A Linear Logical Framework

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Linear Logical Framework A Linear Logical Framework Iliano Cervesato and Frank Pfenning∗ Department of Computer Science Carnegie Mellon University Pittsburgh, PA 15213-3891 {iliano|fp}@cs.cmu.edu Abstract tuitionistic framework. Consequently the adequacy of the representation is difficult to prove and the formal We present the linear type theory LLF as the for- meta-theory quickly becomes intractable. mal basis for a conservative extension of the LF logical Linear logic [7] provides a view of context formulas framework. LLF combines the expressive power of de- as resources, which can be exploited to model the no- pendent types with linear logic to permit the natural and tion of state, as described for example in [4, 10, 12, 22]. concise representation of a whole new class of deductive The current proposals put the emphasis on the issue of systems, namely those dealing with state. As an exam- representing imperative constructs and resource-based ple we encode a version of Mini-ML with references in- logics, but appear inadequate for reasoning effectively cluding its type system, its operational semantics, and about these representations. On the other hand, intu- a proof of type preservation. Another example is the itionistic type-theoretic frameworks such as LF make encoding of a sequent calculus for classical linear logic the representation of meta-reasoning easy, but do not and its cut elimination theorem. LLF can also be given have any notion of linearity built in. an operational interpretation as a logic programming As a concrete example, consider the problem of rep- language under which the representations above can be resenting a cut-elimination procedure for linear logic. used for type inference, evaluation and cut-elimination. Given the derivation D foralinearsequent∆−→ Θ, this procedure produces an equivalent cut-free deriva- tion D0. Since it operates linearly on the formulas ap- 1 Introduction pearing in it, D would be adequately represented by atermpDqin a linear λ-calculus; the same holds for D0 A logical framework is a formal system designed to . This problem was encoded in LF by representing provide effective representations of deductive systems sequents as types and derivations as proof terms [18]. pDq and their properties. Proposals based on intuitionistic LF is intuitionistic and therefore the linearity of pDq logic and intuitionistic type theory, such as the logical needed to be checked explicitly as a property of , framework LF [9], have been widely used to study log- complicating the meta-theory to the extent that it be- ical formalisms [19] and programming languages [11]. came infeasible and only the cut-elimination algorithm Unfortunately, many constructs and concepts needed in without the linearity check was implemented. On the common programming practice cannot be represented other hand, encoding the same problem in Miller’s lin- in a satisfactory way in these meta-languages. In par- ear meta-logic Forum [12] would map linear sequent ticular, constructs based on the notion of state as found derivations to linear derivations in the meta-language. in imperative languages often escape an elegant formal- But since Forum lacks proof terms, no internal nota- ization by means of these tools. Similarly, logical sys- tion for those entities is provided and cut-elimination tems that, by definition (e.g. substructural logics) or cannot be implemented in this manner. by presentation (e.g. Dyckhoff’s contraction-free intu- In this paper, we propose a conservative extension itionistic sequent calculus [5]), rely on destructive con- of the logical framework LF that permits representing text reductions require awkward encodings in an in- linear objects and reasoning about them. This formal- ∗ ism, that we call Linear LF,orLLF for short, is a This work was supported by NSF Grant CCR-9303383. The type theory featuring linear function types (−◦ ), ad- second author was supported by the Alexander-von-Humboldt- > Stiftung when this paper was completed, during a visit to the De- ditive pairing (&), unit type ( ), and intuitionistic partment of Mathematics of the Technical University Darmstadt. dependent function types (Π). LLF extends the ob- This extended abstract will appear on the proceedings of the Eleventh Annual IEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science — LICS’96, New Brunswick, NJ, July 27–30 1996. jects of LF with linear functional abstraction, additive The language of objects is augmented accordingly with pairs and unit, the corresponding destructors, and their the respective constructors and destructors. Linear equational theory. In order to keep the system simple types operate on linear assumptions which we repre- we restrict the indices of type families to be linearly sent as