Ebook Download Principia Ethica Ebook Free Download

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Ebook Download Principia Ethica Ebook Free Download PRINCIPIA ETHICA PDF, EPUB, EBOOK G E Moore | 232 pages | 01 Sep 2004 | Dover Publications Inc. | 9780486437521 | English | New York, United States Principia Ethica PDF Book Freely admitting that much work remains, Moore himself known for his high ethical character, incidentally struggles to define exactly what we might consider good, and on what basis. Namespaces Article Talk. Writers, who maintain such a doctrine, are at present very numerous and very popular; and I propose to take as my example the writer, who is perhaps the best known of them all—Mr Herbert Spencer. Moore's analysis, but the main argument that most ethical theories have committed the naturalistic fallacy was very well elaborated. If we consider whether any object is of such a nature that it may be said to exist now, to have existed, or to be about to exist, then we may know that that object is a natural object, and that nothing, of which this is not true, is a natural object. And it is a fact, that Ethics aims at discovering what are those other properties belonging to all things which are good. The distinction between more and less metaphysical forms of non-naturalism is not one he ever clearly addressed. Moore, my understanding of the subjects dealt with deepens tremendously. Average rating 3. And that an action will have such and such consequences involves a number of causal judgments. It does not matter what we call it, provided we recognise it when we meet with it. To some this conclusion will mean that Moore and his contemporaries ignored important conceptual distinctions; to others it will mean they avoided tedious conceptual debates. And can any one feel inclined to maintain, that that which I already have, while I am still desiring something else, is always and alone the good? Suppose the part removed, and what remains is not what was asserted to have intrinsic value; but if we suppose a means removed, what remains is just what was asserted to have intrinsic value. But Evolution, as Mr Spencer understands it and as it is commonly understood, denotes something very different. But we have no reason to think that this is the case in any instance whatever. How exactly do we become aware of it? But if it is that to which the adjective will apply, it must be something different from that adjective itself; and the whole of that something different, whatever it is, will be our definition of the good. Impersonal Consequentialism Moore's normative view again comprised two main theses. A great book of philosophy to listen to because he is extremely meticulous and clear as he progresses through his arguments, which is appreciated. Principia Ethica also had a powerful influence on modernism through the anti-empiricism of T. But Moore never saw any intrinsic value in achievement, for example in business or politics, or indeed in any active changing of the world. And that it is so, we have very strong evidence in the fact that, of all hedonistic writers, Prof. When Sidgwick noticed Bentham or Spencer equating goodness with a natural property such as pleasure, he thought it a minor slip that ought in charity to be ignored; Moore thought it a horrible error that vitiated the philosopher's entire system. Bertrand Russell has nothing but high praise for G. Even Moore's style of defending moral claims, which so outraged philosophers of the s and s, is in effect the standard style of contemporary normative theorizing, though it tends to take a more complex and circumspect form. I only wish it to be understood that that is not what I mean when I say there is no possible definition of good, and that I shall not mean this if I use the word again. It is certain that a whole formed of a good thing and an indifferent thing may have immensely greater value than that good thing itself possesses. Privacy Overview. Either it is assumed that nothing has intrinsic value which is not possible, or else it is assumed that what is necessary must have intrinsic value. My theory is that it enters in, in this way. In particular, it made much more of the alleged errors of metaethical naturalism than Sidgwick or Rashdall had, saying they vitiated most previous moral philosophy. So analytically minded philosophers decided to leave the pursuit of natural knowledge to the emerging sciences of the day, and occupy themselves with analysing these scientific findings, looking for a foundation of science ultimately mathematics in logic, and interpreting and integrating these scientific discoveries into a consistent and coherent worldview. But that is not what is meant by this phrase; nature is again used to mean a mere part of nature; only this time the part meant is not so much the normal as an arbitrary minimum of what is necessary for life. Moore was the idol of the Bloomsbury group, and Lytton Strachey declared that Principia Ethica marked the rebirth of the Age. The one exception might be Analytical philosophy of mind, which goes back to Descartes and Leibniz, and has antecedents in Classical Philosophy. Friend Reviews. Ethics, therefore, does not deal at all with facts of this nature, facts that are unique, individual, absolutely particular; facts with which such studies as history, geography, astronomy, are compelled, in part at least, to deal. Skip to content. Principia Ethica made the surprising claim that the relevant rules will be the same given any commonly accepted theory of the good, for example, given either hedonism or its own ideal theory Start your review of Principia Ethica Philosophical Classics. Nor did his explicit talk of properties mark a significant departure from Sidgwick. He insists that we