere Geometrie, and 1882. The aim of this pioneering book was to provide a solid foundation, very much in the spirit of synthetic geometry, for 1 For a view of one of Pasch's contemporaries on his life and his work's significance for the axiomatics of geometry, see [325].
    [Show full text]
  • Von Staudt and His Influence
    A Von Staudt and his Influence A.1 Von Staudt The fundamental criticism of the work of Chasles and M¨obius is that in it cross- ratio is defined as a product of two ratios, and so as an expression involving four lengths. This makes projective geometry, in their formulation, dependent on Euclidean geometry, and yet projective geometry is claimed to be more fundamental, because it does not involve the concept of distance at all. The way out of this apparent contradiction was pioneered by von Staudt, taken up by Felix Klein, and gradually made its way into the mainstream, culminating in the axiomatic treatments of projective geometry between 1890 and 1914. That a contradiction was perceived is apparent from remarks Klein quotes in his Zur nicht-Euklidischen Geometrie [138] from Cayley and Ball.1 Thus, from Cayley: “It must however be admitted that, in applying this theory of v. Staudt’s to the theory of distance, there is at least the appearance of arguing in a circle.” And from Ball: “In that theory [the non-Euclidean geometry] it seems as if we try to replace our ordinary notion of distance between two points by the logarithm of a certain anharmonic ratio. But this ratio itself involves the notion of distance measured in the ordinary way. How then can we supersede the old notion of distance by the non-Euclidean one, inasmuch as the very definition of the latter involves the former?” The way forward was to define projective concepts entirely independently of Euclidean geometry. The way this was done was inevitably confused at first, 1 In Klein, Gesammelte mathematische Abhandlungen,I[137, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Geometry Applications: Points and Lines 1
    TRANSCRIPT—Geometry Applications: Points and Lines 1 Geometry Applications: Points and Lines Geometry Applications: Points and Lines, Segment 1: Introduction OUR STUDY OF GEOMETRY OWES MUCH TO THE ANCIENT GREEKS. AND THERE IS NO BETTER SYMBOL OF ANCIENT GREECE THAN THE PARTHENON, A TEMPLE OVERLOOKING THE CITY OF ATHENS COMPLETED IN THE FOURTH CENTURY BC. YET A MORE PERMANENT MONUMENT WAS BUILT A CENTURY LATER BY THE MOST INFLUENTIAL MATHEMATICIAN OF ANCIENT GREECE, EUCLID. HIS BOOK, THE ELEMENTS, LAID THE GROUNDWORK FOR GEOMETRIC THINKING AND MATHEMATICAL REASONING. YET BOTH THE PARTHENON AND THE ELEMENTS SHARE A LOT IN COMMON WHEN IT COMES TO GEOMETRY. THE PARTHENON IS AN ARCHITECTURAL STRUCTURE AND ARCHITECTURE RELIES HEAVILY ON GEOMETRY. THE NOTIONS OF POINTS, LINES, PLANES, AND ANGLES ARE A KEY PART OF GEOMETRY AND OF THE PARTHENON. FOR EXAMPLE, TO SKETCH THE FRONT OF THE PARTHENON YOU WOULD DRAW A SERIES OF POINTS TRANSCRIPT—Geometry Applications: Points and Lines 2 TO MARK THE LINES FOR THE COLUMNS. YOU WOULD CONNECT THESE POINTS TO CONSTRUCT A TRIANGLE. FOR A THREE-DIMENSIONAL VIEW OF THE PARTHENON YOU WOULD NEED TO DRAW SEVERAL PLANES INDICATING THE VARIOUS LEVELS. GEOMETRIC CONSTRUCTIONS LIKE THESE RELY ON SOME UNDERLYING PRINCIPLES. IN THIS PROGRAM WE WILL COVER REAL-WORLD APPLICATIONS THAT EXPLORE THE FOLLOWING GEOMETRIC CONCEPTS: Geometry Applications: Points and Lines, Segment 2: Points IN THE SWISS COUNTRYSIDE SOME IMPORTANT SCIENTIFIC WORK IS TAKING PLACE. SO AS NOT TO OBSTRUCT THE VIEW OF THE ALPS, THIS WORK IS HAPPENING UNDERGROUND. CERN, THE EUROPEAN AGENCY THAT DOES RESEARCH IN SUB ATOMIC PHYSICS HAS RECENTLY LAUNCHED THE LARGE HADRON COLLIDER.
