<<

I. Introduction We Can’t Go By now, much of the public and many of its policy- makers understand the U.S. epidemic through a single narrative: The problem started as one of pre- Cold Turkey: scription painkiller abuse, but users switched to after pills become somewhat harder to get, and this black- supply was quickly tainted by Why Suppressing and other highly potent, synthetic . This narra- tive is powerful, because it also describes both a typical Markets drug user’s progression from pills to heroin to deadly fentanyl-laced injections. But it omits a key acceler- ant that transformed this wave of into an Endangers inferno of death, disease, and personal destruction: criminalized suppression of drug use. At each stage of the crisis, policymakers have sought to extinguish Society the problem of opioid abuse by directing enforce- ment, regulatory agencies, and private parties to try Nick Werle and Ernesto Zedillo cutting off the supplies of and deterring indi- viduals from using them. These suppressive strategies have produced unintended consequences that made the crisis substantially more harmful by pushing dependent users to engage in riskier behavior that is more likely to transmit diseases and lead to overdoses. This essay argues that policies aimed at suppress- ing drug use exacerbate the nation’s opioid problem. It neither endorses drug use nor advocates legalizing the consumption and sale of all substances in all circum- stances. Instead, it contends that trying to suppress drug markets is the wrong goal, and in the midst of an addiction crisis it can be deadly. There is no single, correct ; the right approach depends cru- cially on the substance at issue, the patterns of use and supply, and the jurisdiction’s culture, institutions, and material resources. is no panacea for a nation’s drug problems. Nevertheless, either de jure or de facto decriminalization of personal is a necessary condition for mitigating this crisis. The must shift its policies away from addressing drug use as a criminal justice issue and employ a public-health approach to managing . While some U.S. jurisdictions have adopted strategies to deal with people

Nick Werle, J.D., is a graduate of Yale Law School, a research associate in the International Drug Policy Unit at the London School of Economics and Political Science, and a fellow at Yale’s Solomon Center for Health Law and Policy. He received an MSc in from University College London and an MSc in risk and finance from the London School of Economics and Political Science with support from the U.K.’s Marshall Scholarship. Ernesto Zedillo, Ph.D., is the director of the Yale Center for the Study of Globalization, professor in the field of international economics and politics, and a mem- ber of the Global Commission on Drug Policy. He received his M.A. and Ph.D. in economics from Yale University. He was the president of Mexico from 1994–2000. opioids, law & ethics • summer 2018 325 The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s) DOI: 10.1177/1073110518782942 SYMPOSIUM who use drugs, these demand-side interventions will by making safer alternatives unavailable. Absent an be insufficient on their own to stop this crisis. As the accessible and safe supply of opioids for addiction Global Commission on Drug Policy has emphasized,1 maintenance and treatment, these suppressive policies policymakers must also address the harder, supply- will likely divert dependent demand to street drugs side problems — by expanding lawful access to opi- and worsen the crisis. oids, with the twin objectives of undermining the black This essay pragmatically critiques suppressive drug market and reducing the harm that existing opioid use , arguing that criminalization is a counterpro- poses to dependent users and their communities. ductive response to opioid abuse. We start from the Suppressive policies intended to address opioid premise that is a chronic, relaps- abuse will likely exacerbate the crisis of overdose ing medical condition, not a moral failing.2 Thus, deaths. are rushing to restrict the people suffering from drug addiction deserve treat- supply of opioid painkillers by implementing prescrip- ment and social support, not punishment. Some tion drug monitoring programs (PDMPs) and tighten- criminalization advocates recognize that opioid use ing on medical practice. Over-prescription disorder is a disease, but support criminalization of helped trigger the addiction epidemic, so these crack- drug markets in the misguided belief that this will downs may appear overdue. But the timing is wrong. reduce the number of people who have this illness. In Decades of opioid abuse have changed the background this essay we show that in fact criminalized suppres- sion does little to reduce the incidence of opioid use disorder, and surely increases the harm — including the risk of fatal- Today, there are many chronic opioid users ity — for people who use drugs. Other unlikely to stop consuming when painkillers advocates of criminalization view drug become scarce. With black-market heroin use primarily through a moral lens, and believe that conviction is appropriate to increasingly tainted by fentanyl, and without punish degeneracy. Combatting this idea widespread access to medication-assisted and its consequent stigma is important, treatment, policies that restrict the supply of not least because they contribute to the social exclusion of people who use drugs genuine pharmaceuticals will push people that amplifies substance abuse’s negative toward the more dangerous behavior of effects. But refuting this punitive view is injecting black-market powders. beyond our scope. Racism is another powerful motiva- tion, conscious or not, to criminalize people who use drugs. Many people have conditions against which these policies will operate. powerfully explained how American drug laws reflect Action in the 1990s and early 2000s to prevent the and feed racial anxieties. Criminal drug-control laws pharmaceutical industry, unscrupulous healthcare have contributed to immense racial disparities in providers, and misinformed doctors from flooding the U.S. population, and so racial justice is communities with painkillers might have made today’s an important reason to abandon these policies. The crisis less acute. But today, there are many chronic opi- current crisis has been understood in starkly racial- oid users unlikely to stop consuming when painkillers ized terms, creating a popular understanding that the become scarce. With black-market heroin increasingly opioid epidemic primarily afflicts rural, white people, tainted with fentanyl, and without widespread access even though the overdose death toll is more multira- to medication-assisted treatment, policies that restrict cial and more urban than generally understood.3 The the supply of genuine pharmaceuticals will push peo- narrative that today’s heroin users are largely white ple toward the more dangerous behavior of injecting and that heroin suppliers are largely black and Latino black-market powders. Thus, well-intended policies has contributed to the public’s greater willingness to may increase fatal overdoses and blood-borne disease address opioid use less punitively, even as politicians transmission, just as the introduction of abuse-deter- have advocated for more suppressive supply-side rent pills increased HIV and hepatitis C infections by policies.4 Nevertheless, drug ’s racist ori- pushing users to inject painkillers. The point is not and the suppressive framework’s disparate racial that painkiller diversion and prescription-drug abuse effects are beyond the essay’s scope. are desirable, but rather that policies ought not push Finally, this essay does not address many of the ways existing users to start injecting fentanyl-laced heroin in which criminalization and incarceration harms

