Pascal's Anti- Augustinianism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Pascal's Anti- Augustinianism Pascal’s Anti- Augustinianism Vincent Carraud Université de Caen I analyze the complex relations between Pascal and the three ªgures of Montaigne, Descartes, and St. Augustine, and the relations the ªrst two ªg- ures bear to St. Augustine. For Pascal’s philosophy, one is in effect a resource (Montaigne), another a way of thinking that he makes his own (Descartes), and yet another serves as a model (St. Augustine). I further investigate Pas- cal’s anti-Augustinism, that is, some of the points of resistance in Pascal against the thought of St. Augustine. Central to this investigation is the fa- mous rapprochement between the cogitos of Augustine and Descartes, which requires a consideration of what, for Pascal, it means “to say the same thing.” This analysis leads us to two conclusions: ªrst, Augustine’s The City of God should be placed among the number of works that Pascal did not read; second, there are fundamental philosophical reasons for Pascal to reject certain theses central to that work. Above all, there should no longer be any need to assume a merely abstract conception of an unproblematic Augustin- ianism in Pascal. Montaigne, Descartes and St. Augustine do not have the same status in the composition of Pascal’s thought. Montaigne’s presence is nearly con- stant: he is cited, paraphrased, glossed, discussed, and criticized. The Es- says, especially the Apology of Raymond Sebond, abound throughout Pascal’s texts. The Essays are a frequent resource for Pascal—a resource in the sense that they are the fund, the soil of the Pensées. Next to this fund continu- ously extracted from Montaigne, Descartes is fundamental. Cartesian philosophy1 constitutes the foundation of Pascal’s thought, by which I In memory of Geneviève Rodis-Lewis, author of Augustinisme et cartésianisme, an inovative study that appeared in Paris just over 50 years ago at the end of September 1945. Translated by Nathan D. Smith. 1. In a sense, what follows could also provide a connection between natural philosophy Perspectives on Science 2007, vol. 15, no. 4 ©2007 by The Massachusetts Institute of Technology 450 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc.2007.15.4.450 by guest on 24 September 2021 Perspectives on Science 451 mean: Pascal is a Cartesian—even the ªrst Cartesian. He thinks as a Carte- sian, and it is on the basis of this Cartesian foundation, always reinter- preted, that is, rethought, that a precise and decisive anti-Cartesianism of certain of his theses could arise and develop. Thus, the Pascalian interpre- tation of Descartes is able to create a space for what I have recently called a “conceptual subversion.”2 On the other hand, the presence of St. Augus- tine in the Pensées is neither fund nor foundation. Pascal had not been nourished by the thought of Augustine as essentially as by that of Montaigne or Descartes, neither in the years in which he was principally establishing his scientiªc works, nor even at the time when he wanted to demonstrate the failure of philosophy and clear the way to true religion, nor a fortiori when he discovered an original anthropology and became the thinker of human existence. De Vera Religione undeniably constituted, at least for a time, the model of his apologetical project3 and the renewal of a thoroughly Augustinian opposition between miseria and dignitas4 to which Pascal had wanted to give back its relevance. This would entail that it take an Augustinian focus and frame, but nothing more. Pascal did not seek the same degree of textual resources in Augustine, and he never thought as an Augustinian. The Conversations with Monsieur de Saci should be sufªcient to convince us of that: the voice of St. Augustine is heard in Saci, while Epictetus, Montaigne and—under the pseudonym of Montaigne—the Descartes of the ªrst Meditation, speak through the mouth of Pascal.5 Saci plays the Augustinian while Pascal is the philosopher: and what Saci admired—recall the introduction to the Conversations—in Pascal is that “in all things he agreed with St. Augustine,” he who had “not read the Church fathers.”6 I will come back to the idea of “agreement” later: not with respect to the agreement between Pascal and St. Augustine according to Saci, but that between Descartes and St. Augustine according to Pascal. and the method that it requires, particularly in the experiments on the void: see Carraud 2001 and the comments of Chevalley 2005. 2. The opening section of this study will make frequent use of Carraud 1992. Please ex- cuse these allusions to my former work, which convenience requires, but which also indi- cate that the present study is a continuation of previous work. 3. This text was translated by Arnauld in 1647, with a second edition in 1652. 