    [Show full text]
  • ORDER in AFFINE and PROJECTIVE GEOMETRY Joe
    ORDER IN AFFINE AND PROJECTIVE GEOMETRY Joe Liipman (received July 2, 1962) In this note we give a characterisation of ordered skew fields by certain properties of the negative elements. Properties of negative elements of a skew field K are then interpreted as statements about "betweenness" in any affine geometry over K, or as statements about "separation" in any projective geometry over K. In this way, our axioms for ordered fields permit of immediate translation into postulates of order for affine or projective geometry (over a field). The postulates so obtained seem simple enough to be of interest, (cf. [4], p. 22) 1. We assume we have an ordered skew field K, [l], i. e. there is given a subset P of K (the positive elements) satisfying a) K is the disjoint union of P, \0), -P, b) P+PCP. c) PPcP. Let N be the set of negative elements, i.e. N = { X | X ^ P, X # 0} so that d) P = { X j X 4 N, X # 0} . Canad. Math. Bull, vol.6, no. 1, January 1963. 37 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 27 Sep 2021 at 18:14:09, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. For convenience we write ,f{X} lf to mean X € N. It is clear by elementary properties of ordered fields that (i) N is not empty (ii) {X} - X* 0 (iii) {X} -(1 - X)€P (iv) If { X} and [i e P, then {JJLX }. What we want is the converse: given a subset N of any field K, define P by d), write n{X}!! to mean X € N, and show that (i), (ii), (iii), £iv), imply a), b), c); in other words, if N satisfies (i), (ii), (iii), (iv), show that K can be ordered in such a way that N is the set of negative elements.
    [Show full text]
  • Multidimensional Mereotopology with Betweenness ∗
    Proceedings of the Twenty-Second International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence Multidimensional Mereotopology with Betweenness ∗ Torsten Hahmann Michael Gruninger¨ Department of Computer Science Department of Mechanical and Industrial Engineering University of Toronto University of Toronto [email protected] [email protected] Abstract in more than two points. Even if Main St. intersects, e.g., Ring Rd. twice, both are distinguishable by other intersec- Qualitative reasoning about commonsense space tions they have not in common. Moreover, models of every- often involves entities of different dimensions. We day space are often only interested in a few meaningful enti- present a weak axiomatization of multidimensional ties (such as intersections or bridges) and not in the infinitely qualitative space based on ‘relative dimension’ and many points forced to exist by continuous geometry. dimension-independent ‘containment’ which suf- We design a multidimensional theory of space that al- fice to define basic dimension-dependent mereoto- lows such intuitive, map-like, representations of common- pological relations. We show the relationships to sense space as models. Though its main application will be in other meoreotopologies and to incidence geome- modelling 2- and 3-dimensional space, the general axiomati- try. The extension with betweenness, a primitive of zation is independent of the number of dimensions. We start relative position, results in a first-order theory that with a na¨ıve concept of relative dimensionality
    [Show full text]
  • Foundations of Geometry – Iii
    KATHMANDU UNIVERSITY JOURNAL OF SCIENCE, ENGINEERING AND TECHNOLOGY VOL. I, No. V, SEPTEMBER 2008, pp 95-97 . FOUNDATIONS OF GEOMETRY – III Pushpa Raj Adhikary Department of Natural Sciences Kathmandu University, Dhulikhel, Kavre Corresponding author: [email protected] Received 15 August; Revised 21 September In the beginning, the geometry developed from practical problems concerning the calculations of length, areas and volumes. Instead of correct and exact mathematical methods, these computational methods were crude approximations derived from trial methods. The body of knowledge thus developed by Babylonians and Egyptians for surveying and navigation were passed on to the Greeks. The Greeks, with their scholarly pursuit, transformed this bulk of ideas into a science known as geometry. About 300 B.C. Euclid of Alexandria organized this knowledge of his time in the form of a book, the Elements. This Elements proved such an effective book of geometry that for the next 2000 years