326 journal of law, medicine & ethics The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s) Werle and Zedillo individuals, their families, and communities. Convic- hand, the law employs harsh criminal and regulatory tion and incarceration in any circumstance directly sanctions to suppress unauthorized consumption. infringes an individual’s liberty, presents numerous But on the other hand, legally supplying opioids is an collateral consequences for that person, and harms immensely profitable, legal business: Pharmaceutical others in ways that radiate through families and com- companies may aggressively promote opioid use for munities. These impediments to human flourishing the medically supervised treatment of pain, and DEA- are crucially important to criminal justice reform, licensed healthcare providers can prescribe opioid both in general and specifically with respect to reform- painkillers to treat self-reported neuromuscular and ing suppressive drug laws. But since this essay focuses autoimmune pain, even absent clinical trials prov- on why suppressive policies have exacerbated the opi- ing that opioids are safe and effective for those indi- oid epidemic, we neglect many issues pertinent to a cations. True, the law bans nearly all access to some broader critique of the U.S. criminal justice system. substances, such as heroin. But licensed health care This essay proceeds in three parts. Section II providers may prescribe numerous chemically similar describes how the U.S. law has responded to the prob- opioids for pain management. Even if they prefer spe- lem of drug abuse by suppressing non-medical use cific substances, dependent users are generally will- and illicit supply chains. We also discuss criminalized ing to substitute other opioids based on availability, suppression’s historical roots and contrast it to harm potency, and . The black market’s size and acces- reduction. Section III analyzes criminalized suppres- sibility depends not only on law enforcement action sion’s economic logic and consequences. We discuss but also on the extent of legal access, because con- how the rise of fentanyl is a predictable consequence sumer demand shapes drug-trafficking networks, just of suppressive supply-side policies and how deterrence as consumer demand in other sectors induces suppli- has exacerbated the human costs of opioid addiction. ers to bring products to market. We also explain why state governments are wrong to Likewise, during the Prohibition era, restrict the supply of prescription opioids by creating remained legal for specific purposes and in certain mandatory PDMPs and other suppressive measures preparations. Thus, the law suppressed the alcohol without first radically expanding regulated access to trade rather than prohibiting it outright. The Volstead opioids for maintenance treatment. Finally, section IV Act, which regulated alcohol under Prohibition, per- proposes reforms that reject criminalized suppression mitted people to consume “sacramental” and to and discusses other countries’ pragmatic responses to store pre-Prohibition alcohol in their homes.5 People drug abuse. We argue that decriminalizing drug pos- could also obtain liquor under a doctor’s prescription.6 session is a necessary condition for mitigating this epi- These rules stratified Prohibition’s effects by class. The demic and that the United States must expand access wealthy could still purchase legal, high-quality liquor to medication-assisted treatment so as to provide an through compliant doctors and pharmacies. But those accessible, regulated supply of opioids to dependent unable to pay the extortionate to access genu- users. ine, “medical” liquor were relegated to buying traf- ficked liquor and often-adulterated spirits produced II. Criminalized Suppression: The Legal in black-market distilleries.7 The Volstead Act permit- Structure of Prohibition ted sale of so-called industrial , which were American drug laws reflect a policy framework ori- required to incorporate poisons and distasteful addi- ented toward suppressing unauthorized drug produc- tives so as to deter drinkers. But the criminal orga- tion and consumption, largely through the enforce- nizations and independent distillers that emerged to ment of criminal laws. We describe this framework satisfy the pent-up demand fortified their brews with as “criminalized suppression” of drug markets, an industrial alcohol to boost profitability. As a result, the approach that takes rates of non-medical drug con- poor ended up consuming these poisons to devastat- sumption and interdiction of illicit drugs as primary ing effect. indicators. This section describes criminalized sup- Federal law has long distinguished between opi- pression’s historical origins in the period of alcohol oid prescriptions intended to treat addiction through Prohibition and how it shapes opioid and maintenance therapy and those intended to numb addiction treatment today. pain. This distinction stretches at least to the 1914 Harrison Act, which was the first federal A. Suppression of “Non-Medical” Opioid law to prohibit non-medical opioid use, and its sub- Consumption sequent amendments. The Treasury Department, The United States regulates opioids so as to simulta- charged with enforcement, promulgated regulations neously suppress and promote their use. On the one excluding maintenance as a form of legitimate medi- opioids, law & ethics • summer 2018 327 The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s) SYMPOSIUM cal practice.8 Doctors could only administer opioids to patients.15 Nevertheless, Vivitrol is now the “go-to treat addiction if they rapidly weaned patients to sobri- option” in many of Ohio’s drug courts: The state paid ety, a process known as detoxification. The Supreme more than $38 million to provide 30,594 doses to Court subsequently adopted this view: Webb v. U.S. Medicaid-eligible people in 2016, up from 100 doses presented the question of whether the Harrison Act’s in 2012.16 exception for medical opioid administration applied ’s legal status illustrates the focus on where a physician prescribes “ to an habitual suppression rather than user safety or . user thereof, the order not being issued by him in the The FDA first approved methadone as an analgesic in course of professional treatment in the attempted cure 1947, but since the 1970s it has been used primarily for of the habit, but being issued for the purpose of pro- OAT. Methadone is a synthetic opioid that produces viding the user with morphine sufficient to keep him longer-lasting, less intense intoxication than heroin, comfortable by maintaining his customary use.”9 The permitting people with opioid dependence to achieve Court held 5–4 that maintenance prescriptions were a stable, high-functioning state without withdrawal non-medical and thus prohibited: “[T]o call such an symptoms or cravings. It has been proven to reduce order for the use of morphine a physician’s prescrip- illicit opioid use17 and its harmful consequences, tion would be so plain a perversion of meaning that no including mortality, , overdose, and HIV.18 It is discussion of the subject is required.”10 also cost-effective, despite heavy regulation.19 Today, opioid agonist treatment (OAT) for addic- Still, federal law permits doctors to prescribe meth- tion maintenance is the gold standard for treating opi- adone for pain more easily than for maintenance. oid use disorder. As a chronic, relapsing mental health When used for pain relief, DEA-licensed doctors may condition, opioid use disorder is not susceptible to a prescribe methadone without any more restrictions cure, per se. But evidence-based treatments employ- than would apply to another Schedule II drug, such ing OAT can help patients stabilize their lives, manage as OxyContin.20 In contrast, there are extensive fed- their , reintegrate into society, and reduce eral regulations governing methadone maintenance. the harmful consequences of drug use.11 Maintenance Under federal law, all methadone maintenance treat- therapy has been shown to be more clinically effective ments must occur in a federally regulated opioid treat- and more cost effective than detoxification.12 Absti- ment program. Specially licensed practitioners must nence-based treatments are common in the United provide the treatments, and the law prohibits prohib- States, where they often follow the model for alcohol its doctors from writing a methadone prescription to abuse treatment, with the goal of lifetime abstinence, be filled at a pharmacy, like they would for an opioid but there is little evidence of clinical efficacy.13 Absti- painkiller.21 Methadone for maintenance generally nence-based treatment can increase mortality risk: must be dispensed and immediately consumed, requir- While heroin withdrawal itself is rarely life-threat- ing patients to visit clinics daily.22 Opioid treatment ening, putting people with opioid use disorder into programs must randomly screen patients for illicit withdrawal poses a high risk of overdose, because a drugs.23 And clinics must provide a host of additional period of abstinence leads to reduced tolerance.14 This services to patients, adding to the cost and inconve- risk of overdose explains why abstinence-based treat- nience of methadone maintenance.24 State laws may ment approaches for are dangerous when impose other requirements,25 and local zoning laws applied to people with opioid use disorder: Relapse to or community opposition complicates opening new alcohol use is rarely fatal, but relapse to fentanyl-laced clinics. Methadone patients must organize their lives heroin often kills. around clinic visits, sometimes traveling several hours The government has long sought to suppress con- daily. These obstacles interfere with employment sumption with a medication that would “cure” opi- prospects and hinder social reintegration. oid addiction outright. But evidence shows that this Other forms of opioid maintenance are also goal can be deadly, because using medication to keep restricted by law. Doctors seeking to prescribe someone abstinent further raises overdose risk. Many must receive special training and drug courts and treatment programs now rely on nal- certifications, and federal law limits the number of trexone, which is sold under the brand name Vivitrol patients they may treat at any time.26 Yet no such pre- as a wonder drug for stopping opioid use. Naltrexone scribing limits exist for opioid painkillers, and phar- is an opiate antagonist that triggers immediate with- maceutical companies can even monitor prescribing drawal and blocks opioids’ pharmacological effects. rates and offer perks to the doctors selling the most But this abstinence is costly: Overdoses are more com- pills.27 Federal law requires a “legitimate medical pur- mon following cessation of naltrexone treatment than pose” for opioid prescriptions, and it expressly prohib- among either untreated heroin users or maintenance its doctors from prescribing opioid painkillers for the