do actually desire other things than pleasure, and yet he says we do really desire nothing else. Non-naturalism and the Open-Question Argument 2. What I am concerned with is knowledge only—that we should think correctly and so far arrive at some truth, however unimportant: I do not say that such knowledge will make us more useful members of society. But in his first book he had defended the contrary view. Principia Ethica Writer This principle had been accepted by Idealists such as Bradley, who gave it a characteristically anti-theoretical formulation. I assume it to be perfectly obvious that the idea of the object of desire is not always and only the idea of a pleasure. There he held, like Sidgwick, that all intrinsic goods involve some state of consciousness —04, , Though he thought this a crucial part of love, he took it to involve mere passive admiration of another's beauty, as it were from the other side of the room. That they differ intrinsically from the properties of the dead arm and that they form part of the body are propositions not analytically related to one another. Feb 22, Greg rated it it was amazing Shelves: philosophy. But yellow and good, we say, are not complex: they are notions of that simple kind, out of which definitions are composed and with which the power of further defining ceases. Need another excuse to treat yourself to a new book this week? For Evolution does not, in this [p. But Moore thought it intuitively compelling that the pain is worse; if that made the theory of value less systematic, so much the worse for system. This means, for example, that our consciousness of the thing and our emotional attitude towards the thing are both included in the intrinsic value of the object. Consider yellow, for example. Error rating book. He has already told us p. Moore came along and decided to do away with all the philosophical disputes. The doctrine that pleasure, among other things , is good as an end, is not Hedonism; and I shall not dispute its truth. Categories : non-fiction books Analytic philosophy literature English-language books English non-fiction books Ethics books. Just by doubting we can find the self-evident truths; once we have found these principles, we can apply logic i. Surely this is sufficient evidence that he does not see how essential that step is. The other was the autonomy-of-ethics thesis that moral judgements are sui generis , neither reducible to nor derivable from non-moral, that is, scientific or metaphysical judgements. Sep 28, Ruthie rated it it was ok Shelves: philosophy. Moore lays bare the flaws in all ethical system developed up to and should be credited for this. Principia Ethica. Details if other :. Any additional value in the whole x-plus-y must therefore be attributed to it as an entity distinct from its parts, and with the relations between those parts internal to it. But some may think that no such shifts are needed: they may say of Mill, what Callicles says of Polus in the Gorgias [11] , that he has made this fatal admission through a most unworthy fear of appearing paradoxical; that they, on the other hand, will have the courage of their convictions, and will not be ashamed to go to any lengths of paradox, in defence of what they hold to be the truth. There is no contradiction in supposing them to retain such intrinsic differences and yet not to form part of the body. Principia Ethica Reviews I honestly don't see the meaning in their arguments. The most we can be entitled to say of those vibrations is that they are what corresponds in space to the yellow which we actually perceive. And if anybody tried to define pleasure for us as being any other natural object; if anybody were to say, for instance, that pleasure means the sensation of red, and were to proceed to deduce from that that pleasure is a colour, we should be entitled to laugh at him and to distrust his future statements about pleasure.
Recommended publications
  • Review of Hasna Begum, Moore's Ethics; Tom Regan, Bloomsbury's Prophet; Moore, the Early Essays, E
    80 Russell summer 1989 Reviews 81 Alan and Veronica Palmer. Who's Who in Bloomsbury. Brighton: Harvester Press; New York: St. Martin's Press, 1987. Pp. xi, 215. US$29.95. 1 G.E. MOORE DIED, a grand old man, in 1958. At the time of his death he was respected as an exponent of common-sense philosophy and a precursor of ordinary-language philosophy, which was then fashionable. To admit, as Moore admitted (in Schilpp, p. 14), that philosophical problems were not suggested to him by the world, but only by what philosophers had said about the world, wa~ taken to indicate, not a certain narrowness of vision, but a deep wisdom­ the sign of a man who knows which part of the apple's got the worm. In these respects Moore seemed in the 1950'S a much more modern figure than Russell, whose view that philosophy should aim at a reform of the fabric of knowledge was dismissed as nineteenth-century megalomania. With the subsequent evap­ oration of ordinary-language philosophy, Moore's reputation has suffered a decline. It is only recently that he has come to be seen in historical perspective, and what now seems of most importance is his early work. What he wrote after about 1903, when Principia E thica and "The Refutation ofIdealism" appeared, seems, with one or two exceptions, ofmuch less interest. Like almost everyone else, Russell thought Moore's Ethics (1912) "very poor",2 but he also thought that even Principia Ethica was "nothing like so good" as "The Nature ofJudg­ ment", in which Moore firmly parted company with neo-Hegelianism and Moore and Bloomsbury began the development of analytic philosophy.3 There is something to be said for Russell's judgment (much of it revealed, however unwillingly, by Begum's by Nicholas Griffin book).