4. See Courcelle 1974–1975, 3 vols. The second part, vols. 2 and 3, is dedicated to the “vues platoniciennes et chrétiennes sur la misère et la grandeur de l’homme.” For Pascal and the “paradox of man,” see the conclusion, 732–35. 5. See Courcelle 1981, §6c, after the exposition in the column of “sources.” 6. Courcelle 1981, 1:10–11, cf. 51–52 and 43. Cf. Pascal 1994, 91 and 92. The editors of that volume remark: “Afªrmation inexacte, du moins en ce qui concerne saint Augustin: cf. Philippe Sellier, Pascal et saint Augustin, Paris, 1970”! According to Pascal, Saci knows St. Augustine so much better than he, Pascal, “possesses” Montaigne (Courcelle 1981, l: 366–71; Pascal 1994, 117). Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc.2007.15.4.450 by guest on 24 September 2021 452 Pascal’s Anti-Augustinianism Many elements play a role in the complex relations between Pascal and the three ªgures of Montaigne, Descartes, and St. Augustine, and in the relations each of the ªrst two ªgures themselves bears to St. Augustine. I will be content for the moment to point out their respective roles in the always-continuous formation and elaboration of Pascal’s thought. One is in effect a resource (Montaigne), another a way of thinking that one makes one’s own (Descartes), and yet another serves as a model (St. Augustine). One ought to be able to return to relevance a proposed model without at the same time agreeing wholeheartedly with the thought of its author, a fortiori without following it on certain topics which, not to strip them of their importance, do not belong to those contemporary debates tend to privilege, especially the question of grace. This is why we ªnd in Pascal several points of resistance against the thought of St. Augustine. These points of resistance are all the more remarkable insofar as they constitute, at the same time, points of divergence with those contemporaries whom one could also call Augustinian, particularly Arnauld. There is therefore what we might call an anti-Augustinianism internal to the surrounding Augustinianism of the time—limited and brief, yet in that very way so much more acute—an anti-Augustinianism consisting of fault lines so much more clear, of crests so much more distinct in as much as they are separated from the whole of Augustinianism, or, to employ a more pru- dent formulation, from the ensemble of what could qualify as Augustin- ian: in short, a culture, a feeling of belongingness, and even a militant Augustinianism, which we today would call an ideology. In this sense, it is without doubt that Pascal is Augustinian. This Augustinianism in Pascal ought to be explored, and in fact this is exactly what Sellier (1995) does in a thematic rather than conceptual way in his ªne book. (I want to take a moment here to express my debt to this book which has given me the means, albeit a contrario, to better measure the elements of anti- Augustinianism in Pascal’s thought.) And I will add at the same time that these elements are what I would call points of resistance were they in themselves essential, in contrast with elements of doctrine. The relation between Pascal and St. Augustine will not be expressed in terms of sys- tems: this will have nothing in common with the much debated question of Malebranche’s systematic Cartesianism—or of his Augustinianism— in the sense in which Alquié (1974) could be opposed to the “anti- Cartesianism of Malebranche” in someone like Blondel (1916).7 No, none of that for Pascal. There is little sense—in any case little philosophical in- terest, it seems to me—in judging Pascal’s Augustinianism or anti- 7. Without, of course, being reduced to this opposition, as the opening remarks of Alquié (1974, 9) are sufªcient to point out. Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc.2007.15.4.450 by guest on 24 September 2021 Perspectives on Science 453 Augustinianism en bloc.8 In fact, such an endeavor would be ill suited to the nature of his own thought. I will not address therefore the long list of elements of Augustinian doctrine over which Pascal passes in silence, which would no doubt be of little use. Given the lack of space, I will not try to delineate all of the anti- Augustinian theses in Pascal whether epistemological,9 philosophical, or theological.10 This important task remains to be done, because what I call those anti-Augustinian points of resistance in Pascal are numerous. In- stead, I will be content to demonstrate the following: (1) I will show brieºy that The City of God should be placed among the number of works that Pascal did not read. Not only does nothing indicate to us that he had read it, but there are a certain number of convincing textual indications that establish quite clearly that he had neither read the text nor even leafed through many of the books of The City of God he nonetheless cites.11 There is nothing blameworthy in that.