328 journal of law, medicine & ethics The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s) Werle and Zedillo purpose of addiction maintenance, except under the ity remains vested in the police and judicial system, regulations specifically applicable to buprenorphine rather than public health authorities. Drug courts gen- and methadone.28 This creates an artificial shortage of erally retain the threat of incarceration for non-com- buprenorphine, particularly in rural areas far from a pliance. This structure is a poor match for managing methadone clinic where there are few doctors able to a chronic, relapsing condition, and so incarceration prescribe buprenorphine but high demand for treat- remains common. Judges often make treatment deci- ment. Even in large cities, the regulations create an sions, and without enforceable drug court standards, artificial scarcity for buprenorphine treatment spots, training in is scarce. Finally, many encouraging physicians to charge premium prices for drug courts provide only abstinence-based treatments access, sometimes refusing to accept insurance.29 As to participants. In one 2013 study, only 47% of U.S. a result, access to buprenorphine — much less dis- drug courts provided OAT, and only 26% permitted ruptive to personal lives and less stigmatized than methadone maintenance.34 methadone — is highly stratified by class and race.30 State Medicaid rules may also require buprenorphine C. Harm reduction: An alternative framework patients to attend time-consuming group counseling Many European countries have responded to heroin sessions, conditions that may be unduly burdensome crises of their own by shifting from criminalized sup- for people with poor access to transportation or who pression to harm reduction. Harm reduction is policy are trying to maintain employment on often-inflexible framework less concerned with the quantity of drugs terms. Interviews with patients and providers suggest consumed than with the social and individual harms that these requirements can function as barriers to wrought by drug production, sale, consumption, and treatment, encouraging patients to self-medicate with government policies. Rather than trying to deter peo- buprenorphine purchased from the black market. ple from using drugs with criminal sanctions, harm Demand for opioid maintenance dramatically reduction aims to shift users into patterns of use that outstrips the artificially constrained supply. In rural are less dangerous and less disruptive to society. A areas, methadone clinics can be distant and doctors suppressive framework, focused solely on reducing capable of taking on more buprenorphine patients consumption, threatens to withdraw rare.31 In urban areas, zoning regulations and inad- from people with addiction to make drug use more equate funding also constricts supply. Thus, patients costly and withhold resources from people deemed seeking maintenance treatment can face waiting lists undeserving. In contrast, harm reduction policies lasting a year or longer, during which time they face a steer people with problematic drug use toward tai- ten-fold higher risk of mortality than people immedi- lored services, such as safe injection facilities, low- ately taken on.32 Skeptics have cited black markets and threshold methadone treatment, or supportive hous- diversion as reasons to maintain these restrictions, ing. The goal is to help stabilize their lives, improve but with waiting lists that long, diversion should be their health, and reintegrate them into society, but seen as a symptom of supply shortages, not evidence not necessarily to get them to stop using immediately. that tight regulations are necessary to prevent abuse. Crucially, harm reduction services do not require con- tinuous abstinence from illicit drug use as a condition B. The role of criminalization in suppressing opioid of eligibility. use Adopting a harm reduction approach does not We describe this framework as criminalized suppres- mean condoning drug use. Drug possession is still sion, because criminal law and policing are the central illegal in jurisdictions with comprehensive harm means of enforcing the legal prohibition on illicit drug reduction policies, such as Switzerland and Portugal, consumption and supply. Typically, production, trans- as local officials explain early and often to observers. port, sale, and possession of illicit drugs are criminal However illicit drug possession for personal use rarely offenses under both state and federal law. While the leads to criminal charges. Instead, these societies have Supreme Court has declared it unconstitutional to created a set of institutions that treat substance use enact a “status crime” of being addicted to drugs,33 as a medical and . Police build trust more states can achieve the same result in practice, by effectively, because drug users need not fear incarcera- criminalizing the incidences of drug addiction, such tion. These countries assign primary responsibility for as consumption, the possession of , opioid abuse to public health authorities, who evalu- or the knowing keeping of premises for drug-related ate interventions on the basis of overdose deaths and purposes. disease transmission rates. They also administer low- Even where policymakers have introduced drug threshold OAT, which provides safe, low-cost access to courts and other diversion programs, primary author- opioids for maintenance purposes. These governments opioids, law & ethics • summer 2018 329 The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s) SYMPOSIUM reason that the state can control the black market only drug supply. This development reflects the economic by undercutting it with a safer, cheaper, and more reli- incentives that criminalized suppression creates for able supply than traffickers provide. Addiction treat- drug suppliers. The “iron law of prohibition” describes ment providers can help people achieve abstinence if the tendency for aggressive supply-side policing to they desire, but they define treatment success in terms lead drug supplies to become dominated by increas- of health and social inclusion, rather than urinalysis. ingly potent and toxic additives. Alcohol Prohibition triggered the iron law, poisoning scores who drank III. The Economic Consequences of spirits adulterated with additives that were both toxic Criminalized Suppression and intoxicating. Today, similar economic forces help A century spent trying to eradicate illicit drug use has explain why fentanyl has become so dominant in U.S. confirmed that consumer demand is the most pow- drug markets, even though its dangers are widely erful force shaping drug markets. Where there is an known. existing stock of habitual users, no degree of suppres- Alcohol Prohibition did far more to change what sion consistent with a democratic society can eradi- Americans drank than how much. During the three cate supply. Suppressive policies change, rather than years after the Volstead Act took effect, consumption eliminate, drug markets, altering the prices paid, the dropped to almost 30% of its pre-Prohibition level.35 suppliers who profit, and the content of substances But instead of making alcoholic beverages unavail- ingested. Prohibition increases profitability, by insert- able, the Volstead Act pushed production, trans- ing a large risk premium into drug prices. Prohibition port, sale, and consumption of alcohol underground. also directs drug-market revenues to transnational Organized criminal groups, infamously including the criminal organizations, financing violence and cor- Mafia, took over illicit alcohol markets, which proved ruption in consumer, transit, and producer countries. to be enormously profitable. By the late 1920s, after Criminalization magnifies the risks users face, by the black-market industry had developed, per capita empowering criminal suppliers who predictably cut alcohol consumption rebounded to 60–70% of its pre- drugs with toxic substances, and by stripping users’ Prohibition value.36 access to medical care, social support, and economic Even though per-capita alcohol consumption resources. decreased modestly under the Volstead Act, people This section analyzes the economic implications of drank far more potent brews. The Act’s consequences criminalized suppression. First, we show how crimi- validate the Iron Law of Prohibition: “The more nalized suppression predictably causes the illicit drug intense the law enforcement, the more potent the supply to become more dangerous, because black- drugs will become.”37 This follows from clear economic market producers and smugglers have an economic incentives for black market producers, smugglers, and incentive to use highly potent additives. This “iron law dealers to increase their products’ potency: of prohibition” contributed both to today’s fatal opi- oid overdose crisis and to the epidemic of poisonings [C]oncentrated, potent drugs are more efficiently during alcohol Prohibition. Second, we analyze crimi- smuggled, transported, and sold and are easier nalized suppression’s economic logic, which seeks to for the consumer to conceal, transport, and reduce demand by using the threat of punishment or consume without detection. Another advantage personal harm to deter people from using drugs. This of potent drugs for the seller, but a disadvantage framework has been used to justify government poli- for the buyer, is that potent drugs can more easily cies that make drug use more dangerous to individu- be “cut” with other chemicals that resemble the als and to society, even though it relies crucially on real thing. Often these dilutants are poisons.38 the false assumption that the decision to use drugs is rational, and thus amenable to deterrence. Finally, we Market data bear out that Prohibition’s greatest effect suggest an alternative mode of analyzing drug mar- on consumption was to cause hard liquor and wine to kets during an addiction epidemic that considers sup- replace as Americans’ drinks of choice. Per capita pressive policies’ implications for already-dependent consumption of beer decreased about 70% under Pro- users and people initiating drug use. hibition, but people drank 65% more wine and 10% more liquor, compared to the period from 1911–1914.39 A. Supply-side suppression makes the black market Some estimate that the potency of alcohol products more dangerous increased by more than 150% during Prohibition, Opioid overdoses are now the leading cause of death in compared to the periods before and after.40 This much of the United States. Many of the deaths are due dynamic follows from the cost structure of illicit drug to fentanyl, which has adulterated the black-market trafficking: Actual production and refining costs are

