The Concept of Nature in the Light of Immanuel Kant's „Critique of Pure

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Concept of Nature in the Light of Immanuel Kant's „Critique of Pure BTU Chair of General Ecology Concept of Nature in the „Critique of Pure Reason” 1 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE IN THE LIGHT OF IMMANUEL KANT’S „CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON” Scriptum Udo Bröring BTU, Chair General Ecology Table of Contents Summary Introductory Remarks Prerequisites: Various Philosophers and General Approaches Different Attitudes Towards Nature and the Concept of Causality The „Critique of Pure Reason” - Contents and Reception - Transcendental Aesthetics and Analytics - Transcendental Apperception and the Four Tables of Understanding, Concept of Nature Within the Transcendental Idealism Outlook: The Kantian “Critical Business” References and Further Readings Summary It is reason which prescribes its laws to the sensible universe; it is reason which makes the cosmos. (I. Kant, Prolegom. 85) The „Critique of Pure Reason” (CPR) by Immanuel Kant, first published in 1781, is one of the most important philosophical publications, and the „Copernican Revolution in Philoso- phy” was the result. Various fields of philosophical discussion are affected. I start to give a brief overview on different concepts of science (empirism, rationalism) and different attitudes towards nature before 1781. After some terminological clarifications (transcendental, analytic and synthetic a priori truths, intuition, recognition, reason, and apperception), an overview of the general contents and architecture of CPR and a brief summary of the different parts is given. Special emphasis is laid on the transcendental aesthetic and the transcendental analytic within the first part of CPR („transcendental doctrine of elements”) in order to analyze the concept of nature in the light of the CPR. Discussion within the transcendental aesthetic reveals ideality of space and time, that means that space and time are just modes of our perception („conditions of faculty of experience”) and are not within nature itself. With space and time our intellect arranges our sensations and intuitions by applying the categories of pure understanding. This process is discussed in detail, as according to CPR nature is nothing else than the result of such an application of categories using time schemes within the frame of a BTU Chair of General Ecology Concept of Nature in the „Critique of Pure Reason” 2 system of principles: the result is a representation of the world and the condition is the „facility of the synthesis of the manifold by transcendental apperception” („I think”). What we know about nature are just appearances which are manifold and unreservedly arranged by the subject. We perceive appearances only; the thing in itself („Ding an sich selbst”) is unknow- able to us. Kant himself writes: „By nature, in the empirical sensse, we understand the connection of appearances as regards their existence according to necessary rules, that is, according to laws” (B239) and in the chapter „Analogies of Pure Reason” he provides „transcendental laws of nature”, which he also characterizes as „a priori propositions that are intellectual and at the same time synthetic”. By this it is concluded thaat nature is essentially the existence of things, as it is determiined by scientific laws. Introductory Remarks The „Critique of Pure Reason” by Immanuel Kant is by far the most important philosophical book ever written in Europe (Schopeenhauer). Various fields of philossophical discussion are affected. For modern concepts of nature and scientific research it is a fundamental basis. The Kantian approach is completely different from the very beginning, he straightly goes in the opposite direction (figure 1). Philosophers before Kant asked most frequently: What is the limit of our reason (Gr. λόγος, logos, Lat. ratio), and what is the limit of our perception? What is beyyond our reason (metaphysics)? What is beyond the visible world? Figure 1: Transcendentality versus transcendency. Epistemology (gr. ἐπιστήμη, epistéme – lat. scientia: knowledge, „Erkenntnis”) as one field of philosophical reasoning refers to the first two questions, ontology (gr. ὄν – being, sein) refers to third and fourth question. Contrary to this Kant asked: What is before reason, that is in his words, what are the necessary conditions for the faculty of experience? By this, the approach is „transcendental”, his philosophy is referred to as „transcendental ideaalisms”. BTU Chair of General Ecology Concept of Nature in the „Critique of Pure Reason” 3 Revolutions in Europe and Conditions for Philosophical and Scientific Progress The political, social, cultural, scientific situation in Europe in the middle of the 18th century changed dramatically. Epoch-making changes in a small time window („beginning of the modern age as a historical formation”, „Beginn der Neuzeit”) were: the publication of „Kritik der reinen Vernunft” (1781) by Immanuel Kant for the field of philosophy