geometers all over the world used this books as the starting point. Euclid did not define length, distance, or inclination. He used the "rules of interaction" between the defined objects in his postulates, The five postulates of Euclid, specially the fifth one, the attraction it drew, and the various attempts to prove this postulate in terms of other postulates, has been discussed earlier. In 1763 a man named Klugel wrote a dissertation at gottingen in which he evaluated all significant attempts made to prove the Euclid's parallel (or the fifth) postulate. Out of the 28 attempted proofs of this postulate klugel found no one to be satisfactory. Of particular interest was the work of Saccheri.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:2011.05779V3 [Math.HO] 15 Feb 2021 Nua Esrs[ Measures Angular Ilri H Eeomn Fmteais N19,Dvdhil David 1899, in Mathematics
    ON ANGULAR MEASURES IN AXIOMATIC EUCLIDEAN PLANAR GEOMETRY MARTIN GROTSCHEL,¨ HARALD HANCHE-OLSEN, HELGE HOLDEN, AND MICHAEL P. KRYSTEK Abstract. We address the issue of angle measurements which is a contested issue for the International System of Units (SI). We provide a mathematically rigorous and axiomatic presentation of angle measurements that leads to the traditional way of measuring a plane angle subtended by a circular arc as the length of the arc divided by the radius of the arc, a scalar quantity. This abstract approach has the advantage that it is independent of the assumptions of Cartesian plane geometry. We distinguish between the geometric angle, defined in terms of congruence classes of angles, and the (numerical) angular measure that can be assigned to each congruence class in such a way that, π e.g., the right angle has the numerical value 2 . We argue that angles are intrinsically different from lengths, as there are angles of special significance (such as the right angle, or the straight angle), while there is no distinguished length in Euclidean geometry. This is further underlined by the observation that, while units such as the metre and kilogram have been refined over time due to advances in metrology, no such refinement of the radian is conceivable. It is a mathematically constructed unit, set in stone for eternity. We conclude that angle measurements are dimensionless, and the current definition in SI should remain unaltered. What’s in a name? That which we call a rose, By any other word would smell as sweet. – William Shakespeare 1. Introduction There has been a long discussion within the metrology community regarding angular measures [6, 7, 8, 9, 10, 11].
    [Show full text]
  • Critical Studies/Book Reviews 1. Introduction
    255 Critical Studies/Book Reviews David Hilbert. David Hilbert’s lectures on the foundations of geometry, 1891–1902. Michael Hallett and Ulrich Majer, eds. David Hilbert’s Foun- Downloaded from dational Lectures; 1. Berlin: Springer-Verlag, 2004. ISBN 3-540-64373-7. Pp. xxviii + 661.† Reviewed by Victor Pambuccian∗ http://philmat.oxfordjournals.org/ 1. Introduction This volume, the result of monumental editorial work, contains the German text of various lectures on the foundations of geometry, as well as the first edition of Hilbert’s Grundlagen der Geometrie, a work we shall refer to as the GdG. The material surrounding the lectures was selected from the Hilbert papers stored in two Gottingen¨ libraries, based on criteria of relevance to the genesis and the trajectory of Hilbert’s ideas regarding the foundations of geometry, the rationale, and the meaning of the foun- at Arizona State University Libraries on December 3, 2013 dational enterprise. By its very nature, this material contains additions, crossed-out words or paragraphs, comments in the margin, and all of it is painstakingly documented in notes and appendices. Each piece is pre- ceded by informative introductions in English that highlight the main fea- tures worthy of the reader’s attention, and place the lectures in historical context, sometimes providing references to subsequent developments. It is thus preferable (but by no means necessary, as the introductions alone, by singling out the main points of interest, amply reward the reader of English only) that the interested reader be proficient in both German and English (French would be helpful as well, as there are a few French quotations), as there are no translations.