Recommended publications
  • “Politics and Beatitude”, Studies in Christian Ethics
    SCE0010.1177/0953946816684448Studies in Christian EthicsGregory 684448research-article2016 Article Studies in Christian Ethics 2017, Vol. 30(2) 199 –206 Politics and Beatitude © The Author(s) 2017 Reprints and permissions: sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav DOI: 10.1177/0953946816684448 journals.sagepub.com/home/sce Eric Gregory Princeton University, USA Abstract The limits and secularity of political life have been signature themes of modern Augustinianism, often couched in non-theological language of realism and the role of religion in public life. In dialogue with Gilbert Meilaender, this article inverts and theologizes that interest by asking how Augustinian pilgrims might characterize the positive relation of political history to saving history and the ways in which political action in time might teach us something about the nature of salvation that comes to us from beyond history. This relation of continuity and discontinuity eludes dogmatic formulation, but the goal of the present article is to see where a shared Augustinianism and a shared commitment to aspects of the liberal political tradition might find illuminating disagreement. Keywords Meilaender, Augustine, Augustinianism, politics, eschatology, salvation I remember the anxiety in seeing Gilbert Meilaender raise his hand to ask the final ques- tion. It was one of my first conference presentations many years ago at the Society of Christian Ethics. I was a graduate student ruminating on the nature of desire and the relation of the love commands. Like the Israelites exploring Canaan, I felt like a grass- hopper among giants in the land. Meilaender’s frank question about my reconstruction of Augustine characteristically revealed basic issues about Christian tradition and human experience.
    [Show full text]
  • Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations Spring 2010 Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection Jason Skirry University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Skirry, Jason, "Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection" (2010). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 179. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/179 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/179 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection Abstract This dissertation presents a unified interpretation of Malebranche’s philosophical system that is based on his Augustinian theory of the mind’s perfection, which consists in maximizing the mind’s ability to successfully access, comprehend, and follow God’s Order through practices that purify and cognitively enhance the mind’s attention. I argue that the mind’s perfection figures centrally in Malebranche’s philosophy and is the main hub that connects and reconciles the three fundamental principles of his system, namely, his occasionalism, divine illumination, and freedom. To demonstrate this, I first present, in chapter one, Malebranche’s philosophy within the historical and intellectual context of his membership in the French Oratory, arguing that the Oratory’s particular brand of Augustinianism, initiated by Cardinal Bérulle and propagated by Oratorians such as Andre Martin, is at the core of his philosophy and informs his theory of perfection. Next, in chapter two, I explicate Augustine’s own theory of perfection in order to provide an outline, and a basis of comparison, for Malebranche’s own theory of perfection.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustinian Motifs in Mandeville's Theory of Society
    Journal of Markets & Morality Volume 19, Number 2 (Fall 2016): 317–338 Copyright © 2016 Augustinian Motifs Joost W. Hengstmengel in Mandeville’s Faculty of Philosophy Erasmus Institute for Philosophy Theory of Society and Economics In the eighteenth century, the Dutch-born satirist Bernard Mandeville was generally associated with deism and atheism. Nowadays scholarly opinions about his theo- logical outlook are strongly divided. Instead of reassessing what Mandeville really believed, this article focuses on three theological motifs that recur in Mandeville’s Fable of the Bees. These typically Augustinian ideas concerning the fall of man, the two faces of evil, and the distinction between worldly and real happiness deserves more attention than they have hitherto received. Even if E. G. Hundert is right that Mandeville “abandoned the Augustinian premises” of the Calvinists and the Jansenists, he clearly did not forsake all of them. I argue that the three motifs are part of a framework within which Mandeville develops his theory of man and society. Interestingly, Mandeville’s well-known thesis “private vices, public benefits” also seems to build on these Augustinian ideas. Introduction1 The physician and philosopher Bernard Mandeville (1660–1733) was undoubtedly one of the most controversial writers of the eighteenth century. His is one of only a few names that were mentioned in one and the same breath with Machiavelli, Spinoza, and Hobbes; in the early modern period, this certainly was no compli- ment. In the eyes of his contemporaries, Mandeville, like these other radical writers, had dared to undermine sacred religion, true virtue, and good order. The Anglo-Dutch writer proposed a plan for the establishment of public houses of prostitution, authored a book with liberal thoughts on religion and theology, and produced erotic dialogues and poems.
