Nagarjuna's Madhyamaka: Some Philosophical Problems

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Nagarjuna's Madhyamaka: Some Philosophical Problems Nagarjuna’s Madhyamaka: Some philosophical problems Jan Westerhof Department of Philosophy University of Durham www.janwesterhof.net [email protected] 1 Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka Slide Nāgārjuna’s historical background • 2nd to 3rd century AD • lived mainly in Southern India • six extant philosophical treatises, plenty of later commentarial works Jan October 2007 Westerhof 2 Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka Slide The theory of emptiness . everything is empty of svabhāva . epistemological and ontological notion of svabhāva: • essence: what an object cannot lose while remaining that very object • substance: something which does not depend for its existence on anything else . Only substance-svabhāva is the Mādhyamika’s object of refutation. Jan October 2007 Westerhof 3 Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka Slide Two general problems . Madhyamaka arguments present both general and specific arguments for the thesis of universal emptiness. Reflective problems for the thesis of universal emptiness: • the emptiness of emptiness • the emptiness of the theory of emptiness (the antirealist’s dilemma) Jan October 2007 Westerhof 4 Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka Slide The emptiness of emptiness . Is emptiness itself empty? `Ultimate reality for the Buddhas is svabhāva itself. That, moreover, because it is nondeceptive is the truth of ultimate reality. It must be known by each one for himself.’ . Svabhāva and emptiness are characterized as changeless, not originated, and not dependent on anything else. Emptiness appears to be a contradictory concept. Candrakirti’s Madhyamakāvatārabhāsya 108: 16-19. 5 Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka Slide Priest’s response . The contradictory notion of emptiness shows that reality itself is contradictory. `Reality has no nature. Ultimately, it is not any way at all. On the other side of the street emptiness [the lack of an ultimate nature] is an ultimate characteristic of things. The paradox is grounded in the contradictory nature of reality itself.’ Graham Priest: `Nāgārjuna and the limits of thought’, in: Beyond the Limits of Thought, OUP 2002, 267. 6 Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka Slide An alternative response . `being changeless, not originated and independent’ means something diferent when applied to svabhāva and to emptiness • emptiness is independent because its existence does not depend on some specific object • emptiness is changeless and not originated because it is the property of every object and not produced together with the empty object Jan October 2007 Westerhof 7 Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka Slide Emptiness does not exist by substance- svabhāva . emptiness is not a property phenomena have independently of anything else . example of vitreous floaters . emptiness is dependent since its purpose is to dispel an erroneous conception of objects Jan October 2007 Westerhof 8 Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka Slide Emptiness is the essence-svabhāva of all objects . as heat is the essence of fire emptiness is the essence of all things . the notion of emptiness is not contradictory because emptiness does not constitute an underlying substance . emptiness is no noumenal reality but simply a property objects could not lose without ceasing to be those very objects Jan October 2007 Westerhof 9 Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka Slide The emptiness of the theory of emptiness Antirealist’s dilemma: . For the global anti-realist, what is the status of the theory of global anti-realism itself? • it is an absolute truth: inconsistency • it is relative: no impact Emptiness of the theory of emptiness: . If everything is empty, what is the status of the claim asserting universal emptiness? • it is not empty: inconsistency • it is empty: impotence Jan October 2007 Westerhof 10 Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka Slide Thomas Nagel The claim `everything is subjective’ must be nonsense, for it would itself have to be either subjective or objective. But it can’t be objective, since in that case it would be false if true. And it can’t be subjective, because then it would not rule out any objective claim, including the claim that it is objectively false. […] It is a report of what the subjectivist finds agreeable to say. If he also invites us to join him, we need not ofer any reason for declining since he has ofered us not reason to accept. The Last Word, OUP 1997, page 15. 11 Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka Slide Nāgārjuna’s opponent If there is no substance of things, your statement [that everything is empty] must be devoid of substance too. Therefore it cannot deny the substance of things. […] A non-existent fire cannot burn, a non-existent knife cannot cut […]. But if your statement has a substance your original position is destroyed. There is a contradiction and you have to give the special reason why your statement is not to be counted amongst all things. Vigrahavyāvartanī 1-2. 12 Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka Slide Considering possible replies . embracing the first horn is not attractive . finding a reply to the `no impact/ impotence’ charge • alternative interpretation of the second horn • understanding the force of Nāgārjuna’s opponent’s argument Jan October 2007 Westerhof 13 Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka Slide The `no thesis’ reply ‘If I had a thesis the difculty you mention would apply to me. However, I do not hold any thesis. Therefore there is no defect in my position.’ . Nāgārjuna denies that he asserts any thesis which is to be interpreted according to the opponent’s semantics: • referring to a `ready-made world’ • relying on an objective reference relation Vigrahavyāvartanī 29. 14 Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka Slide A question of semantics . In order to reply to the second horn of the dilemma it is necessary to develop a theory of meaning and truth which dispenses with the notion of a non-linguistic world. treat language not as a means of representation but as a set of conventions for coordination between agents Jan October 2007 Westerhof 15.