and human mind in general; the French revolution (1789) for the field of socio-political and economic situation; the Napoleonic realignment (since 1800) for the political map of Europe. Preconditions were of course the proceeding secularization and the emancipation of human mind. At the end of the 18th century various political and social developments (which started already at the times of the renaissance) and a synthesis of different patterns of thought lead to the end of the age of enlightment („Aufklärung”). The resulting world view is the basis of our today’s scientific and philosophical thinking. A side-effect of this development is of course the irreversible divergence of the philosophy of nature and science („Naturphilosophie” in the sense of Schelling vs. „Naturwissenschaft”) in the course of the 19th century. – „You, that way; we, this way” (Shakespeare, Lost Labour‘s Lost, V,2 the end). Various patterns of thought are characteristic for the cultural and scientific sphere at the end of the 18th century1: Science is purely secular (Hume, Kant, and Laplace): The condemnation of the curios- itas (Augustinus)2 and other theological presettings abridging scientific reasoning is rejected. There is no return.3 Scientific knowledge is knowledge of laws in nature, process has to be described in mathematical (quantitative) terms (Kant). Scientific knowledge is based on experience (Hume, Kant), basic procedure of scien- tific nature research is observation and experiment: Platonic philosophy (e.g. concept of idea and type) and Aristotelian doctrines (e.g. concepts of teleology and entelechy) were eroded. Scientific research leads to scientific and social progress: Everything is possible, it is just necessary to do more and more research! Prerequisites: Various Philosophers and General Approaches When Immanuel Kant was born on April, 22nd 1724 in Kaliningrad, the Leibniz-Wolffian rationalism dominated the philosophical debate in continental Europe, while in Britain empiricism prevailed Newton and Locke. The CPR was revolutionary and crushing down everything completely like an earthquake (Mendelssohn: „alles zermalmend”), however, there 1 See discussion in Trepl (1987) [Geschichte der Ökologie. Frankfurt]. 2 Aurelius Augustinus (354-430) condemned curiosity (curiositas in the „Confessiones”; German: Neugierde) to be too much related to senses and the visible world. His theology had an extremely deep impact for more than thousand years and lead to rejection of scientific research. 3 „Pure religion is based on belief” (Hume 1740 [A treatise on human nature. London. p. 9], see also discussion in Kühn 2001 [Kant. Cambridge: especially p. 301ff.]). BTU Chair of General Ecology Concept of Nature in the „Critique of Pure Reason” 4 were a number of important precursors, and Kant developed his critique of reason closely in the light of the philosophical discussion of his time. Rationalism is formed based on the philosophy of different thinkers: Plato (427-347 BC), René Descartes ('Renatus Cartesius' 1596-1650), Baruch de Spinoza (1632-1677), G.W. Leibniz (1646-1716) and Christian Wolff (1679-1754). Accordingly, sensory experiences are neither the basis nor limitations of our recognition. True is not what sense, but only what reason tells us about the world (Descartes). Metaphysics is possible and necessary. For the dogmatist thinking is a cognitive function and has absolutely no boundaries and therefore claims universality. – Empirism is based on Aristotle (384-324 BC), Francis Bacon ('Baco de Verulam', 1561-1626), John Locke (1632-1704), Isaac Newton (1643-1727), George Berkeley (1685-1753), and David Hume (1711-1776). Contrary to rationalism, empirism states that experience is the only source and limitation of all our recognition and knowledge. There is nothing in our intellect that is not in our senses before (Locke). Therefore, metaphysics is impossible. Additionally, for the skepticism thought is completely unable to perform an act of definite or at least assured knowledge. Kant follows Plato in respect to his distinction between the sensual and the intellectual world, he smoothes and polishes this approach for his own purpose: the construction of the noume- non and the phaenoumenon. The concept of the Platonic idea is modified as well: For the knowledge non-empirical elements are of basic importance, and the idea is not constitutive for knowledge, but has a research- and experience-regulating function (see Höffe 2004). Howev- er, unlike Plato, Kant significantly upgraded the importance of sensuality in the Critique of Pure Reason. Illusion is never in the phenomenon, because senses basically don’t appear in the mode of possible deception: misapprehension
Recommended publications
  • Kant's Theoretical Conception Of