    [Show full text]
  • Feeling Moral Obligation and Living in an Organic Unity: Virginia Woolf’S Response to G
    Feeling Moral Obligation and Living in an Organic Unity: Virginia Woolf’s response to G. E. Moore Rohini Shukla Introduction – Climbing the Cathedral Spire There is an abundance of scholarly work on the topic of Virginia Woolf’s writings and philosophy. One popular trend uses the theoretical framework of continental philosophers such as Heidegger, Derrida, Nietzsche, and Montaigne, amongst others, and argues that Woolf’s works are literary embodiments or instantiations of their concepts, methods, or even entire philosophies.1 Another trend repudiates any connection between Woolf’s literature and philosophy altogether, denying that the latter can provide any insight into the former.2 This denial seems reasonable, for Woolf wrote in times when traditionally accepted answers to amaranthine philosophical questions were vehemently doubted. Lackey calls this phase in the intellectual history of European thought ‘modernist anti-philosophicalism.’3 Modernist anti-philosophicalism can more appropriately be called modernist anti-metaphysicalism, for it was primarily a critique of the metaphysical dogma propounded throughout the history of Western philosophy – from Plato up to Enlightenment philosophers such as Descartes and Kant.4 Much of significance is the fact that British philosopher G.E. Moore, a contemporary of Woolf, was a pioneering proponent of anti-metaphysicalism,5 and interestingly, we know that Woolf engaged with his magnum opus – Principia Ethica (1903).6 Despite the proliferation of secondary literature on Woolf’s writings and philosophy, an exposition of the precise influence of Moore’s thought on Woolf’s writing is curiously lacking. Indeed, reducing her writings to literary articulations of what other philosophers have said, as has been the popular trend, denies her any philosophical merit in her own right.
    [Show full text]
  • Moore in the Middle Author(S): by Thomas Hurka Source: Ethics, Vol
    Moore in the Middle Author(s): by Thomas Hurka Source: Ethics, Vol. 113, No. 3, Centenary Symposium on G. E. Moore's <italic> Principia Ethica</italic> (April 2003), pp. 599-628 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/345624 . Accessed: 04/03/2014 18:04 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 142.150.190.39 on Tue, 4 Mar 2014 18:04:53 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Moore in the Middle Thomas Hurka The rhetoric of G. E. Moore’s Principia Ethica, as of not a few philosophy books, is that of the clean break. Moore claims that the vast majority of previous writing on ethics has been misguided and that an entirely new start is needed. In its time, however, the book’s claims to novelty were widely disputed. Reviews in Mind, Ethics, and Journal of Philosophy applauded the clarity of Moore’s criticisms of Mill, Spencer, and others but said they were “not altogether original,” had for the most part “al- ready been brought out by other critics,” and were even “the standard criticisms.”1 To the Mind reviewer, “The book indicates throughout how strongly the author has been affected by Sidgwick’s views.”2 Hastings Rashdall rejected as historically inaccurate Moore’s claim that only Sidg- wick before him had recognized that “good” is indefinable: “To say nothing of writers who (like Mr.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to G.E. Moore's Principia Ethica G
    University of Richmond UR Scholarship Repository Religious Studies Faculty Publications Religious Studies 2005 Introduction to G.E. Moore's Principia Ethica G. Scott aD vis University of Richmond, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.richmond.edu/religiousstudies-faculty- publications Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Davis, G. Scott. "Introduction." In Principia Ethica, by George E. Moore, ix-xvi. Barnes & Noble Library of Essential Reading. New York: Barnes & Noble, 2005. This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the Religious Studies at UR Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Religious Studies Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UR Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INTRODUCTION WHEN Principia Ethica appeared, in 1903, it became something of a sacred text for the Cambridge-educated elite-Lytton Strachey, Leonard Woolf, john Maynard Keynes-who, along with Virginia Woolf, would form the core of the Bloomsbury Group. In a letter of October 1 1, 1903, Strachey confesses to Moore that he is "car­ ried away" by Principia, which inaugurates, for him, "the beginning of the Age of Reason." Moore's critique of convention, his caustic dismissal of his philosophical predecessors, and the relentless rigor of his method promised a revolution in morality commensu­ rate with the modernist transformation of art and literature. Principia Ethica shifted the study of ethics away from normative questions to issues of "metaethics," the study of ethical concepts. Realism vs. relativism, the relation of goodness to rightness, and the logic of moral argument would come to dominate philosophi­ cal ethics for the next century, even when Moore's philosophical heirs differed from him in their conclusions.
