Four-Volume Cutoff Measure of the Multiverse

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Four-Volume Cutoff Measure of the Multiverse Four-volume cutoff measure of the multiverse The MIT Faculty has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters. Citation Vilenkin, Alexander and Masaki Yamada. "Four-volume cutoff measure of the multiverse." Physical Review D 101, 4 (February 2020): 043520 As Published http://dx.doi.org/10.1103/physrevd.101.043520 Publisher American Physical Society (APS) Version Final published version Citable link https://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/125122 Terms of Use Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 unported license Detailed Terms http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0 PHYSICAL REVIEW D 101, 043520 (2020) Four-volume cutoff measure of the multiverse † Alexander Vilenkin 1,* and Masaki Yamada2, 1Institute of Cosmology, Department of Physics and Astronomy, Tufts University, Medford, Massachusetts 02155, USA 2Center for Theoretical Physics, Laboratory for Nuclear Science and Department of Physics, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, Massachusetts 02139, USA (Received 13 December 2019; accepted 22 January 2020; published 14 February 2020) Predictions in an eternally inflating multiverse are meaningless unless we specify the probability measure. The scale-factor cutoff is perhaps the simplest and most successful measure which avoids catastrophic problems such as the youngness paradox, runaway problem, and Boltzmann brain problem, but it is not well defined in contracting regions with a negative cosmological constant. In this paper, we propose a new measure with properties similar to the scale-factor cutoff which is well-defined everywhere. The measure is defined by a cutoff in the four volume spanned by infinitesimal comoving neighborhoods in a congruence of timelike geodesics. The probability distributions for the cosmological constant and for the curvature parameter in this measure are similar to those for the scale-factor cutoff and are in a good agreement with observations. DOI: 10.1103/PhysRevD.101.043520 I. INTRODUCTION followed by contraction, so a starts to decrease along the geodesics. The scale-factor measure then requires that the Observational predictions in multiverse models depend on entire contracting region to the future of the turnaround one’s choice of the probability measure. Different measure point be included under the cutoff. This gives a higher prescriptions can give vastly different answers. This is the weight to regions of negative Λ, so the scale-factor measure so-called measure problem of eternal inflation. Perhaps the tends to predict that we should expect to measure Λ < 0 simplest way to regulate the infinities of eternal inflation is (unless this is strongly suppressed by anthropic factors). to impose a cutoff on a hypersurface of constant global Some other measure proposals have even more severe time. One starts with a patch of a spacelike hypersurface problems with negative Λ. For example, the light cone time Σ somewhere in the inflating region of spacetime and follows cutoff [8] gives an overwhelming preference for Λ < 0 [9].1 its evolution along the congruence of geodesics orthogonal to In this paper, we introduce a new global time measure Σ. The cutoff is imposed at a hypersurface of constant time t which does not suffer from these problems. We divide the measured along the geodesics. The resulting measure, initial hypersurface Σ into infinitesimally small segments of however, depends on the choice of the time variable t. equal three-volume ϵ → 0 and follow the evolution of these An attractive choice is to use the proper time τ along the segments along the orthogonal congruence of geodesics. The geodesics [1–3]. One finds, however, that this proper time time coordinate Ω is defined as the four volume spanned by measure suffers from the youngness paradox, predicting the segment, that the Universe should be much hotter than observed [4]. Another popular choice is the scale-factor time, t ¼ ln a, Z Z 1 pffiffiffiffiffiffi τ where a is the expansion factor along the geodesics ΩðτÞ¼ −gd4x ¼ dτ0Vð3Þðτ0Þ; ð1:1Þ [1,2,5–7]. The problem with this choice is that the scale- ϵ ð0;τÞ×ϵVð3ÞðτÞ 0 factor evolution is not monotonic. For example, in regions with a negative cosmological constant, Λ < 0, expansion is 1Local measure proposals, which sample spacetime regions around individual geodesics with subsequent averaging over an ensemble of geodesics, yield probability distributions that sensi- *[email protected] tively depend on the choice of the ensemble. This choice is † [email protected] largely arbitrary, and thus these proposals are incomplete as they now stand. The “watcher measure” of Ref. [10] follows a single Published by the American Physical Society under the terms of “eternal” geodesic, but makes the assumption that the big crunch the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International license. singularities in AdS bubbles lead to bounces, where contraction is Further distribution of this work must maintain attribution to followed by expansion, so that geodesics can be continued the author(s) and the published article’s title, journal citation, through the crunch regions. We do not adopt this assumption and DOI. Funded by SCOAP3. in the present paper. 