    [Show full text]
  • "Augustinianism": Studies in the Process of Spiritual Transvaluation (Review)
    "Augustinianism": Studies in the Process of Spiritual Transvaluation (review) Andrew Louth The Catholic Historical Review, Volume 96, Number 1, January 2010, p. 85 (Review) Published by The Catholic University of America Press DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/cat.0.0620 For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/369489 [ This content has been declared free to read by the pubisher during the COVID-19 pandemic. ] BOOK REVIEWS _______ General and Miscellaneous “Augustinianism”: Studies in the Process of Spiritual Transvaluation. By J. D. Green. [Studies in Spirituality, Supplement 14.] (Leuven: Peeters. 2007. Distrib. in the U.S. by David Brown Book Co., Oakville, CT. Pp. viii, 113. $70.00 paperback. ISBN 978-9-042-91976-1.) Augustinianism is a term that arouses a range of expectations, from a form of Christian Platonism to Jansenism. This book is not at all about Augustinianism in such a sense. Rather, J. D. Green sees the heart of St. Augustine’s thought as a capacity for transformation, or as he puts it,“trans- valuation.”In the case of Augustine himself, this is the transvaluation of late- antique philosophy by the Gospel that is found in Augustine’s own spiritual journey and in the way he introduces his congregation in Hippo to this jour- ney of transformation—essentially, the reformation of the image of God in their lives as a result of grace. He focuses on the Confessions and the De Trinitate for his exposition of the return of the triune image of God found in the soul and of the transformation achieved as the mind comes to remember, understand,and love God,and then briefly explores how this pattern is found in the Discourses on the Psalms.The following three chapters of the book take as examples of this “Augustinianism” Pope and Saint Gregory the Great, William of St.Thierry,and Walter Hilton—all thinkers and even mystics whose thought was deeply influenced by their reading of Augustine.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problematic of the Augustinian Doctrine of Grace for Contemporary Theology D
    Journal for Christian Theological Research Volume 5 Article 2 2000 Nature Dis-Graced and Grace De-Natured: The Problematic of the Augustinian Doctrine of Grace for Contemporary Theology D. Lyle Dabney Marquette University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.luthersem.edu/jctr Part of the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Dabney, D. Lyle (2000) "Nature Dis-Graced and Grace De-Natured: The rP oblematic of the Augustinian Doctrine of Grace for Contemporary Theology," Journal for Christian Theological Research: Vol. 5 , Article 2. Available at: http://digitalcommons.luthersem.edu/jctr/vol5/iss2000/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Digital Commons @ Luther Seminary. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal for Christian Theological Research by an authorized editor of Digital Commons @ Luther Seminary. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 12/18/2017 Nature Dis-Graced and Grace De-Natured: The Problematic of the Augustinian Doctrie of Grace for Contemporary Theology D. Lyle Dabney, "Nature Dis­Graced and Grace De­Natured: The Problematic of the Augustinian Doctrine of Grace for Contemporary Theology," Journal for Christian Theological Research [http://apu.edu/~CTRF/articles/2000_articles/dabney.html] 5:3 (2000). Nature Dis­Graced and Grace De­Natured: The Problematic of the Augustinian Doctrine of Grace for Contemporary Theology D. Lyle Dabney Marquette University , Milwaukee, Wisconsin 1. "Contemporary theology" Kilian McDonnell writes, "has turned from a theology of the Word to a theology of the world".(1) That statement, it seems to me, neatly sums up the current situation in theology.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustinianism.Pdf