    [Show full text]
  • Meta-Ethics: an Introduction
    Meta-ethics: An Introduction Leslie Allan Published online: 6 November 2015 Copyright © 2015 Leslie Allan Meta-ethics is the area of philosophy in which thinkers explore the language and nature of moral discourse and its relations to other non-moral areas of life. In this introduction to the discipline written explicitly for novices, Leslie Allan outlines the key questions and areas of analysis in contemporary meta-ethics. In clear, tabular format, he summarizes the core concepts integral to each of the major meta-ethical positions and the strengths of each view. To prompt further thinking and reading, Allan explains briefly the major objections to each theory and lists each view’s best known advocates. To cite this essay: Allan, Leslie 2015. Meta-ethics: An Introduction, URL = <http://www.RationalRealm.com/philosophy/ethics/meta-ethics-introduction.html> To link to this essay: www.RationalRealm.com/philosophy/ethics/meta-ethics-introduction.html Follow this and additional essays at: www.RationalRealm.com This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sublicensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms and conditions of access and use can be found at www.RationalRealm.com/policies/tos.html Leslie Allan Meta-ethics: An Introduction 1. What Is Meta-ethics? Meta-ethics is a major field of enquiry in philosophy. The ‘meta’ in ‘meta-ethics’ signifies ‘above’. Meta-ethics is the attempt to answer questions about ethics. Philosophers working in this area are not so much concerned with what people or acts in particular are ethical.
    [Show full text]
  • Notions of Friendship in the Bloomsbury Group: G. E. Moore, D
    NOTIONS OF FRIENDSHIP IN THE BLOOMSBURY GROUP: G. E. MOORE, D. H. LAWRENCE, E. M. FORSTER, AND VIRGINIA WOOLF by Llana Carroll B.A. in Literature, Purchase College, SUNY, 2003 M.A. in English, University of Pittsburgh, 2008 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Ph.D. in English: Cultural and Critical Studies University of Pittsburgh 2009 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by Llana Carroll It was defended on September 25, 2009 and approved by Troy Boone, Ph.D., Associate Professor Colin MacCabe, Ph.D., Distinguished University Professor Kieran Setiya, Ph.D., Associate Professor Phillip E. Smith, Ph.D., Associate Professor Dissertation Director: Colin MacCabe, Ph.D., Distinguished University Professor ii Copyright © by Llana Carroll 2009 iii NOTIONS OF FRIENDSHIP IN THE BLOOMSBURY GROUP: G. E. MOORE, D. H. LAWRENCE, E. M. FORSTER, AND VIRGINIA WOOLF Llana Carroll, Ph.D. University of Pittsburgh, 2009 In this study I argue that the Bloomsbury Group’s notion of friendship was influenced by G. E. Moore’s philosophy of friendship, developed in “Achilles or Patroclus?” (1894) and Principia Ethica (1903), and the Great War. I posit that these dual influences were central to Lawrence, Forster, and Woolf’s representations of frustrated and melancholic friendship in their post-war novels: Women in Love (1920), A Passage to India (1924), and The Waves (1931). Lawrence rejected Moore’s notion of friendship, suggesting that after the Great War desexualized friendship was impossible. On the other hand, Forster and Woolf continued to believe in Moore’s concept that friendship and the “pleasure of human intercourse” are among “the most valuable things, which we can know or imagine” (Principia Ethica 188–89).