    KANT’S THEORETICAL CONCEPTION OF GOD Yaron Noam Hoffer Submitted to the faculty of the University Graduate School in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Philosophy, September 2017 Accepted by the Graduate Faculty, Indiana University, in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Doctoral Committee _________________________________________ Allen W. Wood, Ph.D. (Chair) _________________________________________ Sandra L. Shapshay, Ph.D. _________________________________________ Timothy O'Connor, Ph.D. _________________________________________ Michel Chaouli, Ph.D 15 September, 2017 ii Copyright © 2017 Yaron Noam Hoffer iii To Mor, who let me make her ends mine and made my ends hers iv Acknowledgments God has never been an important part of my life, growing up in a secular environment. Ironically, only through Kant, the ‘all-destroyer’ of rational theology and champion of enlightenment, I developed an interest in God. I was drawn to Kant’s philosophy since the beginning of my undergraduate studies, thinking that he got something right in many topics, or at least introduced fruitful ways of dealing with them. Early in my Graduate studies I was struck by Kant’s moral argument justifying belief in God’s existence. While I can’t say I was convinced, it somehow resonated with my cautious but inextricable optimism. My appreciation for this argument led me to have a closer look at Kant’s discussion of rational theology and especially his pre-critical writings. From there it was a short step to rediscover early modern metaphysics in general and embark upon the current project. This journey could not have been completed without the intellectual, emotional, and material support I was very fortunate to receive from my teachers, colleagues, friends, and family.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Critique of Pure Reason
    Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason Philosophy 270 Prof. B. Look I. Some Background Look at Prolegomena: David Hume awoke Kant from his “dogmatic slumber.” Kant tried to see if he could put Hume’s problem in a general form. (p. 581b) What is the general form? In a letter in 1772 Kant raises two questions: (1) How can we be justified in applying a priori categories to appearances in advance of experience, as we must if we are to do science? (2) Can there be any justification at all for applying a priori categories to reality? The Critique is going to answer these questions Critique has two aims: (1) In the Aesthetic and the Analytic to provide a philosophical basis for physical science. Think of the notions of cause, interaction, etc. – these are necessary for science but can’t be justified empirically (2) In the Dialectic “to deny knowledge to make room for faith” (Bxxx) What is at issue? God, freedom, immortality Kant claims that his philosophy is akin to the Copernican Revolution Up to now it has been assumed that all our cognition must conform to the objects (transcendental realism), but this leads to problems concerning the possibilities of knowledge; let us assume that objects conform to our cognition (transcendental idealism) We could say that there are two competing models of knowledge: a theocentric model of knowledge and an anthropocentric model theocentric model: the standard of knowledge is a God’s-eye perspective on the way the world is; the point is to have the mind conform to the objects Æ transcendental realism anthropocentric model: the mind is to determine the way we are to conceive of objects Æ transcendental idealism II.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Argument's for God's Existence Kant's Criticisms O
    Kant’s Arguments for God’s Existence Introduction Background: Three Argument’s for God’s Existence Kant’s criticisms of these three arguments Ground vs. Cause: Kant’s reason for rejecting constructive proofs of God’s existence Kant’s first argument for God’s existence: God’s existence as the foundation of causal explanation Kant’s second argument for God’s existence: Natural orderliness as being grounded in the coherence of God’s mind Kant’s third argument for God’s existence: morality as grounded in the coherence of God’s mind Kant’s arguments for God as transcendental arguments Introduction Kant puts forth three arguments for God’s existence---or, what might be more accurate, three very different versions of a single such argument. Each is original and none has any obvious flaws. This is not to say that they prove what they are meant to prove, only that, if they fail to do so, it is not immediately clear why. Background: Three Argument’s for God’s Existence When philosophers try to prove God’s existence, it is almost always by way of one of the following three arguments: the ontological argument, the cosmological argument, and the teleological argument. Kant rejects each of these arguments, and his own arguments are to be understood in terms of this fact. Right now, I will state and evaluate these arguments, and then I will state and evaluate Kant’s arguments. The ontological argument: God is by definition perfect; failure to exist is an imperfection; therefore, God must exist. Analysis: This argument is a total failure, since all it shows is the truism is that if God existed, then, having as he would every conceivable perfection, he would exist— since, in other words, all it shows is that if God existed, then God would exist.