    Augustinianism. This term is used to characterize philosophical, theological and political political ideas which were more or less close to those of S. Augustine of Hippo. The term came into use relatively recently, and can cover a spectrum of views: Augustinianism has never been a homogeneous movement. In particular, it is necessary to distinguish between a broad and a strict sense of the word, In the broad sense, the whole of Latin theology of the medieval and early modern period was strongly influenced by Augustine, as emerges very clearly from the Summae of the twelfth century and above all from Hugh of St Victor and from the authoritative Book of Sentences of Peter Lombard. The early generations of theologians of the mendicant orders – Hugh of St Cher, Alexander of Hales, Bonaventura of Bagnoregio – developed a close bond with Augustine, but they interpreted him in the light of neoplatonic or Aristotelian theories (for example, divine illumination of the intellect, the ‘agent intellect’, matter, rationes seminales [seminal principles]. In the strict sense one must distinguish between the following. #1. Augustinianism from the end of the thirteenth and the beginning of the fourteenth century emerged - especially in the Franciscan School (William de la Mare) and among Augustinian Hermits (“the old Augustinian School according to Giles of Rome) - as a reaction to the widespread reception of Aristotle in the work of Thomas Aquinas, after the condemnations of 1277 at Paris and 1284 at Oxford. Consciously drawing on Augustinian on Augustinian ideas (illumination, the form of created things in the mind of God), Henry of Ghent [a member of the secular clergy] created a coherent new system of speculative theology which would provide a a basis for acute critical analysis and the new order introduced by John Duns Scotus, who substituted for illumination the idea of an intuitive grasp of the essence of things.
    [Show full text]
  • ST7414-1 Augustine and Augustinianism (3) Revised
    Spring 2016, Torch Trinity Graduate University ST7414-1 Augustine and Augustinianism (3) ST7414-1 Augustine and Augustinianism (3) Instructor: Telford Work Office Hours: TBA Contact: [email protected] Classes meet Tuesdays 08:30-11:20 I. Course Description The context, teaching, and influence of Bishop Augustine of Hippo: his historical setting in Roman North Africa at the end of Antiquity, some of his most important writings, and major traditions of Augustinianism in Christian and world history. PhD participants may register this course as 0.5 unit (7000 or 8000 level code) or 1 unit (9000 level code). 7.5 hours of supervision will be given throughout the semester for PhD participants who register as 1 unit. II. Course Objective 1. Students will be introduced to Augustine and Augustinianism in depth. 2. Students will think theologically and philosophically, systematically and contextually, in tracing Augustine’s life, insights, achievements, mistakes, and legacy in Christian thought and society. 3. Students will gain experience reading difficult texts. III. Textbooks - Required Books Peter Brown, Augustine of Hippo: A Biography (read for ‘enjoyment’ and background). Allan D. Fitzgerald, ed., Augustine through the Ages: an Encyclopedia, selections (“quoted”). Augustine, Confessions. Augustine, City of God, selections. Augustine, On Christian Doctrine. Augustine, Enchiridion on Faith, Hope, and Love. - Recommended Books John M. Rist, Augustine: Ancient Thought Baptized. Carol Harrison, Augustine: Christian Truth and Fractured Humanity. IV. Course Requirements & Grading 10% Quality in-class participation. 10% Discussion questions for each session’s reading, when not presenting. 20% total Students will alternate delivering seminar-style in-class presentations on the day’s reading, format to be negotiated.