2470-0010=2020=101(4)=043520(8) 043520-1 Published by the American Physical Society ALEXANDER VILENKIN and MASAKI YAMADA PHYS. REV. D 101, 043520 (2020) where ϵVð3ÞðτÞ is the three volume of the evolved segment at by different vacua in the eternally inflating part of space- proper time τ, τ is set equal to zero at Σ,andVð3Þð0Þ¼1. Ω time, assuming low transition rates between the vacua. has a clear geometric meaning and it clearly grows mono- In Secs. 3 and 4, we find, respectively, the probability tonically along the geodesics. The measure is defined by distributions for the cosmological constant and for the density parameter (or spatial curvature) under assumptions imposing a cutoff at Ωc ¼ const. If the Universe can locally be approximated as homogeneous and isotropic, we can similar to those that were used in Refs. [5,12] to calculate write Vð3ÞðτÞ¼a3ðτÞ, where aðτÞ is the scale factor with these distributions in the scale-factor measure. A formalism að0Þ¼1. Then, that can be used to determine the distributions in more Z general landscapes is outlined in Sec. V. Finally, our results τ are briefly summarized and discussed in Sec. VI. ΩðτÞ¼ dτ0a3ðτ0Þ: ð1:2Þ 0 II. VOLUME DISTRIBUTION OF VACUA We can think of the geodesics in the congruence as Consider a multiverse consisting of bubbles of de Sitter representing an ensemble of inertial observers spread uni- (dS) and terminal (anti–de Sitter [AdS] and Minkowski) formly over the initial surface Σ. The measure prescription is vacua, labeled by index j. The expansion rate of dS vacuum then that each observer samples an equal four volume ∝ Ω . c j is H and nucleation rate of bubbles of vacuum i in parent The distribution of “observers” may become rather j vacuum j per Hubble volume per Hubble time is κij. irregular in regions of structure formation. The scale factor κ ≪ 1— [or the three-volume Vð3Þ in Eq. (1.1)] comes to a halt in We shall assume that ij which is expected, since collapsed regions which have decoupled from the Hubble nucleation occurs by quantum tunneling. In this section, we flow and continues to evolve between these regions. shall calculate the three volume occupied by each dS Ω Furthermore, the geodesic congruence may develop caus- vacuum on a surface of constant in the inflating part tics where geodesics cross. One can adopt the rule that of spacetime and use the result to find the abundances of geodesics are terminated as they cross at a caustic. As it was Boltzmann brains in dS vacua. We shall not be interested in noted in Ref. [11], this does not create any gaps in the volumes occupied by terminal vacua in this section. congruence. But the resulting cutoff surface would still be rather irregular. Such dependence of the measure on details A. Relation to scale-factor cutoff of structure formation appears unsatisfactory and calls for An approximate relation between the four-volume and some sort of coarse graining, with averaging over the scale-factor cutoffs can be found if we note that the scale characteristic length scale of structure formation. This issue factor grows exponentially in the inflating regions, and was emphasized in Ref. [6] in the case of scale-factor therefore the integral in Eq. (1.2) is dominated by the measure and was further discussed in Ref. [7]. upper limit. In a region occupied by vacuum j, the scale Ω Hjτ A somewhat related problem is that even though factor is ajðτÞ¼Ce with C ¼ const., so we can write grows monotonically along geodesics of the congruence, approximately the surfaces of constant Ω are not necessarily spacelike, Z so Ω is not a good global time coordinate. As a result, an τ a3ðτÞ Ω ðτÞ ≈ 3ðτ0Þ τ0 ≈ j ð Þ event may be included under the cutoff, while some events j a d : 2:1 j 3H in its causal past are not included. A possible way to cure j Ω ¼ Ω this problem is to modify the cutoff surface c by Ω ¼ Ω ¼ 2 The cutoff surface at c const can then be excluding future light cones of all points on that surface. approximated as Then all events under the cutoff are included together with their causal past. This prescription also alleviates the a3ðτÞ problem of sensitivity of the measure to structure forma- ¼ Ω ; ð2:2Þ 3H c tion. If the characteristic scale of structure formation is j much smaller than the horizon, the modified cutoff surface so the four-volume cutoff at Ω ¼ Ω is approximately would roughly coincide with a constant Ω surface in the c equivalent to the scale-factor cutoff at background Friedmann-Robertson-Walker geometry.