330 journal of law, medicine & ethics The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s) Werle and Zedillo often insignificant compared to the expenses involved “dark web.”52 But fentanyl is also laced into both heroin in transport, , and distribution, so cutting and counterfeit painkillers. In recent years, the DEA a product’s bulk by boosting its potency is a boon to has identified the rising trend of fentanyl-laced, coun- profitability. Historical alcohol prices reflect this cost terfeit pharmaceuticals as particularly dangerous, structure: While beer prices increased more than because it expands the population of at-risk users.53 700% from pre-Prohibition prices, liquor prices only Fentanyl’s rise was not an unfortunate coincidence; increased about 270%.41 Expenditures on distilled it was a predictable consequence of the supply-side spirits increased from 40% of total pre-Prohibition incentives created by suppressive government policies. alcohol spending to almost 90% during Prohibition.42 Fentanyl is cheaper to produce than heroin, because For those who kept drinking, Prohibition made it does not require labor-intensive cultivation and alcohol more dangerous. Almost immediately after harvesting of poppies. But more importantly, Prohibition began, methyl alcohol, which cost about fentanyl is cheaper to traffic: Its lethal dose is just 2 one-eighth of drinkable ethyl alcohol,43 appeared in milligrams.54 Suppliers can thus boost profitability black-market alcohol. Bootleggers would stretch their by lacing heroin with fentanyl, since they smuggling grain alcohol by adding homemade “wood alcohol” or less bulk produces the same number of doses. The an industrial alcohol after attempting to distill out the government has sought to fortify the southern border, poisonous components.44 This added a long-lasting, responding to Mexican cartels trafficking heroin.55 But powerful intoxication, but distillation was only occa- fentanyl has traditionally taken different smuggling sionally successful.45 Wood alcohol blindness quickly routes than heroin. For a while, much of the illicit fen- reached epidemic proportions.46 Poisonings were tanyl supply entered the United States in illegal ship-

Just as alcohol Prohibition barely reduced drinking and produced a violent black market, attacking today’s drug traffickers is fruitless so long as the U.S. opioid market is so lucrative. Production volumes of illicit drugs are so high, and drug trafficking is so profitable, that interdiction cannot raise prices enough to induce lower consumption. Instead, supply-side suppression has encouraged traffickers to smuggle cheaper and more potent opioids.

common and came in waves, when tainted batches hit ments from China.56 But consistent with the iron law, the streets, just as fatal fentanyl overdoses do today. heightened interdiction rates increased the incentive The scale was comparable to today’s crisis: In 1926, for cartels to substitute fentanyl for heroin. Today, industrial alcohol sickened or blinded 1,200 people Mexican cartels reportedly synthesize fentanyl them- in alone; another 400 died.47 In the selves from Chinese precursors.57 South, a potent concoction known as “Jake ginger” Prohibition in the face of persistent demand gen- was legally sold by prescription for stomach ills but erates a black market with artificially high prices and also adulterated and strengthened by bootleggers.48 grants criminal organizations monopoly power over Even small quantities of Jake caused nerve damage that lucrative commerce. The of scale and permanent paralysis. It produced an “epidemic achievable in drug production, smuggling, , of poisonings,” and ultimately, “public health officials violence, and mean that organized estimated the number of Jake victims at fifty to sixty crime will tend to fight for and ultimately establish thousand.”49 dominant positions in their markets. In regions home The iron law also drives today’s overdose epidemic. to illicit agriculture, cartels can act as monopsonies, Much the death is due to fentanyl, which has per- keeping opium prices low and forcing subsistence vaded the black market since 2013. Fentanyl-related farmers to absorb the costs of crop eradication.58 The overdoses killed more than 20,000 people in 2016, bulk of drugs’ black-market value comes from traf- up more than 540% in three years.50 Some users buy ficking them across international borders, so Mexico’s fentanyl intentionally, because fentanyl is ultra-fast worst violence has been in the north, with cartels fight- acting and produces a more intense intoxication than ing for control of land crossings to the United States. other opioids,51 either from street dealers or via the At the distribution level, a single cartel is dominant in opioids, law & ethics • summer 2018 331 The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s) SYMPOSIUM many U.S. markets, possibly explaining why dealing- drug’s degradation of health and social capital, or the related violence has remained low.59 possibility of prosecution and punishment for illicit Just as alcohol Prohibition barely reduced drinking consumption. The theory also concludes that strong and produced a violent black market, attacking today’s addictions must end “cold turkey,” arguing that any- drug traffickers is fruitless so long as the U.S. opioid thing but immediate, full withdrawal is irrational, and market is so lucrative. Production volumes of illicit thus inappropriate, for treating heroin addiction.62 drugs are so high, and drug trafficking is so profitable, Subsequent economic theories have complicated this that interdiction cannot raise prices enough to induce picture, explaining the decision to use drugs through lower consumption.60 Instead, supply-side suppres- a model of temptation and self-control,63 mistake,64 or sion has encouraged traffickers to smuggle cheaper time-inconsistent preferences65. But these approaches and more potent opioids. still assume rationality and counsel the same policies: deterring future use by raising the user’s expected B. Deterrence and the economic logic of criminalized costs, suppressing drug supplies, and educating peo- suppression ple about drugs’ harmful effects. An oversupply of pharmaceutical opioids may have The rationalist view of addiction has been subject to triggered this addiction epidemic, but mitigating it extensive critique, but its intuitive theory of deterrence requires managing Americans’ demand for illicit opi- still animates policy decisions. Deterrence strategy oids. Traditionally, takes several usually takes the form of trying to make prosecution forms. First, prevention reduces the number of people more likely and punishments more severe. This strat- who begin using opioids, a crucial intervention in the egy reached its apogee during the Reagan era, when midst of an addiction epidemic. Second, treatment Congress imposed draconian mandatory minimum cuts demand from current users, both by reducing sentences for trafficking and production offenses, their consumption and by legally obtaining opioids for criminalized simple possession under federal law, and maintenance. And finally, deterrence convinces people introduced several enhancements that lengthened not to use drugs, by increasing the risks of drug use incarceration for repeat drug offenders and for use of and threats of legal sanctions. American drug policy a in connection with a drug crime. has long relied heavily on deterring drug use and The United States is unique among developed underinvested in addiction treatment. But that faith in democracies in the extent to which it incarcerates deterrence is misplaced, because it relies on a flawed people with substance use disorders, often follow- model of human behavior. The economic theory justi- ing conviction for minor drug distribution or prop- fying deterrence assumes that drug consumption is a erty offenses, even though incarceration is known to rational decision, in which potential users weigh the dramatically increase rates of overdose death. While costs and benefits of getting high. Despite criticism, incarceration generally exacerbates the social, psycho- this theory continues to motivate government policies logical, and economic reasons why someone ends up that exacerbate the health risks and social isolation in prison, incarceration poses extreme risks to people faced by people who use drugs, entrenching addic- with histories of injection drug use. Few U.S. detention tion’s etiology. facilities offer OAT, so incarceration usually produces Deterring future consumption is the central ratio- withdrawal and a dramatic fall in opioid tolerance. nale for punishing drug users. The modern theoreti- Thus, formerly-incarcerated people with histories of cal justification for deterrence is rooted in the micro- opioid addiction face an elevated risk of fatal overdose economic analysis of addiction, which models drug in the weeks following .66 use as a rational choice.61 Microeconomics describes Trying to deter drug use by raising its risks is a someone as acting rationally when she takes only common and deadly government strategy. During those actions for which her expected marginal ben- Prohibition, the federal government tried suppress- efit exceeds her expected marginal costs; that is, if she ing illicit drinking by making it riskier, a strategy that expects the choice to produce more pleasure than pain predictably led to severe consequences. In 1926, “dry” in the future. This model’s conclusion is that someone congressmen demanded that the federal government could rationally use addictive drugs because the plea- more aggressively deter bootleggers from transform- sure of today’s outweighs the present value ing industrial alcohols into salable spirits. In response, of addiction’s future pain and the risk of punishment Secretary of the Treasury Andrew Mellon approved for acting illegally. Consequently, policymakers should federal chemists’ “Formula No. 5,” which doubled the be able to deter people from using drugs by increasing methyl alcohol concentration in denaturing agents.67 the expected future costs of addiction. These expected The strategy worked, in the sense that it made safe costs may come from the drug’s purchase price, the alcohol much harder to obtain. But in so doing, it