    [Show full text]
  • Pomplun Curriculum
    ROBERT TRENT POMPLUN University of Notre Dame • Department of Theology 237 Malloy Hall • Notre Dame, IN 46556 (574) 631-3194 • e-mail: [email protected] EDUCATION • Ph.D. Religious Studies, University of Virginia (2002) • M.A. History of Religions, University of Virginia (1996) • B.A. Religious Studies, Rice University (1993) ACADEMIC APPOINTMENTS • Associate Professor, University of Notre Dame (2020–present) • Associate Professor, Loyola University Maryland (2008–2020) • Assistant Professor, Loyola College (2002–2008) • Lecturer, University of Virginia (2000–2001) PUBLISHING BOOK (AUTHOR) • Jesuit on the Roof of the World: Ippolito Desideri’s Mission to Tibet (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010). BOOKS (EDITOR) • The Blackwell Companion to Catholicism, eds. James Buckley, Frederick Bauerschmidt, and R. Trent Pomplun (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 2007). • John Duns Scotus: The Report of the Paris Lecture (Reportatio IV-A), eds. and trans. Oleg V. Bychkov and R. Trent Pomplun (St. Bonaventure, NY: Franciscan Institute Press, 2016). PEER-REVIEWED ARTICLES • “Like No Other in the World: Ippolito Desideri on Tibetan Religion,” Journal of Early Modern History (forthcoming, 2020). • “The Alphabetum Tibetanum of Agostino Antonio Giorgi (1711–1797): Between Augustinianism and the History of Religions,” History of Religions 59 (2020): 193–221. • “Ippolito Desideri’s Tibetan Works and the Problem of ARSI Goa 74, fols. 47r-92v,” Revue d’Études Tibétaines 52 (2019): 176–99. • “Ippolito Desideri and Madhyamaka: On the Interpretation of Giuseppe Toscano,” Buddhist-Christian Studies 38 (2018): 109–18. • “Thomism and the Study of Asian Languages during the Italian Renaissance,” Divus Thomas 120 (2017): 106–31. • “John Duns Scotus in the History of Medieval Philosophy from the Sixteenth Century to Étienne Gilson (†1978),” Bulletin de philosophie médiévale 58 (2016): 355–445.
    [Show full text]
  • God's Bridle: John Calvin's Application of Natural Law
    Campbell University School of Law Scholarly Repository @ Campbell University School of Law Scholarly Works Faculty Scholarship 2006 God's Bridle: John Calvin's Application of Natural Law C. Scott Pryor Campbell University School of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.campbell.edu/fac_sw Recommended Citation C. Scott Pryor, God's Bridle: John Calvin's Application of Natural Law, 22 J. of Law & Religion 225 (2006). Available at: https://scholarship.law.campbell.edu/fac_sw/116 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Scholarly Repository @ Campbell University School of Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Scholarly Works by an authorized administrator of Scholarly Repository @ Campbell University School of Law. GOD'S BRIDLE: JOHN CALVIN'S APPLICATION OF NATURAL LAW C. Scott Pryor* INTRODUCTION Natural law has made a comeback in legal philosophy.' The revival of natural law thinking in the legal academy began about thirty years ago and has managed to gain a seat at the table in current jurisprudential discussions. Defining natural law, Brian Bix declares that it "claims that there are fundamental and evaluative connections between the universe, human nature, and morality."2 These connections need not have a Christian or even a theistic foundation. A belief in moral realism, that is, the propositions that "(1) there is an objective reality, (2) human beings can know something about it, and (3) there are some things that everyone can, and some things that everyone ought to, do in response to what they know,"3 ties together theistic and non- theistic versions of natural law.
    [Show full text]
  • The Heart of Justice: an Augustinian Ethic of Relational Responsibility
    La Salle University La Salle University Digital Commons Th.D. Dissertations Religion, Department of Spring 2016 The eH art of Justice: An Augustinian Ethic of Relational Responsibility Kathleen Bonnette La Salle University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.lasalle.edu/religion_thd Part of the Catholic Studies Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, and the Ethics in Religion Commons Recommended Citation Bonnette, Kathleen, "The eH art of Justice: An Augustinian Ethic of Relational Responsibility" (2016). Th.D. Dissertations. 2. http://digitalcommons.lasalle.edu/religion_thd/2 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Religion, Department of at La Salle University Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Th.D. Dissertations by an authorized administrator of La Salle University Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. La Salle University School of Arts and Sciences Graduate Program in Theology and Ministry Dissertation The Heart of Justice: An Augustinian Ethic of Relational Responsibility By Kathleen Bonnette (B.A., Villanova University; M.A., Indiana University) Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Theology 2016 The Heart of Justice: An Augustinian Ethic of Relational Responsibility By Kathleen Bonnette Approved By Mentor: _______________________________________________ John Hymers, La Salle University First Reader: _______________________________________________ Jordan Copeland, La Salle University Second Reader: _______________________________________________ Frederick Van Fleteren, La Salle University Copyright © 2016 by Kathleen Bonnette All rights reserved For my parents, who taught me the joy of wondering; For my kids, with hope that they always find their joy in the Truth; And for Dan, with whom the joys of life are doubled and the hardships halved.