Recommended publications
  • Vilenkin's Cosmic Vision a Review Essay of Emmany Worlds in One
    Vilenkin's Cosmic Vision A Review Essay of emMany Worlds in One The Search for Other Universesem, by Alex Vilenkin William Lane Craig Used by permission of Philosophia Christi 11 (2009): 231-8. SUMMARY Vilenkin's recent book is a wonderful popular introduction to contemporary cosmology. It contains provocative discussions of both the beginning of the universe and of the fine-tuning of the universe for intelligent life. Vilenkin is a prominent exponent of the multiverse hypothesis, which features in the book's title. His defense of this hypothesis depends in a crucial and interesting way on conflating time and space. His claim that his theory of the quantum creation of the universe explains the origin of the universe from nothing trades on a misunderstanding of "nothing." VILENKIN'S COSMIC VISION A REVIEW ESSAY OF EMMANY WORLDS IN ONE THE SEARCH FOR OTHER UNIVERSESEM, BY ALEX VILENKIN The task of scientific popularization is a difficult one. Too many authors think that it is to be accomplished by frequent resort to explanatorily vacuous and obfuscating metaphors which leave the reader puzzling over what exactly a particular theory asserts. One of the great merits of Alexander Vilenkin's book is that he shuns this route in favor of straightforward, simple explanations of key terms and ideas. Couple that with a writing style that is marvelously lucid, and you have one of the best popularizations of current physical cosmology available from one of its foremost practitioners. Vilenkin vigorously champions the idea that we live in a multiverse, that is to say, the causally connected universe is but one domain in a much vaster cosmos which comprises an infinite number of such domains.
    [Show full text]
  • Exploring Cosmic Strings: Observable Effects and Cosmological Constraints
    EXPLORING COSMIC STRINGS: OBSERVABLE EFFECTS AND COSMOLOGICAL CONSTRAINTS A dissertation submitted by Eray Sabancilar In partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Physics TUFTS UNIVERSITY May 2011 ADVISOR: Prof. Alexander Vilenkin To my parents Afife and Erdal, and to the memory of my grandmother Fadime ii Abstract Observation of cosmic (super)strings can serve as a useful hint to understand the fundamental theories of physics, such as grand unified theories (GUTs) and/or superstring theory. In this regard, I present new mechanisms to pro- duce particles from cosmic (super)strings, and discuss their cosmological and observational effects in this dissertation. The first chapter is devoted to a review of the standard cosmology, cosmic (super)strings and cosmic rays. The second chapter discusses the cosmological effects of moduli. Moduli are relatively light, weakly coupled scalar fields, predicted in supersymmetric particle theories including string theory. They can be emitted from cosmic (super)string loops in the early universe. Abundance of such moduli is con- strained by diffuse gamma ray background, dark matter, and primordial ele- ment abundances. These constraints put an upper bound on the string tension 28 as strong as Gµ . 10− for a wide range of modulus mass m. If the modulus coupling constant is stronger than gravitational strength, modulus radiation can be the dominant energy loss mechanism for the loops. Furthermore, mod- ulus lifetimes become shorter for stronger coupling. Hence, the constraints on string tension Gµ and modulus mass m are significantly relaxed for strongly coupled moduli predicted in superstring theory. Thermal production of these particles and their possible effects are also considered.