distinguished declarations of the form xˆ: A in closed so that a type can depend only on intuitionis- the context; we write x: A for context elementsala ` LF tic assumptions, but not on linear variables. While at and call them intuitionistic assumptions.Thesyntax first this may appear to be a strong restriction, the re- of LLF is given by the following grammar (constructs sulting system is surprisingly expressive, allowing the not present in LF are separated by a double bar || ): faithful implementation of cut elimination for classical Objects: M ::= c | x | λx:A. M | M1 M2 linear logic, translations between linear natural deduc- || h i | h M 1 ,M2i|fst M | snd M tion and sequent calculus, and properties of imperative | λxˆ :A. M | M1 ˆM2 languages such as type preservation. Families: P ::= a | PM LLF also maintains the computational nature of LF | and is amenable to an efficient implementation as a Types: A ::= P Πx:A1.A2 || > | | −◦ logic programming language in the style of Elf [15, 17]. A 1 & A 2 A 1 A 2 The experience gained with linearity in the language Kinds: K ::= type | Πx:A. K Lolli [10, 2] applies directly to our formalism. Contexts: Ψ ::= ·|Ψ,x:A || Ψ ,xˆ:A The principal contributions of this work are: (1) the Signatures: Σ ::= ·|Σ,a:K | Σ,c:A definition of a uniform type theory admitting linear en- Here x, c and a range over object-level variables, object tities in conjunction with dependent types; (2) the use constants and type family constants, respectively. In of this system as a logical framework to represent and addition to the names displayed above, we will often reason about problems that are not handled well by use N and B to range over objects and types respec- previous formalisms, either linear or intuitionistic; (3) tively. Moreover, we denote generic terms, i.e. objects, the description of an operational system which consti- types or kinds, with the letters U and V , possibly sub- tutes the first step towards an implementation of this scripted. As usual, we write A → U for Πx : A. U formalism as a linear constraint logic programming lan- whenever x does not occur in the type or kind U. guage. To our knowledge, this is the first linear type The notions of free and bound variables are adapted theory that goes beyond simple types. Our work was from LF (notice the presence of a new binding con- inspired by ideas in [14]. struct: linear λ-abstraction). As usual, we identify The paper is organized as follows. Section 2 de- terms that differ only in the name of their bound vari- scribes LLF and presents major results in its meta- ables and write [M/x]U for the capture-avoiding sub- theory, such as the decidability of type-checking. Sec- stitution of M for x in the term U. Finally we require tion 3 indicates that efficient proof search in the style variables and constants to be declared at most once in of logic programming can be achieved in LLF . Sec- a context and in a signature, respectively. tion 4 illustrates the expressiveness of LLF on an ex- Below we will often need to access the intuitionistic ample featuring imperative computations. Section 5 part of a context. Therefore, we introduce the function presents cut-elimination for classical linear logic as an- Ψdefinedasfollows: other example. Finally, Section 6 assesses the results · = · and outlines future work. Ψ,x:A = Ψ,x:A Ψ,xˆ:A = Ψ 2 The Linear Logical Framework LLF We overload this notation and use Ψ to express the fact that the linear portion of the denoted context is In order to facilitate the description of LLF in the constrained to be empty (e.g. in the all rules for type available space, we must assume that the reader is fa- families in Figure 1). miliar with both the logical framework LF [9] and var- The meaning of the syntactic entities of LLF can ious presentations of linear logic [7, 8]. We will also be presented in various forms. Figures 1 and 2 show sparingly take advantage of the natural extension of the a version of the type system for LLF that we call Curry-Howard isomorphism to linear logic by viewing pre-canonical and that is particularly well-suited for types as formulas. proving meta-theoretic properties about this formal- LLF extends the logical framework LF with three ism. The system relies on the following seven judg- connectives from linear logic, seen in this context as ments: type constructors, namely multiplicative implication ` Σ ⇑– Sig (Σ is a pre-canonical signature) −◦ > ( ), additive conjunction (&) and additive truth ( ). `Σ Ψ ⇑– Ctx (Ψ is a pre-canonical context) 2 Signatures ` Σ ⇑– Sig ·`Σ A⇑–type ` Σ ⇑– Sig ·`Σ K⇑–Kind s dot s obj s fam `·⇑–Sig ` Σ,c:A⇑–Sig ` Σ,a:K ⇑–Sig Contexts ` Σ ⇑– Sig `Σ Ψ ⇑– Ctx Ψ `Σ A ⇑– type `Σ Ψ ⇑– Ctx Ψ `Σ A ⇑– type c dot c int c lin `Σ ·⇑–Ctx `Σ Ψ,x:A⇑– Ctx `Σ Ψ,xˆ:A⇑– Ctx Kinds `Σ Ψ ⇑– Ctx Ψ,x:A`Σ K ⇑– Kind kc type kc dep Ψ `Σ type ⇑– Kind Ψ `Σ Πx:A.