    [Show full text]
  • CFP for Conference: “Marsilius of Padua Between
    July 6-7 2018 Institute of Philosophy, KU Leuven (University of Leuven), Belgium Marsilius of Padua between History, Philosophy and Politics Keynote speakers: Gianluca Briguglia (Université de Strasbourg) Cary J. Nederman (University of Texas A & M) Annabel Brett (Cambridge University) Roberto Lambertini (Univeristà di Macerata) Marsilius of Padua (c. 1275-c. 1342) was one of the most influential and controversial thinkers of the Middle Ages. He is best known for his seminal text Defensor Pacis (1324) where he attacks the papal theory of plenitude of power and defends an idea of political community based on the strict separation between secular and religious authority. Marsilius was trained as a physician and master of Arts in Padua and Paris and, with the Averroist philosopher John of Jandun, moved to the court of the Holy Roman Emperor, Ludwig of Bavaria, in Munich. He then followed the emperor in his famous expedition to Italy and, in 1327, was excommunicated by Pope John XXII with John of Jandun. The Paduan philosopher is considered a highly complex theorist. In the Defensor Pacis, he presents an original synthesis of several contemporary themes and traditions: Aristotelianism, Augustinianism, the debate on Franciscan property, the communal tradition of the Italian city-states, Conciliarism, medicine, astrology etc. Marsilius’ ideas also had a significant influence in the early modern period during the Renaissance, the Reformation and the Counter-Reformation. His work lies at the crossroads of different fields, ranging from political philosophy to history of political thought, history of philosophy, history of medicine, civil and canon law, and so on. Reflecting on Marsilius’ thought requires, therefore, an inter- disciplinary approach.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 UNIT 4 DUN SCOTUS and WILLIAM of OCKHAM Contents
    UNIT 4 DUN SCOTUS AND WILLIAM OF OCKHAM Contents 4.0. Objectives 4.1. Introduction 4.2. John Duns Scotus 4.3. William of Ockham 4.4. Let Us Sum Up 4.5. Key Words 4.6. Further Readings and References 4.7. Answers to Check Your Progress 4.0. OBJECTIVES In this Unit, placing ourselves in the post-Thomistic period, we focus our attention on two Franciscans: John Duns Scotus and William of Ockham, in their commonness and disagreement with the Dominican Thomas Aquinas. By the end of this Unit you should be able to: • Clarify the positions held by Aquinas and Scotus; • Explain the univocity of being; • Distinguish formal distinction and individuation; • Clarify psychology and ethics of Scotus; and • Explain Universals according to Ockham, and his principle of simplicity 4.1. INTRODUCTION The thirteenth century was the golden age of scholastic speculation. With the beginning of the fourteenth century the signs of a speculative decline or disintegration became obvious. What hastened this decline is the overemphasis on language and logic, together with an increasing scepticism about the power of reason, so confidently proposed by Aquinas. The long-standing marriage of philosophy and religion began to come apart during this time. In the late scholastic period or in the post-Thomistic period two Franciscans beckon our attention: John Duns Scotus and William of Ockham. What is common to both is their disagreement with the Dominican Thomas Aquinas. 4.2. JOHN DUNS SCOTUS 1 LIFE AND WORKS Little is known of the early life of Duns Scotus. He was ordained a priest on March 17, 1291 and on that basis it is inferred that he was born early in 1266.
    [Show full text]