Recommended publications
  • Studies in Buddhist Hetuvidyā (Epistemology and Logic ) in Europe and Russia
    Nataliya Kanaeva STUDIES IN BUDDHIST HETUVIDYĀ (EPISTEMOLOGY AND LOGIC ) IN EUROPE AND RUSSIA Working Paper WP20/2015/01 Series WP20 Philosophy of Culture and Cultural Studies Moscow 2015 УДК 24 ББК 86.36 K19 Editor of the series WP20 «Philosophy of Culture and Cultural Studies» Vitaly Kurennoy Kanaeva, Nataliya. K19 Studies in Buddhist Hetuvidyā (Epistemology and Logic ) in Europe and Russia [Text] : Working paper WP20/2015/01 / N. Kanaeva ; National Research University Higher School of Economics. – Moscow : Higher School of Economics Publ. House, 2015. – (Series WP20 “Philosophy of Culture and Cultural Studiesˮ) – 52 p. – 20 copies. This publication presents an overview of the situation in studies of Buddhist epistemology and logic in Western Europe and in Russia. Those studies are the young direction of Buddhology, and they started only at the beginning of the XX century. There are considered the main schools, their representatives, the directions of their researches and achievements in the review. The activity of Russian scientists in this field was not looked through ever before. УДК 24 ББК 86.36 This study (research grant № 14-01-0006) was supported by The National Research University Higher School of Economics (Moscow). Academic Fund Program in 2014–2015. Kanaeva Nataliya – National Research University Higher School of Economics (Moscow). Department of Humanities. School of Philosophy. Assistant professor; [email protected]. Канаева, Н. А. Исследования буддийской хетувидьи (эпистемологии и логики) в Европе и России (обзор) [Текст] : препринт WP20/2015/01 / Н. А. Канаева ; Нац. исслед. ун-т «Высшая школа экономи- ки». – М.: Изд. дом Высшей школы экономики, 2015. – (Серия WP20 «Философия и исследо- вания культуры»).
    [Show full text]
  • Finnigan Madhyamaka Ethics 2018
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers This is a draft of a chapter that appears in The Oxford Handbook of Buddhist Ethics ed- ited by Dr Daniel Cozort and Dr James Mark Shields (2018) Madhyamaka Ethics Bronwyn Finnigan 12 Abstract There are two main loci of contemporary debate about the nature of Madhyamaka ethics. The first investigates the general issue of wheth- er the Madhyamaka philosophy of emptiness (śūnyavāda) is consistent with a commitment to systematic ethical distinctions. The second queries whether the metaphysical analysis of no-self presented by Śāntideva in his Bodhicaryāvatāra entails the impartial benevolence of a bodhisattva. This article will critically examine these debates and demonstrate the ways in which they are shaped by competing under- standings of Madhyamaka conventional truth or reality (saṃvṛtisatya) and the forms of reasoning admissible for differentiating conventional truth from falsity and good from bad. 1 School of Philosophy, Research School of Social Sciences, Australian National Univer- sity. Email: [email protected]. 2 Many thanks to Sara McClintock, Tom Tillemans and the editors of this collection for helpful comments on a previous draft of this paper. I am also grateful for feedback from participants of the Australasian Workshop in Moral Philosophy (2016). 2 Finnigan, Madhyamaka Ethics Introduction Madhyamaka is one of two major philosophical schools of Mahāyāna Buddhism, alongside Yogācāra. It is best known for its philosophy of emptiness (śūnyavāda) as articulated by Nāgārjuna in his Mūlamadh- yamakakārikā and has an illustrious lineage of eminent exponents in In- dia, Tibet and China.