    [Show full text]
  • The Anthropic Principle and Multiple Universe Hypotheses Oren Kreps
    The Anthropic Principle and Multiple Universe Hypotheses Oren Kreps Contents Abstract ........................................................................................................................................... 1 Introduction ..................................................................................................................................... 1 Section 1: The Fine-Tuning Argument and the Anthropic Principle .............................................. 3 The Improbability of a Life-Sustaining Universe ....................................................................... 3 Does God Explain Fine-Tuning? ................................................................................................ 4 The Anthropic Principle .............................................................................................................. 7 The Multiverse Premise ............................................................................................................ 10 Three Classes of Coincidence ................................................................................................... 13 Can The Existence of Sapient Life Justify the Multiverse? ...................................................... 16 How unlikely is fine-tuning? .................................................................................................... 17 Section 2: Multiverse Theories ..................................................................................................... 18 Many universes or all possible
    [Show full text]
  • Module 2—Evidence for God from Contemporary Science (Irish Final)
    Module 2—Evidence for God from Contemporary Science (Irish Final) Intro There is a long and strong relationship between the natural sciences and the Catholic Church. At least 286 priests and clergy were involved in the development of all branches of the natural sciences,1 and the Catholic Church hosts an Academy of Sciences with 46 Nobel Prize Winners as well as thousands of University and high school science departments, astronomical observatories and scientific institutes throughout the world (see Module III Section V). This should not be surprising, because as we saw in the previous Module most of the greatest scientific minds throughout history were believers (theists), and today, 51% of scientists are declared believers, as well as 88% of physicians. This gives rise to the question, “if scientists and physicians are evidence-based people, why are the majority of scientists and physicians believers?” What is their evidence? Many scientists, such as Albert Einstein and Eugene Wigner intuited clues of a divine intelligence from the wholly unexpected pervasive mathematical ordering of the universe.2 Today, the evidence for an intelligent transphysical creator is stronger than ever before despite the proliferation of many hypothetical new models of physical reality which at first seem to suggest the non-necessity of a creator. These new models include a multiverse, universes in the higher dimensional space of string theory, and multidimensional bouncing universes. So, what is this evidence that points to an intelligent creator even of multiverses, string universes, and multi- dimensional bouncing universes? There are 3 principal areas of evidence, each of which will be discussed in this Module: 1.
    [Show full text]
  • The Reason Series: What Science Says About God
    Teacher’s Resource Manual The Reason Series: What Science Says About God By Robert J. Spitzer, S.J., Ph.D. and Claude LeBlanc, M.A. Nihil Obstat: Reverend David Leigh, S.J., Ph.D. July 6, 2012 Imprimatur: Most Reverend Tod D. Brown Bishop of Orange, California July 11, 2012 Magis Center of Reason and Faith www.magiscenter.com USCCB Approval: The USCCB Subcommittee for Catechetical Conformity gives approval only for curricula, text book series, teacher’s manuals, or student workbooks that concern a whole course of studies. Partial curricula and programs may obtain ecclesiastical approval by imprimatur from the local Bishop. Since The Reason Series is such a partial curriculum its ecclesiastical approval by the USCCB is validated by the imprimatur. Cover art by Jim Breen Photos: Photos from the Hubble Telescope: courtesy NASA, PD-US Stephen Hawking (page 19): courtesy NASA, PD-US Galileo (page 20): PD-Art Arno Penzias (page 25): courtesy Kartik J, GNU Free Documentation License Aristotle (page 41): courtesy Eric Gaba, Creative Commons Albert Einstein (page 49): PD-Art Georges Lemaitre (page 49): PD-Art Alexander Vilenkin (page 51): courtesy Lumidek, Creative Commons Alan Guth (page 51): courtesy Betsy Devine, Creative Commons Roger Penrose (page 71): PD-Art Paul Davies (page 71): courtesy Arizona State University, PD-Art Sir Arthur Eddington (page 92): courtesy Library of Congress, PD-US Revision © 2016 Magis Institute (Garden Grove, California) All Rights Reserved No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the written permission of the author.