    [Show full text]
  • Research Analysis and Design of Geometric Transformations Using Affine Geometry
    International Journal of Engineering Inventions e-ISSN: 2278-7461, p-ISSN: 2319-6491 Volume 3, Issue 3 (October 2013) PP: 25-30 Research Analysis and Design of Geometric Transformations using Affine Geometry 1N. V. Narendra Babu, 2Prof. Dr. G. Manoj Someswar, 3Ch. Dhanunjaya Rao 1M.Sc., M.Phil., (Ph.D.), Asst. Professor, Department of Mathematics, GITAM University, Hyderabad, A.P., India.(First Author) 2B.Tech., M.S.(USA), M.C.A., Ph.D., Principal & Professor, Department of Computer Science & Engineering, Anwar-ul-uloom College of Engineering &Technology, Yennepally, RR District, Vikarabad – 501101, A.P., India.(Second Author) 3M. Tech. (CSE), IT Professional, I Software Solutions, Patrika Nagar, Hi-Tech City, Hyderabad – 500081, A.P., India. (Third Author) ABSTRACT: In this research paper, we focus on affine transformations of the coordinate system. The affine transformation consists of linear transformations (rotation, scaling, and shear) and a translation (shift). It provides a good approximation for the changes in pose of objects that are relatively far from the camera. The affine transformation also serves as the basic block in the analysis and registration of general and non rigid geometric transformations. When the area considered is small enough, the affine transformation serves as a first-order Taylor series approximation of any differentiable geometric transformation. Keywords: geometric transformation, global algorithms, geometric-radiometric estimation, structured images, textured images, affine space, collinearity. I. INTRODUCTION The most popular methods for estimating the geometric transformations today are based on local features, such as intensity-based regions (IBR) and edge-based region (EBR) [4], and scale-invariant feature transform (SIFT) [5] and maximally stable extremal regions (MSER) [6].
    [Show full text]
  • Axiomatizations of Hyperbolic and Absolute Geometries
    AXIOMATIZATIONS OF HYPERBOLIC AND ABSOLUTE GEOMETRIES Victor Pambuccian Department of Integrative Studies Arizona State University West, Phoenix, AZ 85069-7100, USA [email protected] The two of us, the two of us, without return, in this world, live, exist, wherever we’d go, we’d meet the same faraway point. Yeghishe Charents, To a chance passerby. Abstract A survey of finite first-order axiomatizations for hyperbolic and absolute geometries. 1. Hyperbolic Geometry Elementary Hyperbolic Geometry as conceived by Hilbert To axiomatize a geometry one needs a language in which to write the axioms, and a logic by means of which to deduce consequences from those axioms. Based on the work of Skolem, Hilbert and Ackermann, Godel,¨ and Tarski, a consensus had been reached by the end of the first half of the 20th century that, as Skolem had emphasized since 1923, “if we are interested in producing an axiomatic system, we can only use first-order logic” ([21, p. 472]). ¢ £ ¤ The language of first-order logic consists of the logical symbols , ¡ , , , , a denumerable list of symbols called individual variables, as well as denumerable lists of ¥ -ary predicate (relation) and function (operation) symbols for all natural numbers ¥ , as well as individual constants (which may be thought of as 0-ary § function symbols), together with two quantifiers, ¦ and which can bind only individual variables, but not sets of individual variables nor predicate or function symbols. Its axioms and rules of deduction are those of classical logic. Axiomatizations in first-order logic preclude the categoricity of the axiomatized models. That is, one cannot provide an axiom system in first-order logic which admits as its only model a geometry over the field of real numbers, as Hilbert [31] had done (in a very strong logic) in his Grundlagen der Geometrie.
    [Show full text]