332 journal of law, medicine & ethics The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s) Werle and Zedillo caused needless death and injury, since people contin- ing syringe shortage didn’t deter injection. It just led ued drinking anyway.68 people to share needles, predictably triggering an HIV Opponents of harm-reduction policies often invoke epidemic. In 2015, then-Governor Mike Pence permit- similar logic, arguing that access to syringe exchanges, ted one syringe exchange to open in Scott County, and safe injection facilities, housing programs, and low- a few other counties eventually followed suit. But local threshold OAT will encourage drug use, because it politicians have resisted these harm reduction mea- mitigates the risks of disease, homelessness, and poor sures on moral and deterrence grounds. Two counties health that supposedly dissuade people from using closed their syringe exchanges in late 2017 in the face opioids. For instance, politicians have argued that of ongoing an HIV epidemic. The Indiana Attorney syringe exchange programs encourage illicit drug use, General recently praised these closures, falsely assert- even though public health research has shown that ing that syringe exchanges encourage drug use: “Law- syringe exchanges do not encourage injection.69 In rence County is wise to back off the practice of distrib- fact, syringe exchanges are effective conduits to sub- uting free needles to heroin addicts and other opioid stance abuse treatment.70 abusers. Handing out clean needles encourages sub- Indiana exemplifies how misguided deterrence stance abusers to shoot up and, in many cases, shoot up more often.”75 Misplaced deterrence theories also power resistance to harm reduction ser- These examples demonstrate how the vices proven to reduce overdose deaths. suppressive logic of deterrence has Other countries, including Canada, have exacerbated the health consequences of used safe injection facilities (SIFs) to reduce overdoses, disease transmission, the opioid epidemic by obstructing access and public nuisances stemming from to harm reduction services. When people opioid use.76 But the Department of Jus- who use drugs associate state services with tice recently invoked the threat of federal criminal prosecution to prevent state and only repression and punishment, a deficit of local officials from setting up the nation’s trust develops, the neediest people will be first legally sanctioned SIF, arguing that unlikely to seek out public services. So long it would encourage drug use.77 Similar rhetoric slowed naloxone distribution. as criminalized suppression remains the Opponents claimed that reducing over- framework within which drug-dependent dose risk through naloxone access would people interact with the state, it will unduly encourage injection drug use and would discourage entry to abstinence-based hamper treatment access and social treatments. However, numerous studies provision. have disproven these assertions applying deterrence theory to naloxone access.78 These examples demonstrate how the suppressive logic of deterrence has logic has increased this epidemic’s toll. Scott County exacerbated the health consequences of the opioid in southern Indiana has seen a severe HIV outbreak epidemic by obstructing access to harm reduction ser- since 2015. According to CDC analysis, the outbreak vices. When people who use drugs associate state ser- emerged from abuse of the painkiller Opana, which vices with only repression and punishment, a deficit of gained popularity after access to OxyContin became trust develops, the neediest people will be unlikely to more difficult.71 In 2012, Opana’s manufacturers had seek out public services. So long as criminalized sup- released an abuse-deterrent formulation designed pression remains the framework within which drug- to prevent users from crushing and snorting pills. dependent people interact with the state, it will unduly But once this reformulation arrived in Scott County, hamper treatment access and social service provision. addicts began injecting.72 Indiana law is hostile to harm reduction efforts, and possession of syringes C. Suppressing prescription drugs without expanding with intent to use them for nonmedical purposes is access to opioid maintenance treatment will a felony.73 It is illegal to purchase syringes without a exacerbate the overdose crisis prescription, and a burdensome exception for syringe State governments are responding to the overdose epi- exchanges was only added in 2015.74 But the result- demic suppressing the painkiller supply and making it opioids, law & ethics • summer 2018 333 The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s) SYMPOSIUM

“abuse-resistant.” But these are the wrong policies at their own use or to sell to others. State health depart- the wrong time. With so many people already addicted ments, and law enforcement personnel, can also use and access to opioid maintenance treatment an inac- some states’ PDMPs to identify anomalous behavior cessible patchwork, making it harder for dependent and then target providers or patients for enforcement users to access pharmaceutical opioids will push them actions.85 PDMPs have been shown to reduce the vol- to inject fentanyl-laced, black-market powders and ume of opioids prescribed by more than 30%,86 par- ingest counterfeit pills. Prescription painkiller abuse is ticularly in the 32 states that mandate provider access serious, but pushing users into the black market mag- prior to prescribing opioid analgesics.87 nifies the epidemic’s harmful consequences, including The states have taken other measures to suppress overdoses. Policymakers should respond to the opioid nonmedical use of pharmaceutical opioids and restrict problem by expanding access to OAT, rather than by the diversion of pills to dealers. Some legislatures and pushing people toward riskier behavior. medical boards have limited the number of pills and The misguided effort to suppress painkiller abuse refills doctors may prescribe at a time. Attorneys gen- by introducing abuse-deterrent formulations (ADFs) eral, medical licensing boards, criminal prosecutors, is a cautionary tale. Starting around 2012, pharma- and health departments have sought to deter physi- ceutical companies reformulated several blockbuster cians and pharmacists from prescribing opioids to opioid pills, including OxyContin and Opana, to people with addictions. The federal government, state make them harder to crush and sniff. Manufacturers attorneys general, and private litigants have also sued had two motivations. Public health research showed pharmaceutical manufacturers and distributors for that most heroin users initiated opioid use by tak- misbranding and negligent distribution practices. ing legally dispensed pills, crushing and sniffing the Are these policies helping? PDMPs and these other pills before starting to inject.79 ADFs were intended to measures have been touted for reducing the number make painkiller abuse more difficult and thus prevent of opioid prescriptions.88 But this begs the question painkiller users from developing destructive addic- of whether reducing prescriptions is an unalloyed tions. But financial incentives may have dominated: public health benefit. Restricting the volume of opi- Manufacturers faced impending patent expirations, oids that doctors can prescribe to new pain patients which would have opened their blockbuster painkill- may reduce the rate at which people become addicted. ers to generic competition. They responded by intro- But prescription opioids’ reduced accessibility also ducing newly patented ADFs and then the compels habitual painkiller abusers to switch from FDA to take pills without these “safety” features off genuine pharmaceuticals to using counterfeit pills or the market, preventing non-ADF generics from com- black-market heroin. As with the similar shift follow- peting with brand-name painkillers.80 At the time, no ing ADFs’ introduction, harmful consequences should generics on the market had ADFs. Several years later, increase. Indeed, empirical work from the past year economists and public health officials have confirmed has validated these concerns. A recent econometric that the ADFs backfired and blame them for accelerat- analysis found that adopting PDMPs increased by ing users’ transitions from pills to powders.81 Unable 47%–84% the rate of heroin-involved criminal inci- to snort the pills, many users turned to injecting them, dents that police encounter in the counties with high- increasing risks of overdose and disease transmission. est per capita rates of pre-PDMP prescription opioid Others turned to black-market drugs, buying fen- consumption.89 But in lower-consumption counties, tanyl-laced heroin or counterfeit pills.82 Despite the PDMP adoption did not significantly change the rate evidence, ADFs’ intuitive appeal has attracted federal of heroin-involved incidents.90 Studies of overdose officials eager to be seen responding to the addiction mortality found that PDMP adoption had widely vary- crisis. Expanding the transition to ADFs is now a cen- ing effects across states, but one found that implemen- terpiece of the FDA’s national response.83 tation of PDMPs was associated with an 11% increase State governments have taken the lead in responding in mortality.91 Another study found a to the crisis, but many states’ strategies have empha- slight decrease in mortality overall.92 These data are sized restricting prescription opioid access with Pre- consistent with the proposition that reducing access scription Drug Monitoring Programs (PDMPs) and to genuine pharmaceuticals is harmful where unman- physician discipline, instead of expanding OAT access. aged opioid addiction is prevalent and OAT access is Forty-nine states now operate PDMPs, statewide difficult. databases that record patients’ prescription histories In the same vein, states with restrictive for controlled substances.84 PDMPs permit provid- laws have fared worse than those with legal access. ers to identify patients who are “doctor shopping” to Cannabis is a less addictive analgesic than hydroco- try to obtain multiple, simultaneous prescriptions for done and habitual use is less harmful than habitual