    [Show full text]
  • Spinoza's Ethics Beth Lord
    EDINBURGH PHILOSOPHICAL GUIDES Spinoza's Ethics Beth Lord Spinoza’s Ethics Edinburgh Philosophical Guides Series Titles in the series include: Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason Douglas Burnham with Harvey Young Derrida’s Of Grammatology Arthur Bradley Heidegger’s Being and Time William Large Plato’s Republic D. J. Sheppard Spinoza’s Ethics Beth Lord Descartes’ Meditations on First Philosophy Kurt Brandhorst Husserl’s The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology Katrin Joost Nietzsche’s Thus Spoke Zarathustra Martin Jesinghausen and Douglas Burnham Spinoza’s Ethics An Edinburgh Philosophical Guide Beth Lord Edinburgh University Press © Beth Lord, 2010 Edinburgh University Press Ltd 22 George Square, Edinburgh www.euppublishing.com Typeset in 11/13pt Monotype Baskerville by Servis Filmsetting Ltd, Stockport, Cheshire, and printed and bound in Great Britain by CPI Antony Rowe, Chippenham and Eastbourne A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN 978 0 7486 3449 1 (hardback) ISBN 978 0 7486 3450 7 (paperback) The right of Beth Lord to be identifi ed as author of this work has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. Contents Series Editor’s Preface vi Acknowledgements vii List of Figures viii Introduction 1 1. A Guide to the Text 15 Part I: Being, Substance, God, Nature 15 Part II: Minds, Bodies, Experience and Knowledge 49 Part III: The Affects 83 Part IV: Virtue, Ethics and Politics 103 Part V: Freedom and Eternity 136 2. Study Aids 159 Glossary 159 Further Reading 167 Types of Question you will Encounter 168 Tips for Writing about Spinoza 169 Bibliography 173 Index 179 Series Editor’s Preface To us, the principle of this series of books is clear and simple: what readers new to philosophical classics need fi rst and foremost is help with reading these key texts.
    [Show full text]
  • Herr Kant, Der Alleszermalmer-Kant the "All-Crushing" Destroyer of Metaphysics: Metaphilosophy of the Critique of Pure Reason
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Honors Theses Department of Philosophy Spring 5-18-2015 Herr Kant, der Alleszermalmer-Kant the "All-Crushing" Destroyer of Metaphysics: Metaphilosophy of the Critique of Pure Reason Jake De Backer Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_hontheses Recommended Citation De Backer, Jake, "Herr Kant, der Alleszermalmer-Kant the "All-Crushing" Destroyer of Metaphysics: Metaphilosophy of the Critique of Pure Reason." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2015. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_hontheses/12 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. HERR KANT, DER ALLESZERMALMER: THE “ALL-CRUSHING” DESTROYER OF METAPHYSICS KANT’S METAPHILOSOPHY IN THE CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON An Honors Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for Graduation with Undergraduate Research Honors Georgia State University 2015 by Jake Christopher de Backer Committee: Dr. Eric E. Wilson, Honors Thesis Director Dr. Sarah Cook, Honors College Associate Dean 27 April 2015 HERR KANT, DER ALLESZERMALMER: THE “ALL-CRUSHING” DESTROYER OF METAPHYSICS KANT’S METAPHILOSOPHY IN THE CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON by JAKE CHRISTOPHER DE BACKER Under the Direction of Dr. Eric E. Wilson ABSTRACT The Critique of Pure Reason inaugurated Kant’s Critical Philosophy. Commentators commonly distinguish between Kant’s Positive Project (PP), that is, his epistemology as laid out in the Transcendental Aesthetic and Transcendental Analytic, from his Negative Project (NP), expressed in terms of the destructive implications his epistemology has on speculative metaphysics and rational theology.