Recommended publications
  • Category Theory and Lambda Calculus
    Category Theory and Lambda Calculus Mario Román García Trabajo Fin de Grado Doble Grado en Ingeniería Informática y Matemáticas Tutores Pedro A. García-Sánchez Manuel Bullejos Lorenzo Facultad de Ciencias E.T.S. Ingenierías Informática y de Telecomunicación Granada, a 18 de junio de 2018 Contents 1 Lambda calculus 13 1.1 Untyped λ-calculus . 13 1.1.1 Untyped λ-calculus . 14 1.1.2 Free and bound variables, substitution . 14 1.1.3 Alpha equivalence . 16 1.1.4 Beta reduction . 16 1.1.5 Eta reduction . 17 1.1.6 Confluence . 17 1.1.7 The Church-Rosser theorem . 18 1.1.8 Normalization . 20 1.1.9 Standardization and evaluation strategies . 21 1.1.10 SKI combinators . 22 1.1.11 Turing completeness . 24 1.2 Simply typed λ-calculus . 24 1.2.1 Simple types . 25 1.2.2 Typing rules for simply typed λ-calculus . 25 1.2.3 Curry-style types . 26 1.2.4 Unification and type inference . 27 1.2.5 Subject reduction and normalization . 29 1.3 The Curry-Howard correspondence . 31 1.3.1 Extending the simply typed λ-calculus . 31 1.3.2 Natural deduction . 32 1.3.3 Propositions as types . 34 1.4 Other type systems . 35 1.4.1 λ-cube..................................... 35 2 Mikrokosmos 38 2.1 Implementation of λ-expressions . 38 2.1.1 The Haskell programming language . 38 2.1.2 De Bruijn indexes . 40 2.1.3 Substitution . 41 2.1.4 De Bruijn-terms and λ-terms . 42 2.1.5 Evaluation .
    [Show full text]
  • A Concurrent Logical Framework I: Judgments and Properties
    A concurrent logical framework I: Judgments and properties Kevin Watkins Iliano Cervesato Frank Pfenning David Walker March 2002, revised May 2003 CMU-CS-02-101 School of Computer Science Carnegie Mellon University Pittsburgh, PA 15213 This research was sponsored in part by the National Science Foundation under the title “Meta-Logical Frameworks,” grants CCR-9619584 and CCR-9988281; and in part by NRL under grant N00173-00-C- 2086. Iliano Cervesato was partially supported by NRL under contract N00173-00-C-2086 and by NSF grant INT98-15731. David Walker was partially supported by the Office of Naval Research under the title “Efficient Logics for Network Security,” grant N00014-01-1-0432; by DARPA under the title “Scaling Proof- Carrying Code to Production Compilers and Security Policies,” Contract No. F30603-99-1-0519; and by Microsoft Research. A part of this work was completed while David Walker was a post-doctoral fellow at Carnegie Mellon University. Abstract The Concurrent Logical Framework, or CLF, is a new logical framework in which concurrent computations can be represented as monadic objects, for which there is an intrinsic notion of concurrency. It is designed as a conservative extension of the linear logical framework LLF with the synchronous connectives ⊗,1,!,and∃of intuitionistic linear logic, encapsulated in a monad. LLF is itself a conservative extension of LF with the asynchronous connectives −◦ ,&and>. The present report, the first of two technical reports describing CLF, presents the frame- work itself and its meta-theory. A novel, algorithmic formulation of the underlying type theory concentrating on canonical forms leads to a simple notion of definitional equality for concurrent computations in which the order of independent steps cannot be distinguished.