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond Fitness to Survive- John Mcmurtry
    PHILOSOPHY AND WORLD PROBLEMS- Vol . I-Natural Good And Evil: Beyond Fitness To Survive- John McMurtry NATURAL GOOD AND EVIL: BEYOND FITNESS TO SURVIVE John McMurtry Department of Philosophy, University of Guelph, Guelph NIG 2W1, Canada Keywords: analytic philosophy, axiology, beauty, competition, consequentialism, deontology, duties, ethics, evil, evolution, fitness to survive, global market, good and evil, indefinability, intuitionism, life support systems, life-value, mechanism, natural beauty, naturalistic fallacy, normal/abnormal, open question argument, quality and quantity, rules, ruling value system Contents 4.1. Analytic Philosophy and the Naturalistic Fallacy 4.2. Fitness to Survive as a General Value Theory 4.3. An Implicit Ground of Justification for Evil 4.4. The Meta-Alibi: Denying Value-System Choice Locks It In 4.5. Rules beyond Instincts and Desires: The Moral Difference of the Species 4.6. The Meta-Question of Quantity and Quality 4.7. Ruling Value Equations as the Inner Logic of the Ultimate Global Problem 4.8. The Presupposed Logic of World Reduction 4.9. Beyond Naturalistic Fallacy: the Moral System Problem and its Resolution 4.10. G.E. Moore’s Bridging Concept of ‘the Good’ 4.11. How Contemporary Value Understanding Is Alienated From Natural Beauty 4.12. Finding the Underlying Criteria of Natural Beauty 4.13. Regaining Our Wider Value Body of Nature across Time 4.14. Finding the Ground of Duty beneath Moore and Kant 4.15. The Nature and Ground of Life-Value Duty 4.16. Physics, Economics and Ethics: The Life-Blind Logic across Domains 4.17. Good and Evil without Life Referents: Principia Ethica as a Paradigm Case 4.18.
    [Show full text]
  • Virginia Woolf's Ethics
    Virginia Woolf’s Ethics and Victorian Moral Philosophy Christine Reynier Université Montpellier III- EMMA, France ABSTRACT In spite of her claim for modernity, Woolf’s work owes a lot to the Victorian tradition, especially, I will argue, to British moral philosophers. Moral philosophy, from the early Utilitarians to Sidgwick’s Methods of Ethics and Stephen’s Science of Ethics, will be shown to resonate in Woolf’s work. Basing my argument on “On Being Ill”, I will show that Woolf re- enacts in an original way the debates over morals and ethics that took place in Victorian times while responding to Moore’s philosophy as expounded in Principia Ethica and qualifying it, thus paving the way for later 20th-and 21st-century ethical theories. When Ann Banfield argued in The Phantom Table,1 that the debate about modernism should take into account its revolutionary conception of the objects of sensation and turned to Bertrand Russell’s 1914 theory of knowledge to do so, she challenged on the one hand the critics’ near ignorance of the Cambridge Apostles’ influence on Bloomsbury, and on the other, the “assumption of contemporary understanding of modernism—that the only philosophy of relevance to twentieth-century art and literature is continental.” 2 Following her example, daunting as it may be, I will challenge this last assumption and argue that the philosophy of relevance to the understanding of Woolf’s work is not necessarily continental but British. My purpose here will be to investigate the possible role of philosophers in the shaping of Woolf’s ethics, a field which has just begun to be charted.
    [Show full text]
  • Read Book Principia Ethica
    PRINCIPIA ETHICA PDF, EPUB, EBOOK G E Moore | 232 pages | 01 Sep 2004 | Dover Publications Inc. | 9780486437521 | English | New York, United States Principia Ethica PDF Book Continental philosophers, liberated by Kant from the need to ground their intuitions empirically, have taken on the grand mantle of philosophy of old: metaphysics, aesthetics, history. And it will not imply either, that the parts are inconceivable except as parts of that whole, or that, when they form parts of such a whole, they have a value different from that which they would have if they did not. Get A Copy. Would omore like to tell us about a lower price? But we have no reason to think that this is the case in any instance whatever. Aug 27, Michelle is currently reading it. How to cite this entry. It will not have more intrinsic value under these circumstances than under others; it will not necessarily even be a means to the existence of things having more intrinsic value: but it will, like a means, be a necessary condition for the existence of that which has greater intrinsic value, although, unlike a means, it will itself form a part of this more valuable existent. It may be replied to this: Yes, but we shall look about us just as much, before we settle on our definition, and are therefore just as likely to be right. All that the Evolution-Hypothesis tells us is that certain kinds of conduct are more evolved than others; and [p. But it is important to notice that the whole series of effects within a period of considerable length is actually taken account of in our common judgments that an action is good as a means; and that hence this additional complication, which makes ethical generalisations so far more difficult to establish than scientific laws, is one which is involved in actual ethical discussions, and is of practical importance.