334 journal of law, medicine & ethics The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s) Werle and Zedillo heroin use, so cannabis could have been a better option policies remain tethered to suppression, because most for many chronic pain patients and a less harmful sub- dependent users still lack access to a regulated supply stitute for some non-medical opioid use. A nationwide of drugs. States should rapidly reform both their laws analysis from 1999 to 2010 found that states permit- and practices so as to shift from a punitive framework ting chronic pain patients to obtain to one based on medical treatment, social support, legally had an opioid analgesic overdose mortality rate and harm reduction. 25% lower than states without medical cannabis laws.93 Decriminalization policies must be tailored to spe- ’s experience from 2000–2015 also suggests cific communities. In some areas,de facto decriminal- that legalization of recreational cannabis produced a ization, achieved through law enforcement policies 6.5% reduction in opioid-related deaths in the follow- and cooperative relationships with drug treatment ing two years.94 This evidence supports our contention providers and community groups, may be sufficient. that providing safe, regulated access to “illicit” drugs However, de jure decriminalization is better, because mitigates the consequences that drugs pose to society. it eliminates police officers’ power to selectively Counterintuitively, the best response to the opioid arrest drug users, thereby fostering greater trust. For epidemic at this juncture may be to increase, rather instance, Good Samaritan laws that protect people than to suppress, regulated opioids access. We are not witnessing an opioid overdose from arrest amplify the arguing that prescription opioid abuse is good. Rather, public-health benefits from equipping police officers we contend that with such a large stock of dependent with naloxone, because witnesses are more likely to users and without access to low-threshold mainte- call for help. Even better is the model of cooperation nance treatment, suppressing the supply of genuine between police and social workers in the Law Enforce- pharmaceuticals pushes addicted people to consumer ment Assisted Diversion (LEAD) model: Social work- riskier black-market drugs. Therefore, until OAT is ers, defense attorneys, prosecutors, and police officers widely accessible, further suppression of pharmaceu- work together in case-management teams to stabi- ticals is unwise. lize the lives of marginalized drug users. In practice, LEAD operates as de facto decriminalization of drug IV. Toward Public-Health Oriented possession, with cooperative rehabilitation replacing Regulation of Opioids outright suppression. By substituting social support In 2016, more than 2.1 million Americans had an for arrest, LEAD has been able to reduce participants’ opioid use disorder.95 Those unable to remain absti- odds of arrest by 58%.96 nent need a regulated and safe means of maintaining Non-U.S. jurisdictions that have effectively stopped their addictions and obtaining treatment. Introduc- opioid epidemics have shifted primary responsibil- ing a safe, reliable, and sufficiently accessible supply of ity to public-health agencies, which tend to respond opioids for existing users can erode the demand that to relapse with service provision rather than punish- supports black markets. Just as important, a regu- ment. The difference between American drug courts lated supply system can improve individual and - and the Portugal’s commissions for the dissuasion of lic health, because people are less likely to overdose drug addiction (CDTs) highlight why public health or contract diseases consuming pharmaceutical-grade authorities must take the leading role. American drug opioids than injecting substances bought on the street courts operate on a post-arrest diversion model, with or in an anonymous, online bazaar. This system of sup- criminal prosecution held in abeyance pending com- ply should be run through a revamped, low-threshold, pletion of the drug court program. People can avoid insurance-funded OAT system. This section discusses a judgment only if they avoid relapsing. The entire why decriminalization of drug possession for personal process of arrest, booking, detention, and ongoing use is a necessary response to the crisis and describes proceedings is costly and stigmatizing, complicating reforms to the U.S. OAT system that could transform social and economic reintegration even if someone is it into an effective way of supplying opioid-dependent “successful.” But if the defendant fails the drug court’s people with an accessible and regulated source for program, she remains liable to incarceration. Such addiction maintenance. failure is common, because many drug courts ascribe to an abstinence-based philosophy and either prohibit A. Decriminalization is a necessary but insufficient OAT or permit it only under restrictive conditions.97 response to the crisis Because substance use disorder is a chronically relaps- Some U.S. jurisdictions have abandoned the most ing condition characterized by compulsive drug use, a draconian tactics for suppressing drug consumption. model that punishes people for “failure” is itself poorly But even where the government relies less on threat- equipped for success. ened punishment to deter people from using drugs, opioids, law & ethics • summer 2018 335 The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s) SYMPOSIUM

In contrast, the Portuguese public health authorities injection drug use, safe injection facilities ought to be run the CDT system. If the police encounter someone opened as soon as possible. SIFs are professionally on the street in possession of drugs for personal use, supervised healthcare facilities that seek to reduce they give him an administrative summons for atten- mortality and morbidity by providing high risk drug dance at the local CDT. There is no arrest and no crim- users with a safe, hygienic place to consume drugs inal record. CDT panels comprise psychiatrists, social obtained off-premises. While politically contentious, workers, and lawyers, working together with a staff to SIFs’ public health benefits are well settled. More than understand the client’s needs in a holistic manner. If 90 SIFs operate legally in other countries, includ- the CDT determines that his drug use is unproblem- ing Switzerland, , Spain, France, Denmark, atic, they may impose a small fine, order community Norway, Canada, and Australia.98 Unsanctioned service, or merely dismiss him. But if it finds that he SIFs operate in New York City and elsewhere in the has an addiction or another social problem, it will United States, and several cities’ public health depart- refer him to appropriate services, chiefly low-thresh- ments are working toward opening a municipal SIF old OAT. Access to these drugs is much easier than in in 2018, despite the federal government’s steadfast the United States: Vans circulate throughout Lisbon, opposition.99 Numerous studies have found that SIFs

Law enforcement agencies cannot address the root causes of substance use disorder, because they lack authority to establish regulated systems of supply and low-threshold OAT. But for those systems to work, law enforcement agencies must be fully engaged partners, policing in ways that reinforce, rather than undermine, the medical care and social reintegration of people who use drugs.

dispensing methadone to clients without burdensome do not increase injection drug use, drug trafficking, rules or drug testing requirements. The CDT operates or crime.100 SIFs do, however, decrease the morbid- as a case manager, connecting people with necessary ity and mortality associated with injection drug use, services. People with more severe problems receive increase uptake of addiction treatment, and reduce more substantial services, and there is no threat of the public nuisances associated with drug use, such juridical coercion. as discarded syringes and injection in public spaces.101 Portugal’s is a religious and socially conserva- SIFs have been remarkable successful in reducing tive society. Portuguese officials stress that drug use fatal opioid overdoses: In Vancouver, Canada opening remains illegal, but that decriminalization is the neces- a SIF caused fatal opioid overdoses to fall 35% in the sary condition for their real reform — low-threshold surrounding area.102 In Sydney, Australia, the num- OAT — to work. American commentators advocat- ber of ambulance calls responding to overdoses near ing drug policy reform often point to Portugal as an a SIF decreased 68% during its operating hours.103 example of how “decriminalization” can eliminate drug None of the legally operating SIFs has ever reported problems. But that’s not how the Portuguese see it. a fatal opioid overdose by a someone using its ser- Only by decriminalizing the lives of drug users can the vice.104 In 2011, when the Canadian Supreme Court state build the trust necessary to bring them into state ordered the Minister of Health to continue licensing care for addiction treatment, social services, and OAT. Vancouver’s experimental SIF, the Court declared its Portugal’s current situation is by no means utopian, social value to be settled: “[the Vancouver SIF] saves and there is still problematic drug use. But the country lives. Its benefits have been proven. There has been enacted a self-consciously pragmatic policy response no discernable negative impact on the public safety to a severe opioid epidemic at the end of the 1990s, and and health objectives of Canada during its eight years these measures successfully restrained the crisis and of operation.”105 reduced overdose deaths and disease transmission. Abstinence-based limits on access to wraparound The United States should adopt a similar harm social services and public benefits should also be reduction strategy. Given the prevalence of high-risk removed, because requiring people to be abstinent