    [Show full text]
  • A Linear-Logical Reconstruction of Intuitionistic Modal Logic S4
    A Linear-logical Reconstruction of Intuitionistic Modal Logic S4 Yosuke Fukuda Graduate School of Informatics, Kyoto University, Japan http://www.fos.kuis.kyoto-u.ac.jp/~yfukuda [email protected] Akira Yoshimizu French Institute for Research in Computer Science and Automation (INRIA), France http://www.cs.unibo.it/~akira.yoshimizu [email protected] Abstract We propose a modal linear logic to reformulate intuitionistic modal logic S4 (IS4) in terms of linear logic, establishing an S4-version of Girard translation from IS4 to it. While the Girard translation from intuitionistic logic to linear logic is well-known, its extension to modal logic is non-trivial since a naive combination of the S4 modality and the exponential modality causes an undesirable interaction between the two modalities. To solve the problem, we introduce an extension of intuitionistic multiplicative exponential linear logic with a modality combining the S4 modality and the exponential modality, and show that it admits a sound translation from IS4. Through the Curry–Howard correspondence we further obtain a Geometry of Interaction Machine semantics of the modal λ-calculus by Pfenning and Davies for staged computation. 2012 ACM Subject Classification Theory of computation → Linear logic; Modal and temporal logics; Proof theory; Type theory Keywords and phrases Linear logic, Modal logic, Girard translation, Curry–Howard correspondence, Geometry of Interaction, Staged computation Acknowledgements The authors thank Kazushige Terui for his helpful comments on our work and pointing out related work on multicolored linear logic, and Atsushi Igarashi for his helpful comments on earlier drafts. Special thanks are also due to anonymous reviewers of FSCD 2019 for their fruitful comments.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 3: Typed Lambda Calculus and Curry-Howard
    Lecture 3: Typed Lambda Calculus and Curry-Howard H. Geuvers Radboud University Nijmegen, NL 21st Estonian Winter School in Computer Science Winter 2016 H. Geuvers - Radboud Univ. EWSCS 2016 Typed λ-calculus 1 / 65 Outline H. Geuvers - Radboud Univ. EWSCS 2016 Typed λ-calculus 2 / 65 Typed λ calculus as a basis for logic λ-term : type M:A program : data type proof : formula program : (full) specification Aim: • Type Theory as an integrated system for proving and programming. • Type Theory as a basis for proof assistants and interactive theorem proving. H. Geuvers - Radboud Univ. EWSCS 2016 Typed λ-calculus 3 / 65 Simple type theory Simplest system: λ! or simple type theory, STT. Just arrow types Typ := TVar j (Typ ! Typ) • Examples: (α ! β) ! α,(α ! β) ! ((β ! γ) ! (α ! γ)) • Brackets associate to the right and outside brackets are omitted: (α ! β) ! (β ! γ) ! α ! γ • Types are denoted by A; B;:::. H. Geuvers - Radboud Univ. EWSCS 2016 Typed λ-calculus 4 / 65 Simple type theory `ala Church Formulation with contexts to declare the free variables: x1 : A1; x2 : A2;:::; xn : An is a context, usually denoted byΓ. Derivation rules of λ! (`ala Church): x:A 2 Γ Γ ` M : A ! B Γ ` N : A Γ; x:A ` P : B Γ ` x : A Γ ` MN : B Γ ` λx:A:P : A ! B Γ `λ! M : A if there is a derivation using these rules with conclusion Γ ` M : A H. Geuvers - Radboud Univ. EWSCS 2016 Typed λ-calculus 5 / 65 Examples ` λx : A.λy : B:x : A ! B ! A ` λx : A ! B.λy : B ! C.λz : A:y (x z):(A!B)!(B!C)!A!C ` λx : A.λy :(B ! A) ! A:y(λz : B:x): A ! ((B ! A) ! A) ! A Not for every type there is a closed term of that type: (A ! A) ! A is not inhabited That is: there is no term M such that ` M :(A ! A) ! A: H.