    [Show full text]
  • Reviewing Kant's View of God's Existence and Status in Religion Revista Publicando, 5 No 15
    Reviewing Kant's View of God's Existence and Status in Religion Revista Publicando, 5 No 15. (1). 2018, 199-215. ISSN 1390-9304 Reviewing Kant's View of God's Existence and Status in Religion Babak Shamshiri1, Mohammad Hasan Karimi2, Shahrzad Shahsani3, Shima Naghibi4 1 Shiraz University, [email protected] 2 Shiraz University, [email protected] 3 Shiraz University, [email protected] 4 Shiraz University, [email protected] ABSTRACT Throughout history, the main and most important subject of metaphysics, namely, God and, consequently, religion, has been at the focus of attention of philosophers and thinkers. In the philosophy of Greece and the Middle Ages, philosophical thinking began from God and led to a discussion of nature and man. But this changed in the Enlightenment era, especially in Kant's philosophy. The distinction between Kant's thinking was that he began from mankind and then began to think of God as one of the concepts of human intellect. Indeed, from the eighteenth century onwards, with the critique of pure reason and practical reason in Kant's philosophy, the concept of God, and consequently religion and religiosity, became subject to fundamental change, and this fashioned the modern approach to the concept of God and its functions. The main purpose of this paper is to examine the concept of God and its place in religion based on Kant's reading. Because in the thought of Kant, the origin of the concept of God is not reason (pure reason) and nor is verifiable by pure reason; therefore, in the critique of practical reason, he proposes and proves the concept of God as the guarantor of ethics, and therefore the above-mentioned concepts In Kant's philosophy differ fundamentally from the conventional point of views.
    [Show full text]
  • Descartes Doubted, Berkeley Denied, and Kant Endorsed*
    What Descartes Doubted, Berkeley Denied, and Kant Endorsed* KENNETH L. PEARCE Trinity College Dublin ABSTRACT: According to Kant, there is some doctrine, which he sometimes calls ‘empirical realism,’ such that it was doubted by Descartes, denied by Berkeley, and endorsed by Kant himself. The primary aim of this paper will be to reconstruct Kant’s own narrative of the historical relationship between Descartes, Berkeley, and himself, in order to identify the doctrine Kant calls ‘empirical realism.’ I argue that the empirical realism that Descartes doubted, Berkeley denied, and Kant endorsed is the doctrine that the concept of extended substance has legitimate application. RÉSUMÉ : Selon Kant, il existe une doctrine, qu’il appelle quelquefois le «réalisme empirique», à propos de laquelle Descartes aurait exprimé des doutes, qui aurait été niée par Berkeley, et que Kant lui-même aurait approuvée. L’objectif principal de cet article sera reconstituer le récit fait par Kant de la relation entre Descartes, Berkeley et lui-même, et ce, afin d’identifier la doctrine qualifiée par Kant de «réalisme empirique». Je soutiens que le réalisme empirique en question est la doctrine selon laquelle le concept de substance étendue a une application légitime. Keywords: Immanuel Kant, George Berkeley, René Descartes, empirical realism, iDealism, substance Idealism (I mean material iDealism) is the theory that Declares the existence of objects in space outsiDe us to be either merely Doubtful anD indemonstrable, or else false anD impossible; the former is the problematic iDealism of Descartes, wHo Declares only one empirical assertion (assertio), namely I am, to be inDubitable; the latter is the dogmatic iDealism of Berkeley, wHo Declares space, together with all the things to wHicH it is attacHeD as an inseparable conDition, to be something that is impossible in itself, anD wHo therefore also Declares things in space to be merely imaginary.
