Duration and Simultaneity Henri Bergson

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Duration and Simultaneity Henri Bergson BOBBS-MERRILL THE LIBRARY OF LIBERAL ARTS BERGSON Duration and Simultaneity .B413 Duration and Simultaneity WITH REFERENCE TO EINSTEIN'S THEORY Henri Bergson Translated by Leon Jacobson Professor of Art, East Carolina College With an Introduction by Herbert Dingle Professor Emeritus of History and Philosophy of Science University of London The Library of Liberal Arts published by THE BOBBS-MERRILL COMPANY, INC. A Subsidiary of Howard W. Sams & Co., Inc. Publishers • Indianapolis • New York • Kansas City Henri Bergson: 1859-1941 Duree et Simultaneity was originally published in 1922 COPYRIGHT © 1965 ™ BOBBS-MERRILL COMPANY, INC. 1 Unked States of America Librar^rot ? y Congress Catalog Card Number 64-66064 First Printing Translator's Preface It is the moral of Bergson's philosophy that we shall not live as fully as we could, and that philosophy and science will not co-operate as they might, as long as we remain unaware that "it is time which is happening and, more than that, which causes everything to happen." If we do not notice the actuality and efficacy of time, it is not through oversight, but because time is ruled out by the intelligence, whether exercised in our daily problem-solving or, much more precisely, in scientific investigation. For our intellect was made to prepare our action upon things; and action is taken on fixed points. Our intelli- gence, looking for fixity, masks the flow of time by conceiving it as a juxtaposition of "instants" on a line. But, in Bergson's view, despite this normal exteriorization of our feeling of duration into a "spatialized" time, the mind, being more than intellect, is still capable of apprehending uni- versal becoming in a vision in which "what was immobile and frozen in our perception is warmed and set in motion." It is possible to "reascend the slope of nature" and, by a concen- trated effort of attention, by "intuition," to contact directly, deep within, that concrete duration which is "the very stuff of our existence and of all things." Bergson well understood, then, that it is our practical rou- tine that has militated against a renewal, or deepening, of our perception; that "our senses and our consciousness have re- duced real time and real change to dust in order to facilitate our action upon things." Nor, certainly, does he condemn positive science for not being concerned with duration (even though that is its inspiration), since "the function of science is, after all, to compose a world for us in which we can, for the convenience of action, ignore the effects of time." What he deplores, however, is the tendency of science, and philosophy, vi DURATION AND SIMULTANEITY to mistake its conceptualizations of reality for reality itself. It is, indeed, against a biological and psychological "meta- physics" that Bergson's major works are directed, always with the ultimate aim of clearing the path to vision. Duration and Simultaneity is the concluding chapter in this long polemic with scientism. In the work before us, Bergson argues against the demand by "the theoreticians of relativity," made in the name of Ein- stein's theory of special relativity, that we believe in the "slow- ing" of time by motion in each relatively moving system in the universe. Of course, the very notion of slowed times runs counter to the common-sense view of a single, universal time; and it also contradicts Bergson's allied conception of duration, central in his philosophy. It therefore becomes Bergson's pur- pose in Duration and Simultaneity to demonstrate: (1) that it is actually the supposition of multiple, real times, not that of a single, real time, which Einstein's postulate of the reciprocity of motion contradicts; (2) that the considering of Einstein's times as "real" is attributable to an oscillation, in the course of physical investigation, between the standpoints of Einstein's "bilateral" and Lorentz' "unilateral" theory of relativity; and that (3) this oscillation is itself traceable to "our not having first analyzed our representation of the time that flows, our feeling of real duration." Let us first consider this last, and widest, "frame" of Bergson's argument. As in all his works, Bergson points out in Duration and Simultaneity that it is not the experience of duration that we ordinarily have in mind when we speak of time, but its meas- urement. For what we care about in practical life is the meas- urement of the real and not its nature. But we cannot di- rectly measure that reality which is duration, since it is an indivisible flow, and therefore has no measurable parts. To be measured, it must first be spatialized. Now, the first step in this process is taken when we think of the experienced flow of our mner duration as motion in space; and the next, when we agree to consider the path described by this motion as , translator's