336 journal of law, medicine & ethics The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s) Werle and Zedillo in order to get access to services does not help people ment than the United States and prohibit the kinds of manage addiction. The best-studied context is hous- financial incentives and marketing practices that led ing, and the evidence is clear: “[The] traditional absti- to overreliance on painkillers in the first place. nence approach was not more effective at reducing Low-threshold methadone maintenance is the cor- rates of substance use.”106 In randomized controlled nerstone of comprehensive drug treatment. Where trials, people provided with housing first, and subject methadone and buprenorphine maintenance is avail- to no abstinence requirements, were “significantly able in the United States, the numerous regulatory and less likely to use or abuse substances when com- practical barriers to access make it a “high-threshold” pared to Treatment First clients.”107 Deterrence-based service. Features of high-threshold treatment include approaches are counterproductive, because relapse requirements that patients visit specialized and often does not follow from rational cost-benefit calcula- inaccessible clinics daily for supervised drug admin- tions. Stable housing permits people who use drugs to istration, inflexible admission criteria, waiting lists, reintegrate into society and better manage chemical limited-duration treatment, zero-tolerance of illicit dependencies. Stress is a crucial driver of relapse to drug use, and high prices. In contrast, low-threshold problematic drug use, and eviction needlessly intro- services impose few requirements to access treatment. duces stress, trauma, and disruption into an already Patients need not abstain from illicit drugs as a condi- disorganized life. So even if abstinence is the goal, law tion of service use, and these programs aim to reduce should not make it a necessary condition receiving all documented barriers to service access and mini- social support. mize requirements for retention.108 They also aim to Law enforcement agencies cannot address the destigmatize treatment, so people who use drugs feel root causes of substance use disorder, because they welcome, trust the service, and know they will not be lack authority to establish regulated systems of sup- discriminated against. Low-threshold services con- ply and low-threshold OAT. But for those systems to sider relapses to be expected features of the underly- work, law enforcement agencies must be fully engaged ing condition, and they respond with additional ser- partners, policing in ways that reinforce, rather than vices rather than discipline. Wraparound services and undermine, the medical care and social reintegration counseling are usually offered but are not compulsory. of people who use drugs. Service providers seek to be minimally disruptive to patients’ lives, so they do not require patients to travel B. Public health-oriented regulation of opioids long distances, using pharmacy distribution, “metha- How can we design a system that provides an acces- done buses,” and take-home doses to eliminate daily sible, regulated supply of opioids to people already clinic visits. dependent on the drugs without encouraging others Other countries’ pragmatic responses to opioid crises to start using? Other countries, including Switzerland, of their own can serve as a model for U.S. policymakers. Portugal, Germany, and the have faced In France, methadone maintenance must be initi- epidemics of heroin abuse in the past and reformed ated in clinics, but a patient may transfer her prescrip- their systems for healthcare, policing, and social ser- tion to a general practitioner after her condition is vices to abate the crisis and manage future abuse. stabilized. Methadone is free in clinics and pharmacy- Each successful national addiction treatment system dispensed doses are reimbursed through standard has at its core a comprehensive, low-threshold OAT prescription coverage. Pharmacies may provide up to system that provides existing users with an accessible a week’s doses at a time. Users are not required to reg- and low-cost source for pharmaceutical grade opioids. ister, undergo no testing for illicit drug use, and need Access to maintenance drugs is considered essential, not undergo counseling as a condition of treatment.109 mainstream medical care, and so regulations permit These policies, introduced in 1995, are credited with people who have stabilized their conditions to quickly substantially reducing opioid overdoses, HIV and escape the disruptive pattern of daily clinic visits for hepatitis C incidence, and drug-related crime.110 methadone maintenance by shifting oversight to In Hong Kong, the Department of Health actively general practitioners and permitting prescriptions promotes methadone maintenance and makes on- for take-home doses to be filled at local pharmacies. demand methadone treatment very accessible. Opi- Several jurisdictions have also recognized the value ate-dependent people can generally access methadone of adding medical-grade heroin as an OAT mainte- maintenance on the same day they present for treat- nance option because some patients’ conditions are ment, following a urine test to verify that they are opi- more stable with heroin-assisted treatment (HAT) oid users. People under 18 are admitted, and parental than with methadone or buprenorphine. Finally, consent is preferred but not mandatory.111 The fee for these jurisdictions use far fewer opioids in pain treat- each visit is fixed at HK$1 ($0.13).112 The clinics oper- opioids, law & ethics • summer 2018 337 The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s) SYMPOSIUM ate daily and are open before and after work hours, as high-threshold, clinic-based HAT. Swiss health insur- more than half of maintenance patients are employed. ance plans must cover all OAT options, providing Methadone’s accessibility is key, and mobile ser- extremely low-cost and reliable access to a safe, high vice provision has been successful in several cities. In quality, supply. And since providing these services Amsterdam, the government has distributed metha- is not unusually profitable, providers lack structural done by bus since the 1970s. These mobile clinics dis- incentives to expand the market. The absolute num- pense free methadone throughout the city, so patients ber of opioid consumers, including OAT recipients, may attend more easily.113 Lisbon adopted this model has stayed consistent since the height of the Swiss in 2001, and now has several buses that dispense opioid epidemic in the early 1990s, indicating that free methadone throughout the greater metropoli- prevention efforts and the regulatory structure gov- tan area.114 One can only imagine how providing such erning OAT have kept people from initiating opioid mobile methadone services would increase mainte- use, despite collapsing heroin prices.120 The addiction nance treatment access both in the rural areas of the treatment system has largely replaced the black mar- United States, where addiction is rampant and metha- ket as a source for accessing opioids. The black market done access extremely limited, and in sprawling met- has been structurally stable and largely non-violent ropolitan areas. during this period, with well entrenched, Albanian The U.S. government should also add pharma- criminal organizations dominating the scene.121 Intel- ceutical-grade heroin to the list of approved drugs ligence suggests that the heroin trade is now mini- for maintenance therapy. Switzerland, Germany, the mally profitable. So long as the potency and volume of Netherlands, the United Kingdom, France, Australia, the heroin market remain stable and residual traffick- and Canada have all offered heroin-assisted treatment ing activity produces neither violence nor public nui- (HAT) in specialized clinics, either as an established sances, suppressing the illicit heroin market remains a or experimental treatment.115 Studies have shown that low police priority. incorporating heroin maintenance was more effec- Skeptics may object that expanding the OAT system tive than methadone maintenance alone for certain and lowering access thresholds would risk providing groups of long-term and treatment-resistant drug an accessible and socially acceptable means for people users and produced no greater incidence of seri- to initiate drug use. But the experiences of Switzerland ous adverse effects.116 Randomized controlled trials and other countries belay that fear. Low-threshold in the Netherlands have shown that HAT patients OAT access does not mean no-threshold access: Pro- experienced significantly fewer heroin cravings and viders still test patients’ urine to ensure that they are engaged in less illicit heroin use than methadone opioid users, because giving methadone to someone maintenance patients.117 A randomized, controlled without any tolerance is dangerous. A well-regulated trial in Vancouver found that for some patients, using OAT system actually reduces the risk of initiation, injectable heroin for maintenance was more effective because it undermines black-market suppliers, who than oral methadone at retaining people in addiction have incentives to promote opioid dependence and treatment and at reducing illicit drug use and other so seek out new customers. In the United States, the illegal activity, such as sex work.118 Interviews in Van- black market’s ubiquity likely explains the troubling couver showed that HAT permitted people with long- increase from in the proportion of people initiating term addictions to stabilize their lives, improve their opioid use directly with black-market heroin. A recent health, regain employment, and reintegrate into social study estimated that the proportion of Americans who and political life. But realizing these benefits requires initiated opioid use with heroin increased from 9% in open-ended maintenance treatment, since forced 2005 to 33% in 2015.122 This dramatic increase in peo- cessation of HAT causes the gains to evaporate.119 ple starting directly with heroin further suggests that Introducing pharmaceutical-grade heroin as a main- policymakers focused on restricting painkiller access tenance therapy option could therefore improve the are actually fighting the last . health of America’s existing injection drug users and Opioids are highly addictive substances, but politi- help extinguish the demand powering illicit markets. cal is as important as chemistry in triggering Switzerland shows how government-administered an addiction epidemic. In better regulated supplies, OAT can stabilize an epidemic of drug use and under- the goal should providing dependent users with a safe, cut an incumbent black market. Methadone and accessible, and reliable supply of opioids for addic- buprenorphine are available on a low-threshold basis tion maintenance without encouraging oversupply through general practitioners and regular pharma- and initiation of abuse. Unlike today’s alcohol mar- cies. Patients addicted for more than two years who ket, no entities should have economic incentives to have twice failed other treatment regimens qualify for promote problematic consumption. Given the intrin-