    [Show full text]
  • Transcendental Apperception in the Critique of Pure Reason: Influence of Previous Philosophical Writings and Their Inherited Reapplication
    TRANSCENDENTAL APPERCEPTION IN THE CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON: INFLUENCE OF PREVIOUS PHILOSOPHICAL WRITINGS AND THEIR INHERITED REAPPLICATION APERCEPÇÃO TRANSCENDENTAL NA CRÍTICA DA RAZÃO PURA: INFLUÊNCIA DOS ESCRITOS FILOSÓFICOS ANTERIORES E A REAPLICAÇÃO DE SUA HERENÇA Thomas Matiolli Machado* Recebido: 06/2016 Aprovado: 10/2016 Abstract: In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant developed new perspectives on apperception never before contemplated in the history of philosophy. However, not everything that the author of the first Critique wrote was entirely original. Indeed, Kant reapplied much that he had learned from historical philosophy, by which he was deeply influenced, creating innovative new approaches to apperception. This article aims to explain how Kant learned from the philosophers of the past in order to develop the concept of transcendental apperception in the Critique of Pure Reason. Keywords: Critique of Pure Reason, Transcendental apperception, Abidance, Spontaneity. Resumo: Na Crítica da razão pura, Kant desenvolveu novas perspectivas sobre a apercepção nunca contempladas antes na história da filosofia. Mas, nem tudo o que o autor da primeira Crítica escreveu possui raízes originais. Kant reaplicou muito do que aprendeu com o passado histórico-filosófico, pelo qual foi profundamente influenciado, de um modo inovador criando novas abordagens sobre a apercepção. Este artigo tem por objetivo esclarecer como Kant aprendeu com os filósofos do passado para desenvolver o conceito de apercepção transcendental na Crítica da razão pura. Palavras-chave: Crítica da razão pura, Apercepção transcendental, Permanência, Espontaneidade. INTRODUCTION The Critique of Pure Reason1 is considered one of the most important and difficult works of western philosophical literature. Although Kant’s writing style might be laborious, it is usually accepted that the concepts and ideas behind his words are very clear.
    [Show full text]
  • Study Guide for Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason: Preface
    Study Guide for Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason: Preface and Introduction [2nd Edition] How does human cognition begin, according to Kant? What is the distinction between starting “with experience” and starting “from experience” (44)? What besides experience is present in our cognition (43–451)? What does Kant mean by “a priori cognitions” and “empirical cognitions”? How do these relate to experience, in terms of priority and posteriority? What is distinct about “pure” a priori cognitions (45)? What two characteristics does Kant find “by which we can safely distinguish a pure cognition from empirical ones” (46)? Explain how he argues that each is such a characteristic. What is empirical universality, and why is it not sufficient? How do the two characteristics stand in relation to one another (46)? Kant claims that “it is easy to show that in human cognition there actually are . pure a priori judgments” (46). Consider how he shows this: • What is taken as given in the first way, by examples “from the sciences” (46) and “from the most ordinary use of understanding” (47)? • Explain how he establishes “a priori” (47) the existence of these judgments. Is he assuming that our experience is certain? If so, why is he making such an assumption? • What is shown in the fact that certain cognitions “even leave the realm of all possible experiences” (48)? Does Kant’s demonstration assume that this kind of speculation is possible, or merely take as rhetorical evidence the fact that some have tried such speculation? • Are these sufficient proofs? What objections might one make against either of these two arguments? 1 Immanuel Kant.