preface vii. the motion itself. In dividing and measuring the path, we then say we are dividing and measuring the duration of the mo- tion that is tracing it. For us, it is the earth's rotation that is the model motion tracing the path of time. Time then seems to us "like the un- winding of a thread, like the journey of the mobile [the earth] entrusted with measuring it. We shall then say that we have measured the time of this unwinding and of the universal unwinding as well." But, if we can correlate these two un- windings, it is only because we have at our disposal the con- cept of simultaneity; and we owe this concept to our ability to perceive external flows of events either together with the flow of our own duration, or separately from it, or, still better, both separately and together, at one and the same time. If we then refer to two external flows which take up the same duration as being "simultaneous," it is because they abide within the duration of yet a third, our own. But, to be useable, these simultaneities of durations must be converted into simultaneities of instants; and this we do as soon as we have learned to spatialize time. As noted above, we divide the path that has come to symbolize the flow of real time into equal units of space, and into "instants," which are the ex- tremities of these units. But, now, in addition, we point off the whole length of the moving path of a contemporary event with corresponding points of division. Any portion of the duration of its motion is then considered measured when we have counted a number of such correspondences, or simul- taneities. These simultaneities are instantaneities, not partaking of the real time that endures. But they are yet simultaneous with instants pointed off by them along our inner duration, and created in the very act of pointing. Bergson declares, there-: fore, that it is because instant-simultaneities are imbedded in flow-simultaneities, and because the latter are referrable to our own duration, that what we are measuring is time as: well as space; and, conversely, if the time being measured is viii DURATION AND SIMULTANEITY not finally convertible into an experienced duration, it is not time, but space, which we are measuring. Now, it happens that none of the motion-induced slowings of time allegedly uncovered by Einstein's theory of special relativity is convertible into duration. For, from Einstein's standpoint of the reciprocity of motion in space, these times are merely attributed by a real physicist-observer in a con- ventionally stabilized, "referrer" system S, to merely imagined physicist-observers in a conventionally mobilized, "referred-to" system 5'. Not being "pasted" to a time which is either lived or livable, they are purely fictional, in no way comparable to the actually lived time of the physicist in S. But the unreality of multiple times betokens the singleness of real time. For, were the referrer-physicist in S to betake himself to S', he would, by that very fact, be immobilizing it into a referrer system and would then live the same time there which he had lived in the former referrer system S. This mterchangeability of observers and their lived times in two systems in a state of uniform and reciprocal motion is conse- quent upon Einstein's hypothesis of the reciprocity of motion in space. Hence, "far from ruling out the hypothesis of a single, universal duration, Einstein's theory of special rela- tivity calls for it and confers upon it a superior intelligibility." The fact is, according to Bergson, that it is in Lorentz' unilateral," not Einstein's "bilateral" theory of relativity that multiple times can logically be considered real. For, it is there alone that a system of reference is regarded as at abso- lute rest, while other systems are in absolute motion. These conditions, found in Lorentz' theory, do imply the existence ot multiple times, all on the same footing and all "real." Yet, physicists support Einstein's, not Lorentz' theory of relativity; the question arises as to why they should attribute to instein a doctrine properly ascribable to Lorentz. To n confusi ,' °n of Einstein's Lorentz' viewpoints seems«Jr and almost inevitable. It stems from the fact that even when P ysicist begins by granting Einstein's thesis that any two translator's preface ix systems, S and S', are in reciprocal motion, he cannot, as a physicist, investigate this system without immobilizing one of them into a "stationary" system of reference. The result is that "absolute rest expelled by the understanding is reinstated by the imagination." In the mind of the physicist, two representa- tions of relativity then accompany one another, one, "radical and conceptual" (Einstein's), and the other, "attenuated and imagist" (Lorentz'), and "the concept undergoes contamina- tion by the image." In other words, even though the physicist conceives relativity from the standpoint of Einstein, he sees it a little from that of Lorentz.