    [Show full text]
  • From Mādhyamika to Yogācāra, an Analysis of MMK, XXIV. 18 and MV
    THE JOURNAL OF THE INTERNATIONAL ASSOCIATION OF BUDDHIST STUDIES EDITOR-IN-CHIEF A. K. Narain University of Wisconsin, Madison, USA EDITORS Heinz Bechert Leon Hurvitz Universitat Gottingen FRG University of British Columbia Vancouver, Canada Lewis Lancaster A. W. MacDonald University of California, Berkeley, USA Universiti de Paris X, Nanterre, France B. J. Stavisky Alex Wayman WCNILKR, Moscow, USSR Columbia University, New York, USA ASSOCIATE EDITOR Stephen Beyer University of Wisconsin, Madison, USA Volume 2 1979 Number 1 TABLE OF CONTENTS I. ARTICLES 1. The Mongol Khans and Chinese Buddhism and Taoism, by Sechin Jagchid 2. From Madhyamika to Yogacara, an Analysis of MMK, XXIV. 18 and MV, 1.1-2, by Gadjin m. Nagao 3. Dynamic Liberation in Yogacara Buddhism, by Alan Sponberg 4. Yogacara and the Buddhist Logicians, by Alex Wayman II. SHORT PAPERS 1. Sambodhi in ASoka's 8th Rock Edict, by A. L. Basham 81 2. Can Meditational Practice be Measured? A Report on a Quantitative Survey, by Jacques Maquet 84 3. Nirvana and Metaphysical Experience, by Ismael Quiles 91 III. BOOK REVIEWS AND NOTICES Reviews: 1. World Conqueror and World Renouncer, by S.J. Tambiah 99 2. Comparative Ethics in Hindu and Buddhist Traditions, by Roderick Hindery. 103 3. Mahayana Buddhist Meditation: Theory and Practice, by Minoru Kiyota, assisted by Elvin W. Jones 106 4. Chandi Borobudur: A Monument of Mankind, by Dr. Soekmono 108 Obituary: 1. Paul Demieville, by Alexander W. Macdonald 110 FROM MADHYAMIKA TO YOGACARA An Analysis of MMK, XXIV. 18 and MV, 1.1-2 by Gadjin M. Nagao In the Sino-Japanese Buddhist tradition, the Madhyamika and Yogacara-Vijnanavada tenets have been understood to be both parallel and opposite to each other.
    [Show full text]
  • Unearthing the Foundations of Tibetan Buddhist Philosophy
    Introduction Unearthing the foundations of Tibetan Buddhist philosophy Pascale Hugon and Kevin Vose The contributions to this volume are the result of a panel on the theme “Tibetan Scholasticism in the 11th and 12th centuries” or- ganized at the 15th Conference of the International Association of Buddhist Studies held at Emory University, Atlanta, in June 2008.1 Our motivation for this panel came in great part from the recent surfacing of new material pertaining to this period, which opens the way to novel research on the development of Tibetan Buddhism in the early part of the Second Diff usion (phyi dar). In particular, the 2006 publication of the fi rst 30-volume set of the bKaʼ gdams gsuṅ ʼbum by the dPal brtsegs Institute for Ancient Tibetan Manuscripts (dpal brtsegs bod yig dpe rñiṅ źib ʼjug khaṅ)2 1 Three further papers were presented in the IABS panel at Emory: “Roṅ zom Chos kyi bzaṅ po’s Subclassifi cation of the Madhyamaka School” by Orna Almogi, “Roṅ zom Chos kyi bzaṅ po on ‘Dialectics’ (mtshan ñid), ‘Secret Mantra’ (gsaṅ sṅags), and the ‘View’ (lta ba)” by Nathaniel Rich, and “Challenging Candrakīrti: Phywa pa Chos kyi seṅ ge’s Criticism of Prāsaṅgika-Madhyamaka” by Dorji Wangchuk. Owing to other commitments, these could not be included in the present vol- ume. Thomas Doctor’s paper was originally presented in the panel “Madhyamaka and Yogācāra Models of Truth or Reality in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism.” 2 The fi rst 30 volumes appeared in 2006 and a second set of 30 vol- umes in 2007.