    [Show full text]
  • A Practical Module System for LF *
    A Practical Module System for LF ? Florian Rabe1 and Carsten Sch¨urmann2 1 Jacobs University [email protected] 2 IT University of Copenhagen [email protected] Abstract. Module Systems for proof assistants provide administrative support for large developments when mechanizing the meta-theory of programming languages and logics. In this paper we describe a module system for the logical framework LF. It is based on two main primitives: signatures and signature morphisms, which provide a semantically transparent module level and permit to represent logic translations as homomorphisms. Modular LF is a conser- vative extension over LF, and integrates an elaboration of modular into core LF signatures. We have implemented our design in the Twelf system and used it to modularize large parts of the Twelf example library. 1 Introduction The Twelf system [PS99] is a popular tool for reasoning about the design and properties of modern programming languages and logics. It has been used, for example, for verifying the soundness of typed assembly language [Cra03] and Standard ML [LCH07], for checking cut-elimination proofs for intuitionistic and classical logic [Pfe95], and for specifying and validating logic morphisms, for example, between HOL and Nuprl [SS06]. Twelf, however, supports only mono- lithic proof developments and does neither offer any support for modular proof engineering, composing logic morphisms, code reuse, nor name space manage- ment. In this paper we develop a simple yet powerful module system for pure type systems in general, and therefore for the logical framework LF [HHP93] in particular. If one subscribes to the judgement-as-types methodology (as we do in the Twelf community), the defining features of a logical framework, such as its equa- tional theory, determine usually the application areas it excels in.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1910.10703V3 [Cs.LO] 30 Mar 2020 Stesfwr Htcek T O a Ebosrptuti O in Trust Bootstrap System We a Can Such How in It
    Metamath Zero: The Cartesian Theorem Prover Mario Carneiro[0000−0002−0470−5249] Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh PA [email protected] Abstract. As the usage of theorem prover technology expands, so too does the reliance on correctness of the tools. Metamath Zero is a ver- ification system that aims for simplicity of logic and implementation, without compromising on efficiency of verification. It is formally speci- fied in its own language, and supports a number of translations to and from other proof languages. This paper describes the abstract logic of Metamath Zero, essentially a multi-sorted first order logic, as well as the binary proof format and the way in which it can ensure essentially linear time verification while still being concise and efficient at scale. Metamath Zero currently holds the record for fastest verification of the set.mm Metamath library of proofs in ZFC (including 71 of Wiedijk’s 100 formalization targets), at less than 200 ms. Ultimately, we intend to use it to verify the correctness of the implementation of the verifier down to binary executable, so it can be used as a root of trust for more complex proof systems. Keywords: Metamath Zero, mathematics, formal proof, verification, metamathematics 1 Introduction The idea of using computers to check mathematical statements has been around almost as long as computers themselves, but the scope of formalizations have grown in recent times, both in pure mathematics and software verification, and it now seems that there is nothing that is really beyond our reach if we aim for it. But at the same time, software faces a crisis of correctness, where more powerful systems lead to more reliance on computers and higher stakes for failure.