Recommended publications
  • INTUITION .THE PHILOSOPHY of HENRI BERGSON By
    THE RHYTHM OF PHILOSOPHY: INTUITION ·ANI? PHILOSO~IDC METHOD IN .THE PHILOSOPHY OF HENRI BERGSON By CAROLE TABOR FlSHER Bachelor Of Arts Taylor University Upland, Indiana .. 1983 Submitted ~o the Faculty of the Graduate College of the · Oklahoma State University in partial fulfi11ment of the requirements for . the Degree of . Master of Arts May, 1990 Oklahoma State. Univ. Library THE RHY1HM OF PlllLOSOPHY: INTUITION ' AND PfnLoSOPlllC METHOD IN .THE PHILOSOPHY OF HENRI BERGSON Thesis Approved: vt4;;. e ·~lu .. ·~ests AdVIsor /l4.t--OZ. ·~ ,£__ '', 13~6350' ii · ,. PREFACE The writing of this thesis has bee~ a tiring, enjoyable, :Qustrating and challenging experience. M.,Bergson has introduced me to ·a whole new way of doing . philosophy which has put vitality into the process. I have caught a Bergson bug. His vision of a collaboration of philosophers using his intuitional m~thod to correct, each others' work and patiently compile a body of philosophic know: ledge is inspiring. I hope I have done him justice in my description of that vision. If I have succeeded and that vision catches your imagination I hope you Will make the effort to apply it. Please let me know of your effort, your successes and your failures. With the current challenges to rationalist epistemology, I believe the time has come to give Bergson's method a try. My discovery of Bergson is. the culmination of a development of my thought, one that started long before I began my work at Oklahoma State. However, there are some people there who deserv~. special thanks for awakening me from my ' "''' analytic slumber.
    [Show full text]
  • Duration, Temporality and Self
    Duration, Temporality and Self: Prospects for the Future of Bergsonism by Elena Fell A thesis submitted in partial fulfilment for the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy at the University of Central Lancashire 2007 2 Student Declaration Concurrent registration for two or more academic awards I declare that white registered as a candidate for the research degree, I have not been a registered candidate or enrolled student for another award of the University or other academic or professional institution. Material submitted for another award I declare that no material contained in the thesis has been used in any other submission for an academic award and is solely my own work Signature of Candidate Type of Award Doctor of Philosophy Department Centre for Professional Ethics Abstract In philosophy time is one of the most difficult subjects because, notoriously, it eludes rationalization. However, Bergson succeeds in presenting time effectively as reality that exists in its own right. Time in Bergson is almost accessible, almost palpable in a discourse which overcomes certain difficulties of language and traditional thought. Bergson equates time with duration, a genuine temporal succession of phenomena defined by their position in that succession, and asserts that time is a quality belonging to the nature of all things rather than a relation between supposedly static elements. But Rergson's theory of duration is not organised, nor is it complete - fragments of it are embedded in discussions of various aspects of psychology, evolution, matter, and movement. My first task is therefore to extract the theory of duration from Bergson's major texts in Chapters 2-4.