    [Show full text]
  • Time in Cosmology
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Philsci-Archive Time in Cosmology Craig Callender∗ C. D. McCoyy 21 August 2017 Readers familiar with the workhorse of cosmology, the hot big bang model, may think that cosmology raises little of interest about time. As cosmological models are just relativistic spacetimes, time is under- stood just as it is in relativity theory, and all cosmology adds is a few bells and whistles such as inflation and the big bang and no more. The aim of this chapter is to show that this opinion is not completely right...and may well be dead wrong. In our survey, we show how the hot big bang model invites deep questions about the nature of time, how inflationary cosmology has led to interesting new perspectives on time, and how cosmological speculation continues to entertain dramatically different models of time altogether. Together these issues indicate that the philosopher interested in the nature of time would do well to know a little about modern cosmology. Different claims about time have long been at the heart of cosmology. Ancient creation myths disagree over whether time is finite or infinite, linear or circular. This speculation led to Kant complaining in his famous antinomies that metaphysical reasoning about the nature of time leads to a “euthanasia of reason”. But neither Kant’s worry nor cosmology becoming a modern science succeeded in ending the speculation. Einstein’s first model of the universe portrays a temporally infinite universe, where space is edgeless and its material contents unchanging.
    [Show full text]
  • Creation Ex Nihilo: Theology and Science William Lane Craig
    Creation ex nihilo: Theology and Science William Lane Craig SUMMARY The biblical doctrine of temporal creation ex nihilo has received strong scientific confirmation from post-relativistic physics. Two lines of evidence point to an absolute beginning of the universe: the expansion of the universe and the thermodynamics of the universe. In each case attempts to maintain a past-eternal universe have become increasingly difficult to defend. Given the beginning of the universe, the question arises as to how the universe could have come into being. Attempts by some physicists to maintain that physics can explain the origin of the universe from nothing either trade on an equivocal use of the term “nothing” or else are guilty of philosophical faux pas. Supernatural creation ex nihilo is the better explanation. CREATION EX NIHILO: THEOLOGY AND SCIENCE Introduction “In the beginning God created the heavens and the earth” (Gen. 1.1). With majestic simplicity the author of the opening chapter of Genesis thus differentiated his viewpoint, not only from the ancient creation myths of Israel’s neighbors, but also effectively from pantheism, such as is found in religions like Vedanta Hinduism and Taoism, from panentheism, whether of classical neo- Platonist vintage or twentieth-century process theology, and from polytheism, ranging from ancient paganism to contemporary Mormonism. The biblical writers give us to understand that the universe had a temporal origin and thus imply creatio ex nihilo in the temporal sense that God brought the universe into being without a material cause at some point in the finite past. [1] Moreover, the Church Fathers, though heavily influenced by Greek thought, dug in their heels concerning the doctrine of creation, sturdily insisting on the temporal creation of the universe ex nihilo in opposition to the prevailing Hellenistic doctrine of the eternity of matter.