    [Show full text]
  • Madhyamaka and Yogācāra: Allies Or Rivals? Eds
    Madhyamaka and Yogācāra: Allies or Rivals? eds. by Jay L. Garfield and Jan Westerhoff (review) Oren Hanner Philosophy East and West, Volume 68, Number 2, April 2018, pp. 629-633 (Review) Published by University of Hawai'i Press For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/690307 Access provided by University of California @ Berkeley (14 Apr 2018 01:33 GMT) and thought. I highly recommend this book to anyone interested in the life and thought of a seminal Korean Confucian philosopher. Note 1 – Edward Y. J. Chung, The Korean Neo-Confucianism of Yi T’oegye and Yi Yulgok: A Re- appraisal of the “Four-Seven Thesis” and Its Practical Implications for Self-Cultivation (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1995). Madhyamaka and Yogācāra: Allies or Rivals? Edited by Jay L. Garfield and Jan Wester- hoff. New York: Oxford University Press, 2015. Pp. xi + 280. Hardcover $105.00, ISBN 978-0-1902-3128-6. Paper $36.95, ISBN 978-0-1902-3129-3. Reviewed by Oren Hanner University of California, Berkeley [email protected] Recent decades have witnessed a number of scholarly attempts to illuminate the philosophical affinity between the Madhyamaka and Yogācāra, the two main systems of thought in the Mahāyāna stream of Buddhism. Both schools originated in India in the first centuries of the common era, and had a significant impact on the doc- trines of Asian Buddhism in such countries as China, Korea, Tibet, and Japan. Conse- quently, their views concerning reality have been documented in various textual sources, ranging from early philosophical treatises by their chief founders, Nāgārjuna (Madhyamaka) and Vasubandhu and Asaṅga (Yogācāra), to sūtras and later commen- taries.
    [Show full text]
  • A Synopsis of the Madhyamaka- Alazkdra of Sntaraksita (1)
    A Synopsis of the Madhyamaka- alazkdra of Sntaraksita (1) Masamichi Ichigo Santaraksita was born in a time of great scholarly activity for the four Buddhist schools: Vaibhasika, Sautrantika, Yogacarin and Madhyamika. They were already well established and were emulating each other in their philosophies. It is saidl) that he, together with his pupil Kamalasila, established the so-called Madhyamika-Yogacarin synthetic school, on the one hand, inheriting through Jnanagarbha the two-truth theory of Bhavaviveka, a man who was one of the leaders of the Madhyamika school; and, on the other hand, being influenced by the logic and epistemology of Dharmakirti, a founder of the Sautrantika-Yogacarin synthetic school. The Madhyamakalamkara of Santaraksita has been referred to here and there and is historically known to use). It is considered to be the basic source for the Yogacara-Sautrantika-Madhyamika3>, and judging from the way it is described in Tibetan histories, it, rather than Tattvasarhgraha, can be supposed to be Santaraksita's main work. But its contents have been obscured so faro). This may be partly because the text is extant only in Tibetan translation. The Madhyamakalamkara-karika (MAK), listed in the Catalogue of Peking Reprint Editions (CPRE) as no. 5284, is composed of 97 verses. Santaraksita's 1) S. Katsura, Dharmakirti ni okeru Jikoninshiki no Riron (Dharmakirti's Theory of Svasamvedana), Nanto Bukkyo, No. 23, p. 29, 2) F. D. Lessing & A. Wayman, Mkhas grub rje's fundamentals of the Buddhist tantr as, Mouton 1968, p. 91. G. N. Roerich, The blue annals, Part one, Royal Asiatic Society of Bengal, Monograph Series vol.
    [Show full text]
  • 85The Madhyamaka Speaks to the West.Pdf
    Kent Academic Repository Full text document (pdf) Citation for published version McGuire, Robert (2015) The Madhyamaka Speaks to the West: A philosophical analysis of nyat as a universal truth. Doctor of Philosophy (PhD) thesis, University of Kent,. DOI Link to record in KAR https://kar.kent.ac.uk/54341/ Document Version UNSPECIFIED Copyright & reuse Content in the Kent Academic Repository is made available for research purposes. Unless otherwise stated all content is protected by copyright and in the absence of an open licence (eg Creative Commons), permissions for further reuse of content should be sought from the publisher, author or other copyright holder. Versions of research The version in the Kent Academic Repository may differ from the final published version. Users are advised to check http://kar.kent.ac.uk for the status of the paper. Users should always cite the published version of record. Enquiries For any further enquiries regarding the licence status of this document, please contact: [email protected] If you believe this document infringes copyright then please contact the KAR admin team with the take-down information provided at http://kar.kent.ac.uk/contact.html The Madhyamaka Speaks to the West A philosophical analysis of śūnyatā as a universal truth by Robert McGuire A thesis submitted in fulfilment of the requirements of a Doctor of Philosophy in Theology and Religious Studies Department of Religious Studies School of European Culture and Languages October 2015 (word count: 99,617) This work was supported by the Arts and Humanities Research Council under Grant number AH/K503046/1.