    [Show full text]
  • Definitions and Standards for Expedited Reporting
    European Medicines Agency June 1995 CPMP/ICH/377/95 ICH Topic E 2 A Clinical Safety Data Management: Definitions and Standards for Expedited Reporting Step 5 NOTE FOR GUIDANCE ON CLINICAL SAFETY DATA MANAGEMENT: DEFINITIONS AND STANDARDS FOR EXPEDITED REPORTING (CPMP/ICH/377/95) APPROVAL BY CPMP November 1994 DATE FOR COMING INTO OPERATION June 1995 7 Westferry Circus, Canary Wharf, London, E14 4HB, UK Tel. (44-20) 74 18 85 75 Fax (44-20) 75 23 70 40 E-mail: [email protected] http://www.emea.eu.int EMEA 2006 Reproduction and/or distribution of this document is authorised for non commercial purposes only provided the EMEA is acknowledged CLINICAL SAFETY DATA MANAGEMENT: DEFINITIONS AND STANDARDS FOR EXPEDITED REPORTING ICH Harmonised Tripartite Guideline 1. INTRODUCTION It is important to harmonise the way to gather and, if necessary, to take action on important clinical safety information arising during clinical development. Thus, agreed definitions and terminology, as well as procedures, will ensure uniform Good Clinical Practice standards in this area. The initiatives already undertaken for marketed medicines through the CIOMS-1 and CIOMS-2 Working Groups on expedited (alert) reports and periodic safety update reporting, respectively, are important precedents and models. However, there are special circumstances involving medicinal products under development, especially in the early stages and before any marketing experience is available. Conversely, it must be recognised that a medicinal product will be under various stages of development and/or marketing in different countries, and safety data from marketing experience will ordinarily be of interest to regulators in countries where the medicinal product is still under investigational-only (Phase 1, 2, or 3) status.
    [Show full text]
  • Staphylococcus Aureus Bloodstream Infection Treatment Guideline
    Staphylococcus aureus Bloodstream Infection Treatment Guideline Purpose: To provide a framework for the evaluation and management patients with Methicillin- Susceptible (MSSA) and Methicillin-Resistant Staphylococcus aureus (MRSA) bloodstream infections (BSI). The recommendations below are guidelines for care and are not meant to replace clinical judgment. The initial page includes a brief version of the guidance followed by a more detailed discussion of the recommendations with supporting evidence. Also included is an algorithm describing management of patients with blood cultures positive for gram-positive cocci. Brief Key Points: 1. Don’t ignore it – Staphylococcus aureus isolated from a blood culture is never a contaminant. All patients with S. aureus in their blood should be treated with appropriate antibiotics and evaluated for a source of infection. 2. Control the source a. Removing infected catheters and prosthetic devices – Retention of infected central venous catheters and prosthetic devices in the setting of S. aureus bacteremia (SAB) has been associated with prolonged bacteremia, treatment failure and death. These should be removed if medically possible. i. Retention of prosthetic material is associated with an increased likelihood of SAB relapse and removal should be considered even if not clearly infected b. Evaluate for metastatic infections (endocarditis, osteomyelitis, abscesses, etc.) – Metastatic infections and endocarditis are quite common in SAB (11-31% patients with SAB have endocarditis). i. All patients should have a thorough history taken and exam performed with any new complaint evaluated for possible metastatic infection. ii. Echocardiograms should be strongly considered for all patients with SAB iii. All patients with a prosthetic valve, pacemaker/ICD present, or persistent bacteremia (follow up blood cultures positive) should undergo a transesophageal echocardiogram 3.
    [Show full text]
  • The Relationship of Drought Frequency and Duration to Time Scales
    Eighth Conference on Applied Climatology, 17-22 January 1993, Anaheim, California if ~ THE RELATIONSHIP OF DROUGHT FREQUENCY AND DURATION TO TIME SCALES Thomas B. McKee, Nolan J. Doesken and John Kleist Department of Atmospheric Science Colorado State University Fort Collins, CO 80523 1.0 INTRODUCTION Five practical issues become important in any analysis of drought. These include: 1) time scale, 2) The definition of drought has continually been probability, 3) precipitation deficit, 4) application of the a stumbling block for drought monitoring and analysis. definition to precipitation and to the five water supply Wilhite and Glantz (1985) completed a thorough review variables, and 5) the relationship of the definition to the of dozens of drought definitions and identified six impacts of drought. Frequency, duration and intensity overall categories: meteorological, climatological, of drought all become functions that depend on the atmospheric, agricultural, hydrologic and water implicitly or explicitly established time scales. Our management. Dracup et al. (1980) also reviewed experience in providing drought information to a definitions. All points of view seem to agree that collection of decision makers in Colorado is that they drought is a condition of insufficient moisture caused have a need for current conditions expressed in terms by a deficit in precipitation over some time period. of probability, water deficit, and water supply as a Difficulties are primarily related to the time period over percent of average using recent climatic history (the which deficits accumulate and to the connection of the last 30 to 100 years) as the basis for comparison. No deficit in precipitation to deficits in usable water single drought definition or analysis method has sources and the impacts that ensue.