    [Show full text]
  • Curry-Howard Isomorphism
    Lectures on the Curry-Howard Isomorphism Morten Heine B. Srensen University of Copenhagen Pawel Urzyczyn University of Warsaw Preface The Curry-Howard isomorphism states an amazing correspondence between systems of formal logic as encountered in proof theory and computational calculi as found in type theory. For instance, minimal propositional logic corresponds to simply typed -calculus, rst-order logic corresponds to de- pendent types, second-order logic corresponds to polymorphic types, etc. The isomorphism has many aspects, even at the syntactic level: formulas correspond to types, proofs correspond to terms, provability corresponds to inhabitation, proof normalization corresponds to term reduction, etc. But there is much more to the isomorphism than this. For instance, it is an old idea—due to Brouwer, Kolmogorov, and Heyting, and later formalized by Kleene’s realizability interpretation—that a constructive proof of an implication is a procedure that transforms proofs of the antecedent into proofs of the succedent; the Curry-Howard isomorphism gives syntactic representations of such procedures. These notes give an introduction to parts of proof theory and related aspects of type theory relevant for the Curry-Howard isomorphism. Outline Since most calculi found in type theory build on -calculus, the notes be- gin, in Chapter 1, with an introduction to type-free -calculus. The intro- duction derives the most rudimentary properties of -reduction including the Church-Rosser theorem. It also presents Kleene’s theorem stating that all recursive functions are -denable and Church’s theorem stating that -equality is undecidable. As explained above, an important part of the Curry-Howard isomor- phism is the idea that a constructive proof of an implication is a certain procedure.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic-Independent Proof Search in Logical Frameworks (Extended Report)
    Logic-Independent Proof Search in Logical Frameworks (extended report) Michael Kohlhase1, Florian Rabe1, Claudio Sacerdoti Coen2, and Jan Frederik Schaefer1 1 Computer Science, FAU Erlangen-N¨urnberg 2 Department of Computer Science and Engineering, Universit`adi Bologna Abstract. An important question in research on logical framework is whether they can induce a logic-independent automated theorem prover. While many theorem proving innovations can indeed be generalized to large classes of logics, practically competitive provers usually require logic-specific optimizations. To investigate this question more deeply, we build a suite of modular logic definitions in a logical framework and generate Prolog-based the- orem provers for them. We focus on generality and avoid taking logic- specific knowledge into account. Our generated provers support natural deduction proof search, including backchaining, as well as tableau provers and model generators. Even though these efforts have only just started, we are already able to use the latter in a system for natural language understanding that combines grammatical with semantic processing. 1 Introduction and Related Work Logical frameworks like LF [HHP93] and λProlog [Mil] enable prototyping and analyzing logical systems, using high-level declarative logic definitions based on higher-order abstract syntax. Building theorem provers automatically from declarative logic definitions has been a long-standing research goal. But cur- rently, logical framework-induced fully logic-independent proof support is gen- erally limited to proof checking and simple search. Competitive proof support, on the other hand, is either highly optimized for very specific logics, most im- portantly untyped first-order logic, or obtained by defining logics as DSLs inside interactive proof assistants like Isabelle [Pau94].
    [Show full text]
  • A Concurrent Logical Framework: the Propositional Fragment
    A Concurrent Logical Framework: The Propositional Fragment Kevin Watkins1, Iliano Cervesato2, Frank Pfenning1, and David Walker3 1 kw,[email protected], Department of Computer Science, Carnegie Mellon University 2 [email protected], ITT Industries, AES Division 3 [email protected], Department of Computer Science, Princeton University Abstract. We present the propositional fragment CLF0 of the Concurrent Logical Framework (CLF). CLF extends the Linear Logical Framework to allow the natural representation of concurrent computations in an object language. The underlying type theory uses monadic types to segregate values from computations. This separation leads to a tractable notion of definitional equality that identifies computations differing only in the order of execution of independent steps. From a logical point of view our type theory can be seen as a novel combination of lax logic and dual intuitionistic linear logic. An encoding of a small Petri net exemplifies the representation methodology, which can be summarized as “concurrent computations as monadic expressions”. 1 Introduction A logical framework is a meta-language for deductive systems. It is usually defined as a formal meta-logic or type theory together with a representation methodology. A single implementation of a logical framework can then be used to study a va- riety of deductive systems, thereby factoring the effort that would be required to implement each deductive system separately. Applications of logical frameworks lie mostly in logic and programming languages, where deductive systems have be- come a common conceptual tool and presentation device. Examples are rules of logical inference, typing rules, and rules specifying the operational semantics of a programming language.