    [Show full text]
  • Santaraksita and Modern Philosophy
    SANTARAKSITA AND MODERN PHILOSOPHY Marie-Louise Friquegnon William Paterson University The philosopher Santaraksita was born in Bengal, the son of the king, in the same family as Atisa.. Renouncing worldly honors, he became a monk. Eagerly pursuing knowledge, he became one of the greatest Buddhist philosopher of all time. Professor of philosophy and abbot at the famous university-monastery of Nalanda in north India, he analyzed and refuted many tenets of Buddhist and non-Buddhist schools. Summary: Santaraksita asserted nothing to be true on the absolute level. But on the relative level he claimed that all of reality was nothing other than mind. He arrived at his philosophical position in the following way. There are two possible candidates for the nature of reality, -material and mental. If reality is material, it must be made of parts. The smallest of these are said to be atoms. But if they are the smallest, they must be indivisible. However, if they are indivisible, they can have no extension. (For the only number which is indivisible is zero.) Nor can they have sides to attach to one another, for if they had sides, they would be divisible into those sides. So they cannot combine to make up larger objects. So it would seem that the only alternative is that reality is mental. It is, after all, impossible to deny awareness without utilizing awareness. But there are problems with the concept of mind and its relation to an object. Mind is either one or many, a unity or a plurality, one with its object or different.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    Introduction The Philosophical Grounds and Literary History of Zhentong Klaus-Dieter Mathes and Michael R. Sheehy Though the subject of emptiness śūnyatā( , stong pa nyid) is relatively well estab- lished in English-language texts on Buddhism, it is usually presented only as the emptiness of lacking independent existence or, more literally, the emptiness of an own nature (svabhāva, rang bzhin). However, the general reader of English literature on Buddhism may not be aware that such an understanding of emptiness reflects a particular interpretation of it, advanced predominantly by the Sakya, Kadam, and Geluk orders, which has exercised a particularly strong influence on the dis- semination of Buddhist studies and philosophy in the West. In Tibetan discourse, this position is referred to as rangtong (rang stong), which means that everything, including the omniscience of a Buddha, is taken to be empty of an own nature. It is this lack of independent, locally determined building blocks of the world that allows in Madhyamaka the Buddhist axiom of dependent origination. In other words, rangtong emptiness is the a priori condition for a universe full of open, dynamic systems. The union of dependent origination and emptiness—the insepa- rability of appearance and emptiness—sets the ground for philosophical models of interrelatedness that are increasingly used in attempts to accommodate astonishing observations being made in the natural sciences, such as wave-particle duality or quantum entanglement. Throughout the long intellectual history of Indian and Tibetan Buddhism, one of the major questions that remains unresolved is whether a systematic pre- sentation of the Buddha’s doctrine requires challenging rangtong as the exclusive mode of emptiness, which has led some to distinguish between two modes of emptiness: (1) Rangtong (rang stong), that is, being empty of an own nature on the one hand, and (2) Zhentong (gzhan stong), that is, being empty of everything other 1 © 2019 State University of New York Press, Albany 2 Klaus-Dieter Mathes and Michael R.