    [Show full text]
  • Miracles: Metaphysics, Physics, and Physicalism
    Religious Studies 44, 125–147 f 2008 Cambridge University Press doi:10.1017/S0034412507009262 Printed in the United Kingdom Miracles: metaphysics, physics, and physicalism KIRK MCDERMID Department of Philosophy and Religion, Montclair State University, Montclair, NJ 07403 Abstract: Debates about the metaphysical compatibility between miracles and natural laws often appear to prejudge the issue by either adopting or rejecting a strong physicalist thesis (the idea that the physical is all that exists). The operative component of physicalism is a causal closure principle: that every caused event is a physically caused event. If physicalism and this strong causal closure principle are accepted, then supernatural interventions are ruled out tout court, while rejecting physicalism gives miracles metaphysical carte blanche. This paper argues for a more moderate version of physicalism that respects important physicalist intuitions about causal closure while allowing for miracles’ logical possibility. A recent proposal for a specific mechanism for the production of miracles (Larmer (1996d)) is criticized and rejected. In its place, two separate mechanisms (suitable for deterministic and indeterministic worlds, respectively) are proposed that do conform to a more moderate physicalism, and their potential and limitations are explored. Introduction Many writers assert that miracles are law-violating instances (Swinburne (1970), Odegard (1982), Collier (1996), MacGill (1996)), but respondents claim that this idea is variously incoherent (McKinnon (1967), Flew (1967)), or false (Basinger (1984), Larmer (1996a)). The incoherence charge only applies to a strictly Humean view of laws as merely accounts of what actually happened (McKinnon (1967)), not to more robust views of laws as representing some variety of physical necessity or causal power.
    [Show full text]
  • Safety Reporting Requirements for Inds and BA/BE Studies
    Guidance for Industry and Investigators Safety Reporting Requirements for INDs and BA/BE Studies U.S. Department of Health and Human Services Food and Drug Administration Center for Drug Evaluation and Research (CDER) Center for Biologics Evaluation and Research (CBER) December 2012 Drug Safety Guidance for Industry and Investigators Safety Reporting Requirements for INDs and BA/BE Studies Additional copies are available from: Office of Communications Division of Drug Information, WO51, Room 2201 Center for Drug Evaluation and Research Food and Drug Administration 10903 New Hampshire Ave. Silver Spring, MD 20993-0002 Phone: 301-796-3400; Fax: 301-847-8714 [email protected] http://www.fda.gov/Drugs/GuidanceComplianceRegulatoryInformation/Guidances/default.htm or Office of Communication, Outreach and Development, HFM-40 Center for Biologics Evaluation and Research Food and Drug Administration 1401 Rockville Pike, Suite 200N, Rockville, MD 20852-1448 [email protected]; Phone: 800-835-4709 or 301-827-1800 http://www.fda.gov/BiologicsBloodVaccines/GuidanceComplianceRegulatoryInformation/default.htm U.S. Department of Health and Human Services Food and Drug Administration Center for Drug Evaluation and Research (CDER) Center for Biologics Evaluation and Research (CBER) December 2012 Drug Safety TABLE OF CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION..............................................................................................................................................1 II. BACKGROUND AND BRIEF OVERVIEW OF THE REQUIREMENTS.................................................1
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 6: Duration Modeling
    Duration Modeling 1 CHAPTER 6: DURATION MODELING 1. INTRODUCTION Hazard-based duration models represent a class of analytical methods which are appropriate for modeling data that have as their focus an end-of-duration occurrence, given that the duration has lasted to some specified time (Kiefer 1988; Hensher and Mannering 1994). This concept of conditional probability of termination of duration recognizes the dynamics of duration; i.e., it recognizes that the likelihood of ending the duration depends on the length of elapsed time since start of the duration. Hazard-based models have been used extensively for several decades in biometrics and industrial engineering to examine issues such as life-expectancy after the onset of chronic diseases and the number of hours of failure of motorettes under various temperatures. Because of this initial association with time till failure (either of the human body functioning or of industrial components), hazard models have also been labeled as “failure-time models”. However, the label “duration models” more appropriately reflects the scope of application to any duration phenomenon. Two important features characterize duration data. The first important feature is that the data may be censored in one form or the other. For example, consider survey data collected to examine the time duration to adopt telecommuting from when the option becomes available to an employee (Figure 1). Let data collection begin at calendar time A and end at calendar time C. Consider individual 1 in the figure for whom telecommuting is an available option prior to the start of data collection and who begins telecommuting at calendar time B.