    [Show full text]
  • Semantics of Mizar As an Isabelle Object Logic
    Journal of Automated Reasoning https://doi.org/10.1007/s10817-018-9479-z Semantics of Mizar as an Isabelle Object Logic Cezary Kaliszyk1 · Karol P˛ak2 Received: 5 January 2018 / Accepted: 11 August 2018 © The Author(s) 2018 Abstract We formally define the foundations of the Mizar system as an object logic in the Isabelle logical framework. For this, we propose adequate mechanisms to represent the various components of Mizar. We express Mizar types in a uniform way, provide a common type intersection operation, allow reasoning about type inhabitation, and develop a type inference mechanism. We provide Mizar-like definition mechanisms which require the same proof obligations and provide same derived properties. Structures and set comprehension opera- tors can be defined as definitional extensions. Re-formalized proofs from various parts of the Mizar Library show the practical usability of the specified foundations. 1 Introduction Mizar [8] is one of the longest-lived proof assistants today. Its set theoretic foundations [27] together with an intuitive soft type system make the system attractive for mathematicians [68] and its formal library—the Mizar Mathematical Library (MML) [7]—became one of the largest libraries of formalized mathematics today. It includes many results absent from those derived in other systems, such as lattices [9], topological manifolds [63], and random-access Turing machines [42]. The unique features of the system include: – A soft type system which allows for dependent types and intersection types, – Declarative proofs in Ja´skowski-style natural deduction [33], – Convenient structure types with (multiple) inheritance, – A term language that allows for disambiguation based on types, in some cases allowing hundreds of meanings of a single symbol, – Proof checking corresponding to the research on the notion of “obviousness” of a single proof step, without the need to explicitly reference proof procedures or tactics.
    [Show full text]
  • Representing Model Theory in a Type-Theoretical Logical Framework Fulya Horozal, Florian Rabe ∗ Jacobs University Bremen, Germany Article Info a B S T R a C T
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Theoretical Computer Science 412 (2011) 4919–4945 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Theoretical Computer Science journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/tcs Representing model theory in a type-theoretical logical framework Fulya Horozal, Florian Rabe ∗ Jacobs University Bremen, Germany article info a b s t r a c t Keywords: In a broad sense, logic is the field of formal languages for knowledge and truth that have a Logical framework formal semantics. It tends to be difficult to give a narrower definition because very different Model theory kinds of logics exist. One of the most fundamental contrasts is between the different Proof theory First-order logic methods of assigning semantics. Here two classes can be distinguished: model theoretical Module system semantics based on a foundation of mathematics such as set theory, and proof theoretical semantics based on an inference system possibly formulated within a type theory. Logical frameworks have been developed to cope with the variety of available logics unifying the underlying ontological notions and providing a meta-theory to reason abstractly about logics. While these have been very successful, they have so far focused on either model or proof theoretical semantics. We contribute to a unified framework by showing how the type/proof theoretical Edinburgh Logical Framework (LF) can be applied to the representation of model theoretical logics. We give a comprehensive formal representation of first-order logic, covering both its proof and its model theoretical semantics as well as its soundness in LF.
    [Show full text]
  • A Type Theory for Defining Logics and Proofs
    A Type Theory for Defining Logics and Proofs Brigitte Pientka David Thibodeau Andreas Abel Francisco Ferreira Rebecca Zucchini School of Computer Science Dept. of Computer Science and Eng. Dept. of Computing ENS Paris Saclay McGill University Gothenburg University Imperial College London Abstract—We describe a Martin-Lof-style¨ dependent type this view, intensional LF-style functions represent syntactic theory, called COCON, that allows us to mix the intensional binding structures and functions are transparent. However, function space that is used to represent higher-order abstract we cannot write recursive programs about such syntactic syntax (HOAS) trees with the extensional function space that describes (recursive) computations. We mediate between HOAS structures within LF, as we lack the power of recursion. representations and computations using contextual modal types. In contrast, (recursive) computation relies on the extensional Our type theory also supports an infinite hierarchy of universes type-theoretic function space. Under this view, functions are and hence supports type-level computation thereby providing opaque and programmers cannot compare two functions for metaprogramming and (small-scale) reflection. Our main con- equality nor can they use pattern matching on functions to tribution is the development of a Kripke-style model for COCON that allows us to prove normalization. From the normalization inspect their bodies. Functions are treated as a black box. proof, we derive subject reduction and consistency. Our work lays To understand the fundamental difference between defining the foundation to incorporate the methodology of logical frame- HOAS trees in LF vs. defining HOAS-style trees using in- works into systems such as Agda and bridges the longstanding ductive types, let us consider an inductive type D with one gap between these two worlds.
    [Show full text]