    [Show full text]
  • A Hundred Years of Pincipia Ethica
    A HUNDRED YEARS OF PRINCIPIA ETHICA An interview with Thomas Baldwin ethic@: A hundred years ago, Principia Ethica was first published. As one of the best scholars of Moore’s philosophy, could you, please, tell us how you came across this book and what is its importance in twentieth-century ethics. Baldwin: My first Philosophy supervisor (tutor) at Trinity College Cambridge in October 1965 was Simon Blackburn, and one of the very first tasks he gave me was an essay on the ‘naturalistic fallacy’, for which he told me to read chapter 1 of Principia Ethica.Thiswas my first acquaintance with the book, and during the subsequent months I read it all since it still had a special place in the teaching of ethics at Cambridge. In assessing the importance of the book in twentieth century ethical theory it is, I think, important not to exaggerate its initial impact when it was first published in Cambridge in 1903. If one looks to writings in ethics in English during the ten years after its publication, there is not much sign that Principia Ethica was widely read and appreciated. Instead Moore’s reputation during this period largely rested on his paper ‘The Refutation of Idealism’ (Mind 1903) and on his subsequent papers in the philosophy of perception such as ‘The status of sense-data’ (Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 1913-4). Of course Moore’s friends within the Bloomsbury Group (especially Lytton Strachey, Maynard Keynes, Clive Bell and Leonard Woolf) were immediately impressed by Principia Ethica, as was Bertrand Russell; but beyond this circle of friends, the book’s reputation was limited.
    [Show full text]
  • Axiology--Theory of Values Author(S): Samuel L
    International Phenomenological Society Axiology--Theory of Values Author(s): Samuel L. Hart Source: Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 32, No. 1 (Sep., 1971), pp. 29-41 Published by: International Phenomenological Society Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2105883 Accessed: 27-03-2020 09:06 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms International Phenomenological Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy and Phenomenological Research This content downloaded from 94.27.222.80 on Fri, 27 Mar 2020 09:06:39 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms AXIOLOGY - THEORY OF VALUES Axiology, which stems from two Greek words - axios or worth, and logos or reason, theory - is a relatively new discipline. "In the twentieth century the term axiology was apparently first applied by Paul Lapie (Logique de la Volonte, 1902) and E. von Hartmann (Grundriss der Axiology, 1908)." (The Dictionary of Philosophy, edited by Dagobert D. T. Runes, Philosophical Library.) The problems and issues axiology investigates have been with us from the moment man began to reflect upon conditions of his life, the structure of reality, the order of nature and man's place in it.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ethics of Keynes Novelists E
    Journal of Markets & Morality Volume 20, Number 1 (Spring 2017): 23–37 Copyright © 2017 The Ethics Hadley T. Mitchell of Keynes Taylor University Early in Keynes’s student days at Cambridge University, at the beginning of the twentieth century, he was attracted to the Apostles, a group of free-thinking students, including Bertrand Russell and A. N. Whitehead, together with several literary and artistic figures prominent in the British scene who were enamored with the moral philosophy of G. E. Moore. These intellectuals, under Moore’s influence, questioned all moral authority. Moore’s ethical standard required one to consider all the consequences of any moral act, even into the infinite future. However, by the late 1930s, in his “My Ethical Beliefs,” Keynes would distance himself somewhat from that moral standard. Keynes also rejected any system of natural laws governing economics. Hence, order in any economic system needed to be imposed, for example, by wise policymakers. Introduction While John Maynard Keynes grew up in a churchgoing family, by the time he began his university years at Cambridge, he had already stopped attending church with his family. Once he started at Cambridge, he was attracted to the “Apostles,” where he came under the influence of the ethicist G. E. Moore. Moore was then developing a radical system of ethics, later to be published as his Principia Ethica. His preparation for this work was discussed by brilliant young students who later were to have a profound effect on British intellectual life in the arts, literature, and mathematics—students who were willing to discard the Victorian ethics in which they had been raised in favor of Moore’s system that challenged everything.
    [Show full text]