    [Show full text]
  • Indeterminism and Natural Selection by R
    Reprinted from Philosophy of Science published by University of Chicago Press, copyright © 1934 by the Philosophy of Science Assoc. All rights reserved 121 Indeterminism and Natural Selection BY R. A. FISHER ABSTRACT The historical origin and the experimental basis of the concept of physical determinism indicate that this basis was removed with the acceptance of the kinetic theory of matter, while its difficulties are increased by the admission that human nature, in its entirety, is a product of natural causation. An indeterministic view of causation has the advantages (a) of unifying the con- cept of natural law in different spheres of human experience and (b) of a greater generality, which precludes the acceptance of the special case of com- pletely deterministic causation, so long as this is an unproved assumption. It is not inconsistent with the orderliness of the world, or with the fruitful pursuit of natural knowledge. It enriches rather than weakens the concept of of causation. It possesses definite advantages with respect to the one- sidedness of human memory, and to the phenomena of aiming and striving observable in man and other animals. Among biological theories it appears to be most completely in harmony with the theory of natural selection, which in its statistical nature resembles the second law of thermo -dynamics. In an indeterministic world natural causation has a creative element, and science is interested in locating the original causes of effects of special interest, and not merely in pushing a chain of causation backwards ad infinitum. These contrasting tendencies are illustrated by a critique of the mutation theory, and by an attempt more closely to define the sense in which indeterministic causation should be thought of as creative.
    [Show full text]
  • IDSA/ATS Consensus Guidelines on The
    SUPPLEMENT ARTICLE Infectious Diseases Society of America/American Thoracic Society Consensus Guidelines on the Management of Community-Acquired Pneumonia in Adults Lionel A. Mandell,1,a Richard G. Wunderink,2,a Antonio Anzueto,3,4 John G. Bartlett,7 G. Douglas Campbell,8 Nathan C. Dean,9,10 Scott F. Dowell,11 Thomas M. File, Jr.12,13 Daniel M. Musher,5,6 Michael S. Niederman,14,15 Antonio Torres,16 and Cynthia G. Whitney11 1McMaster University Medical School, Hamilton, Ontario, Canada; 2Northwestern University Feinberg School of Medicine, Chicago, Illinois; 3University of Texas Health Science Center and 4South Texas Veterans Health Care System, San Antonio, and 5Michael E. DeBakey Veterans Affairs Medical Center and 6Baylor College of Medicine, Houston, Texas; 7Johns Hopkins University School of Medicine, Baltimore, Maryland; 8Division of Pulmonary, Critical Care, and Sleep Medicine, University of Mississippi School of Medicine, Jackson; 9Division of Pulmonary and Critical Care Medicine, LDS Hospital, and 10University of Utah, Salt Lake City, Utah; 11Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, Atlanta, Georgia; 12Northeastern Ohio Universities College of Medicine, Rootstown, and 13Summa Health System, Akron, Ohio; 14State University of New York at Stony Brook, Stony Brook, and 15Department of Medicine, Winthrop University Hospital, Mineola, New York; and 16Cap de Servei de Pneumologia i Alle`rgia Respirato`ria, Institut Clı´nic del To`rax, Hospital Clı´nic de Barcelona, Facultat de Medicina, Universitat de Barcelona, Institut d’Investigacions Biome`diques August Pi i Sunyer, CIBER CB06/06/0028, Barcelona, Spain. EXECUTIVE SUMMARY priate starting point for consultation by specialists. Substantial overlap exists among the patients whom Improving the care of adult patients with community- these guidelines address and those discussed in the re- acquired pneumonia (CAP) has been the focus of many cently published guidelines for health care–associated different organizations, and several have developed pneumonia (HCAP).