    [Show full text]
  • The Critiques of Pure & Practical Reason
    1 The Critiques of Pure & Practical Reason Immanuel Kant 1844 Squashed version edited by Glyn Hughes © 2011 THE CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON I - KNOWLEDGE TRANSCENDENTAL: AESTHETIC EXPERIENCE is something of which we are conscious. It is the first result of our comprehension, but it is not the limit of our understanding, since it stimulates our faculty of reason, but does not satisfy its desire for knowledge. While all our knowledge may begin with sensible impressions or experience there is an element in it which does not rise from this source, but transcends it. That knowledge is transcendental which is occupied not so much with mere outward objects as with our manner of knowing those objects, that is to say, with a priori concepts of them. All our knowledge is either a priori or a posteriori. That is a posteriori knowledge which is derived from sensible experience as including sensible impressions or states; while a priori knowledge is that which is not thus gained, but consists of whatever is universal or necessary. A complete Transcendental Philosophy would be a systematic exposition of all that is a priori in human knowledge, or of 'all the principles of pure reason.' But a Critique of Pure Reason cannot include all this. It can do little more than deal with the synthetic element or quality in a priori knowledge, as distinguished from the analytic elements. We perceive objects through our sensibility which furnishes us, as our faculty of receptivity, with those intuitions that become translated into thought by means of the understanding. This is the origin of our conceptions, or ideas.
    [Show full text]
  • Pulses of Emotion: Whitehead's 'Critique of Pure Feeling'
    Pulses of Emotion: Whitehead’s “Critique of Pure Feeling” Steven Shaviro [email protected] According to Alfred North Whitehead, “the basis of experience is emotional” (1933/1967, 176). Whitehead writes that his philosophy “aspires to construct a critique of pure feeling, in the philosophical position in which Kant put his Cri- tique of Pure Reason. This should also supercede the remaining Critiques required in the Kantian philosophy” (1929/1978, 113). In what follows, I would like to work through this “critique of pure feeling,” and show how Whitehead opens the way to an affect-based account of human (and not just human) experience. For Whitehead, the questions of how we feel, and what we feel, are more fundamental than the epistemological and hermeneutical questions that are the focus of most philosophy and criticism (including Kant’s Critiques). This emphasis upon feel- ing leads, in turn, to a new account of affect-laden subjectivity. Most broadly, Whitehead’s affect theory places aesthetics – rather than ontology (Heidegger) or ethics (Levinas) – at the center of philosophical inquiry. Aesthetics is the mark of what Whitehead calls our concern for the world, and for entities in the world (1933/1967, 176).1 1In what follows, I will use the terms “feeling”, “emotion”, and “affect” pretty much inter- changeably. This is in accordance with Whitehead’s own usage. Nonetheless, I remain mindful of Brian Massumi’s (2002) crucial distinction between affect and emotion (27-28 and passim). For Massumi, affect is primary, non-conscious, asubjective or presubjective, asignifying, unquali- fied, and intensive; while emotion is derivative, conscious, qualified, and meaningful, a “content” that can be attributed to an already-constituted subject.
    [Show full text]
  • Schopenhauer, Spinoza, and the Physics of Objective Evil
    Open Philosophy 2018; 1: 59–78 Drew M. Dalton* Towards an Object-Oriented Ethics: Schopenhauer, Spinoza, and the Physics of Objective Evil https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2018-0006 Received May 25, 2018; accepted August 1, 2018 Abstract: Objects are inert, passive, devoid of will, and as such bear no intrinsic value or moral worth. This claim is supported by the argument that to be considered a moral agent one must have a conscious will and be sufficiently free to act in accordance with that will. Since material objects, it is assumed, have no active will nor freedom, they should not be considered moral agents nor bearers of intrinsic ethical vale. Thus, the apparent “moral neutrality” of objects rests upon a kind of subject/object or mind/body dualism. The aim of this paper is to explore two paths by which western thought can escape this dualism, re-valuate the alleged “moral neutrality” of material objects, and initiate a sort of “object oriented ethics,” albeit with surprising results. To do so, this paper explores the work of Arthur Schopenhauer and Baruch Spinoza to interrogate both the claim that material objects have no will and that freedom is the necessary condition for ethical responsibility. This paper concludes by arguing that not only should objects been seen as bearers of their own ethical value, a determinate judgement can be made regarding that value through a basic understanding of the laws of physics. Keywords: object; ethics; evil; freedom; will; Schopenhauer; Spinoza; physics; thermodynamics; entropy 1 On the alleged passivity and ethical neutrality of objects Objects are inert and passive – they are devoid of life and will; or, at least, so we have been told.
    [Show full text]