    [Show full text]
  • Madhyamaka in India and Tibet." in Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy.” Edited by J
    CHAPTER 16 Dunne, John D. (2011). "Madhyamaka in India and Tibet." In Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy.” Edited by J. Garfield and W. Edelglass. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 206-221. MADHYAMAKA IN INDIA AND TIBET JOHN DUNNE THE Mahayana Buddhist philosophy of India and Tibet contains several major strands, and while some strands were eventually construed to be flawed, one became dominant in Indian Mahayana. Its hegemony continued in Tibet, where it became the largely unquestioned pinnacle of Buddhist thought. It is the Madhyamika or "Middle Way" philosophy, initially developed by Nagarjuna (fl. third century). In the context of Mahayana Buddhism, sweeping claims rarely survive a careful review of the historical evidence, but in saying that the Madhyamika eventually became the pinnacle of Indo-Tibetan Mahayana thought, one is unlikely to run afoul of historical contradictions. The superiority of the Madhyamika is nevertheless not a simple matter, for the term applies to a wide range of stances. In Tibet especially, the great variety of systems called "Madhyamika" (Tib. dbu ma) might lead one to conclude that the term simply became an obligatory epithet for a tradition's most cherished philosophy, what­ ever it might be. This conclusion, however, would belie the commonalities that Madhyamika thinkers share-commonalities that become evident when they trace themselves back to Nagarjuna, the revered originator of Madhyamika thought. This essay will thus focus on Nagarjuna's initial articulation of Madhyamika, and it will then examine
    [Show full text]
  • Kamalasila's Theory of the Yogacara
    Kamalasila's Theory of the Yogacara Jitsudo Nagasawa Santaraksita (710-792-) united the Madhyamaka doctrine and the Yogacara in his Madhyamakalamkara-karika & vrtti, 91.92. Kamalasila (730 -794-) explained Santaraksita's Yogacara-theory and commented on the three gathas of the Lankavatara quoted in the Vrtti in his Panjika. If we collate these commentaries with the explanations of the same three gathas in his Bhavanakrama, we can understand Kamalasila's theology more clearly. Then, what a situation holds Kamalasila, being heir to Santaraksita, in Indian Buddhism of the 8th century? ABBREVIATIONS: BhK Kamalasila, "Bhavanakrama", Minor Buddhist Texts, II. ed. G. Tucci, Roma, 1958. Lank The Lankavatara Sutra, ed. B. Nanjio, 1923. MAK Santaraksita, Madhyamakalamkara-karika, The Tibetan Tripitaka, Peking Edition Reprinted (=PER) Tokyo-Kyoto, Vol. 101, No. 5284. MAV Santaraksita, Madhyamakalamkara-vrtti, PER, Vol. 101, No. 5285. MAP Kamalasila, Madhyamakalamkara-panjika, PER, Vol. 101, No. 5286. MVT Sthiramati, Madhyantavibhaga-tika, ed. S. Yamaguchi, 1934. SDV Jnanagarbha, Satyadvayavibhaga-vrtti, Tohoku., No. 3882. SN Samdhinirmocana-sutra I. from MAV, 91 Cittamatra as the law of cause-effect (mutual im- manent attribute of cause-effect) in the world. Although the law of cause- eff ect as the origination of the world is mere citta-caitta substantially, but there are two theories: (1) one attaching weight to caitta, and (2) one giving priority to citta (called "the two Madhyamaka doctrines" in MAP). (1) is one who contend "that which is preached cittamatra is for the sake of setting apart a kartr and a bhoktr" in, the sastra (MAP appoints Mad- (1) hyamakahrdaya of Acarya Bhavya).
    [Show full text]
  • Madhyamaka and Yogācāra — Allies Or Rivals?, Edited by Jay L
    BSRV 33.1-2 (2016) 303–307 Buddhist Studies Review ISSN (print) 0256-2897 doi: 10.1558/bsrv.31650 Buddhist Studies Review ISSN (online) 1747-9681 BOOK REVIEWS Madhyamaka and Yogācāra — Allies or Rivals?, edited by Jay L. Garfield and Jan Westerhoff. Oxford University Press, 2015. 300pp. Pb. £23.49. ISBN-13: 9780190231293. Reviewed by Warren Lee Todd, University of South Wales, warren.todd@south- wales.ac.uk Keywords Buddhism, philosophy, ontology, phenomenology, mind One of the optional essay questions on the M.A. module I happen to teach reads ‘Are the philosophies of the Madhyamaka and Yogācāra schools compatible/complemen- tary or incompatible?’. In one form or another, it is a question that has concerned the minds of many great Buddhist philosophers, as well as having been addressed by outsiders, like Śaṅkara (eighth century) in his Brahma Sūtra Bhāṣya (II.ii.32), and more recently by modern scholars such as Paul Williams, Ian Harris, Peter Harvey, Janice Willis and Gadjin Nagao. So, apart from the immediate delight felt at seeing the release of this book, the first question that leapt to mind was whether‘Allies or Rivals?’ was equivalent to ‘compatible/complementary or incompatible?’. Unravelling this question seemed a fruitful way forward. Turning first to the book chapters, after the Introduction by Jay L. Garfield and Jan Westerhoff: ch.1 is by Chaisit Suwanvarangkul on, ‘Pratītyasamutpāda and Dharmadhātu in Early Mahāyāna Buddhism’; ch.2 by Mattia Salvini on, ‘Language and Existence in Madhyamaka and Yogācāra: Preliminary Reflections’;
    [Show full text]