    [Show full text]
  • A Scenario for a Natural Origin of Our Universe Using a Mathematical Model Based on Established Physics and Cosmology
    A Scenario for a Natural Origin of Our Universe Using a Mathematical Model Based on Established Physics and Cosmology Victor J. Stenger Abstract: A mathematical model of the natural origin of our universe is presented. The model is based only on well-established physics. No claim is made that this model uniquely represents exactly how the universe came about. But the viability of a single model serves to refute any assertions that the universe cannot have come about by natural means. Why is there something rather than nothing? This question is often the last resort of the theist who seeks to argue for the existence of God from physics and cosmology and finds all his other arguments fail. Philosopher Bede Rundle calls it "philosophy's central, and most perplexing, question." His simple (but book-length) answer, "There has to be something."1 Clearly many conceptual problems are associated with this question. How do we define "nothing"? What are its properties? If it has properties, doesn't that make it something? The theist claims that God is the answer. But, then, why is there God rather than nothing? Assuming we can define "nothing," why should nothing be a more natural state of affairs than something? In fact, we can give a plausible scientific reason based on 2 our best current knowledge of physics and cosmology that something is more natural than nothing! It is commonly believed that the universe cannot have come about naturally. Although many authors writing at both the popular and academic levels have described various scenarios for a natural origin, usually based on the vague notion of "quantum fluctuations," even they admit that their ideas are speculative and surrender to the prevailing wisdom that the origin of our universe remains unexplained.2 What is it that science does when it "explains" some phenomenon? At least in the case of the physical sciences, it builds a mathematical model to describe the empirical data associated with the phenomenon.
    [Show full text]
  • The Future of Theoretical Physics and Cosmology Celebrating Stephen Hawking's 60Th Birthday
    The Future of Theoretical Physics and Cosmology Celebrating Stephen Hawking's 60th Birthday Edited by G. W. GIBBONS E. P. S. SHELLARD S. J. RANKIN CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS Contents List of contributors xvii Preface xxv 1 Introduction Gary Gibbons and Paul Shellard 1 1.1 Popular symposium 2 1.2 Spacetime singularities 3 1.3 Black holes 4 1.4 Hawking radiation 5 1.5 Quantum gravity 6 1.6 M theory and beyond 7 1.7 De Sitter space 8 1.8 Quantum cosmology 9 1.9 Cosmology 9 1.10 Postscript 10 Part 1 Popular symposium 15 2 Our complex cosmos and its future Martin Rees '• • •. V 17 2.1 Introduction . ...... 17 2.2 The universe observed . 17 2.3 Cosmic microwave background radiation 22 2.4 The origin of large-scale structure 24 2.5 The fate of the universe 26 2.6 The very early universe 30 vi Contents 2.7 Multiverse? 35 2.8 The future of cosmology • 36 3 Theories of everything and Hawking's wave function of the universe James Hartle 38 3.1 Introduction 38 3.2 Different things fall with the same acceleration in a gravitational field 38 3.3 The fundamental laws of physics 40 3.4 Quantum mechanics 45 3.5 A theory of everything is not a theory of everything 46 3.6 Reduction 48 3.7 The main points again 49 References 49 4 The problem of spacetime singularities: implications for quantum gravity? Roger Penrose 51 4.1 Introduction 51 4.2 Why quantum gravity? 51 4.3 The importance of singularities 54 4.4 Entropy 58 4.5 Hawking radiation and information loss 61 4.6 The measurement paradox 63 4.7 Testing quantum gravity? 70 Useful references for further
    [Show full text]
  • Eternal Inflation, Past and Future
    Eternal Inflation, past and future Anthony Aguirre1 Department of Physics/SCIPP UC Santa Cruz 1156 High St., Santa Cruz, CA 95064 [email protected] Cosmological inflation, if it occurred, radically alters the picture of the `big bang', which would merely point to reheating at the end of inflation. More- over, this reheating may be only local so that inflation continues elsewhere and forever, continually spawning big-bang-like regions. This chapter reviews this idea of `eternal inflation’, then focuses on what this may mean for the ul- timate beginning of the universe. In particular, I will argue that given eternal inflation, the universe may be free of a cosmological initial singularity, might be eternal (and eternally inflating) to the past, and might obey an interesting sort of cosmological time-symmetry. 1 The inflationary Genie Cosmological inflation, as discussed at length in Chapter 2, was developed as a means of explaining the very simple yet specific `initial' conditions that define the hot big-bang cosmological model. But while inflation grants the wish of providing a very large, uniform, hot, monopole-free region with ap- propriate density fluctuations, it is also, like the proverbial Genie let out of the bottle, difficult to contain. In most inflation models, the selfsame accel- erated expansion that allows inflation’s explanatory and predictive successes also completely changes the ultra-large-scale structure of the universe in which it occurs, through the process of `everlasting' or `eternal' inflation.1 In this picture, once inflation starts, it continues forever { at least some- where { continually spawning non-inflating regions large enough to be our arXiv:0712.0571v1 [hep-th] 4 Dec 2007 entire observable universe.