    [Show full text]
  • The Causal Effect of Unemployment Duration On
    The Causal Effect of Unemployment Duration on Wages: Evidence from Unemployment Insurance Extensions∗ Johannes F. Schmiedery Till von Wachterz Stefan Benderx Boston University University of California, Los Angeles, Institute for Employment NBER, and IZA NBER, CEPR, and IZA Research (IAB) November 2014 Abstract This paper estimates the causal effect of long-term unemployment on wages. Job search theory implies that if Unemployment Insurance (UI) extensions do not affect wages condi- tional on the month of unemployment exit, then reservation wages do not bind on average. Then, UI extensions affect mean wages only through unemployment durations and are valid instrumental variables (IV). Using a regression discontinuity design, we find that UI extensions in Germany reduced job searchers’ reemployment wages on average, but did not affect wages conditional on unemployment duration. Resulting IV estimates imply substantial negative effects of unemployment duration on wages of 0.8% per month. ∗We would like to thank David Card, Kyle Herkenhoff, Larry Katz, Pat Kline, Kevin Lang, Rafael Lalive, Claudia Olivetti, Daniele Paserman, Luigi Pistaferri, Robert Shimer, Fabien Postel-Vinay, Albert Yung-Hsu Liu, as well as seminar participants at Boston University, the University of Chicago, Stanford, the ETH Zurich, Princeton University, Northwestern University, Northeastern University, Ohio State University, University of California Los Angeles, University of California Riverside, the Atlanta FRB, the Minnesota FRB, the NY FRB, the American Economic Association Meetings, the Society of Labor Economics, and the NBER Labor Studies meeting for helpful comments on this project. Johannes Schmieder gratefully acknowledges funding from the 2011 Scholars Program of the Department of Labor. All errors are our own.
    [Show full text]
  • Causality Assessment
    From Signal Identification to Decision Making 1 Adverse Reaction Signal • Reported information on a possible causal relationship between an adverse event and a drug, the relationship being unknown or incompletely documented previously. • Usually more than one report is required to generate a signal, depending on the seriousness of the event and the quality of the information. WHO definition 2 Factors favouring signal detection (1) • The clinical event – a very low natural frequency – characteristic or unusual signs and symptoms – occurring in groups of similar patients – known to be frequently drug-induced • Drug exposure – high frequency 3 Factors favouring signal detection (2) • Adverse Reaction – high frequency – suggestive time relationship – suggestive dose relationship – plausible pharmacological and pathological mechanism 4 Speed of signal detection • depends on: – number of users of the drug – frequency of adverse reaction – reporting rate – quality of documentation 5 Qualitative V Quantitative signals • Qualitative – small number of cases – suggestive time relationship – plausible mechanism • Quantitative – relative risk calculations – more patients - better precision – comparisons within drug or between drugs 6 Criteria for Signal Assessment • Quantitative – strength of association • number of case reports • statistical disproportionality 7 Measures of disproportionality • Information Component – Bayesian statistics •Odds Ratio • Proportional ADR Reporting Ratio • Yule’s Q • Poisson • Chi square 8 Disproportionality of reporting
    [Show full text]