    [Show full text]
  • Many Worlds in One: the Search for Other Universes
    on many of the topics in the text; his ex- quantum fluctuations amplified during perience is reflected in the interesting Many Worlds inflation. Those quantum fluctuations and cohesive perspectives related to the later give rise to galaxies. different subjects discussed and in the in One However, a few years after the inven- adaptation of calculations from his own The Search for Other tion of inflationary theory, cosmologists work to new, substantial, and intrigu- Universes realized that the theory may have some ing problems. unforeseen consequences. Like water, Each chapter has two short intro- Alex Vilenkin which can be either solid or liquid in ductions: one to outline its contents and Hill and Wang, New York, 2006. different parts of the ocean, vacuum $24.00 (235 pp.). the other to discuss the exercises at the may have different properties in differ- ISBN 978-0-8090-9523-0 end of the chapter. The introductions ent parts of the universe. Inflation are most useful for providing context, Alexander Vilenkin’s Many Worlds in makes each of those parts uniform and and they help the flow of the presenta- One: The Search for Other Universes is a exponentially large, so by looking at tion. The one choice made by the author beautifully written story of a new any of those parts, one would think, in- with which I disagree is that he did not worldview that has developed during correctly, that the whole universe looks provide literature recommendations the past 25 years. Cosmologists associ- the same everywhere. when he did not cover a topic in depth.
    [Show full text]
  • The Reason: What Science Says About God
    Teacher’s Resource Manual The Reason: What Science Says About God By Robert J. Spitzer, S.J., Ph.D. and Claude LeBlanc, M.A . Magis Center of Reason and Faith www.magisreasonfaith.org Cover art by Jim Breen Photos: Photos from the Hubble Telescope: courtesy NASA, PD-US Stephen Hawking (page 19): courtesy NASA, PD-US Galileo (page 20): PD-Art Arno Penzias (page 25): courtesy Kartik J, GNU Free Documentation License Aristotle (page 41): courtesy Eric Gaba, Creative Commons Albert Einstein (page 49): PD-Art Georges Lemaitre (page 49): PD-Art Alexander Vilenkin (page 51): courtesy Lumidek, Creative Commons Alan Guth (page 51): courtesy Betsy Devine, Creative Commons Roger Penrose (page 71): PD-Art Paul Davies (page 71): courtesy Arizona State University, PD-Art Sir Arthur Eddington (page 92): courtesy Library of Congress, PD-US © 2012 Magis Institute (Irvine, California) All Rights Reserved No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the written permission of the author. This edition published by: Magis Publications 2532 Dupont Drive Irvine, California 92612 www.magisreasonfaith.org ISBN: 978-0-9838945-1-3 Printed in the United States of America “It is said that an argument is what convinces reasonable men and a proof is what it takes to convince even an unreasonable man. With the proof now in place, cosmologists can no longer hide behind the possibility of a past-eternal universe… There is no escape, they have to face the problem of a cosmic beginning.” From Many Worlds in One: The Search for Other Universes (New York Macmillan) 2007, by Dr.
    [Show full text]