338 journal of law, medicine & ethics The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s) Werle and Zedillo sic risks of dispensing opioids and the documented addiction treatment for themselves or their loved success of existing OAT regimens, it makes sense to ones often lack the information necessary to make organize access through the treatment system and informed choices, and maintenance therapy’s stigma to fund the care through medical insurance. Relying drives people away from evidence-based treatment. on market-based incentives to enlist private-sector As a result, many patients are in expensive facilities providers entails making maintenance treatment suf- but lack access to OAT. The trend has even resulted in ficiently profitable. But making opioid prescription of purportedly public institutions, such profitable entails its own substantial risks, made plain as facilities for civil commitment of opioid users, which in the well-known stories of pharmaceutical industry are increasingly run by the private prison industry and manipulations and physician profiteering that ignited too rarely provide high-quality OAT. the epidemic of painkiller addiction. Government has an important role, not just as a The pharmaceutical industry’s dismal track record regulator but as a direct service provider or a link in in fomenting this epidemic is a cautionary tale. Even the supply chain. Models exist for using exclusive gov- some libertarian-minded advocates of drug “legal- ernment provision of critical supply chain services to ization” have questioned their stances, in light of the prevent profit-maximizing, private entities from over- role legal opioids played in triggering addictions.123 supplying a habit-forming substance and damaging But concluding that prohibition is best follows only public health. For instance, the Uruguayan law legal- from an ideological premise that criminalized pro- izing recreational cannabis created a state monopoly hibition and unregulated legalization are the only at the wholesale level. This entity mediates between available policy alternatives. Prescription painkillers highly regulated growers and highly regulated retail- caused such damage because they were aggressively ers, setting prices that both ensure sufficient returns and deceptively marketed in a regulatory environment on investment to attract private capital and prevent excessively deferential to industry and focused more the industry from expanding and commercializing to a on profitability than on health. Many of prescription degree that would undermine public health. In an ear- opioids’ dangers stem from the fee-for-service financ- lier era, the British government successfully addressed ing models that generally bedevil American health- the problem of drunkenness in wartime factory towns care, though the iatrogenic risks of over-testing pale in by nationalizing , which then provided alcohol comparison to those of over-medicating post-surgical under conditions dictated by public health concerns and pain management patients. Even more dangerous rather than profitability.126 And following Prohibition, are laws permitting pharmaceutical manufacturers to some U.S. states retained government monopolies on supplement physicians’ incomes with perks and con- retail liquor sales. Of course, public control does not sulting fees, as Perdue Pharma famously did for doc- eliminate risk of bad regulatory design: One need only tors that prescribed the most OxyContin. To regulate consider state-run lotteries to see how public entities opioids consistently with public health needs, provid- can also run amuck. ers must be compensated on the basis of population Widespread public provision of low-threshold health, not services rendered. And prescribers should maintenance treatment would be an excellent invest- follow the direction of impartially generated medical ment. Numerous studies have found that mainte- evidence, not industry marketing materials. nance therapies are cost effective, even as currently Neither are addiction treatment providers guaran- provided, because people with OAT-stabilized addic- teed to be public-health regarding. Indeed, this addic- tions impose fewer costs on other social programs, tion epidemic has spurred a concomitant boom in the law enforcement, and healthcare services.127 But the treatment market, and private capital is rushing in to current system is unnecessarily expensive and thus exploit profit opportunities. This has financed dra- crowds out more and better services for people who matic consolidation of addiction treatment providers, use drugs. Methadone is an unpatented medicine fueled by billions of dollars in cash from the private that is cheap to produce. Many of the costs associated equity industry.124 Since American addiction treat- with maintenance treatment are the result of the sup- ment lacks clear standards of care, profitability, rather pressive regulations that also impede access. Shift- than evidence, often determines treatment regimens. ing maintenance treatment to a low-threshold model This frequently means abstinence and group therapy, would not just ease access to care, but that it would rather than OAT. Sometimes, it can also mean com- also make proper addiction medicine more affordable pulsory work programs, with sober home residents and thus more widely available. or drug court participants sent to work without pay Ultimately, drug policies that govern policing and in local businesses that have made financial arrange- prescribing cannot solve this crisis on their own. Issues ments with “treatment” providers.125 People seeking as disparate as employment conditions, pharmaceuti- opioids, law & ethics • summer 2018 339 The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s) SYMPOSIUM

ment Compared to Enriched 180-Day Methadone Detoxifica- cal misbranding regulations, healthcare finance, hous- tion,” Addiction 99, no. 6 (2004): 718–726. ing policy, and sustainable development programs 13. See A. Paraherakis et al., “An Abstinence-Oriented Program all affect patterns of drug use and supply. Cannabis for Substance Use Disorders: Poorer Outcome Associated with Opiate Dependence,” The Canadian Journal of Psychia- legalization and implementation of harm reduction try 45, no. 10 (2000): 927-931. responses to the opioid epidemic reflect a growing 14. van den Brink and Haasen, supra note 11, at 637. awareness that eradication of non-medical drug use 15. A. J. Ritter, “Naltrexone in the Treatment of Heroin Depen- dence: Relationship with Depression and Risk of Over- is a futile objective. Our contribution is to show that dose,” Australian and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry 36, suppression is not just fruitless but is actually harm- no. 2 (2002): 224-228, at 227. ful. Although beset by crisis, the United States has 16. R. Dissell, “Ohio’s Spending on Opioid Addiction Treatment Drugs Vivitrol and Suboxone Spikes, Spurs Debate on what an historic opportunity to break from the policies of Treatments Work,” Cleveland Plain Dealer, April 30, 2017. criminalized suppression. No two drug crises are the 17. R. P. Mattick et al., “Methadone Maintenance Therapy versus same, just as no two societies are interchangeable. No Opioid Replacement Therapy for Opioid Dependence,” Cochrane Database Systematic Reviews 3, no. 3 (2009): 10-11. Nevertheless, other countries’ experiences demon- 18. van den Brink and Haasen, supra note 14, at 637. strate that a public health approach to drug problems 19. P. G. Barnett, “The Cost-Effectiveness of Methadone Main- is both more humane and more effective than crimi- tenance as a Health Care Intervention,” Addiction 94, no. 4 (1999): 479–488. nalized suppression. 20. C. S. Davis and D. H. Carr, “The Law and Policy of Opioids for Pain Management, Addiction Treatment, And Overdose Note Reversal,” Indiana Health Law Review 14 (2017): 1–39, at 17. The authors have no conflicts to declare. 21. 42 C.F.R. § 8.12. 22. 21 C.F.R. § 1306.7. 23. 42 C.F.R. § 8.12(f)(6). Acknowledgements 24. 42 C.F.R. § 8.12(f). Many thanks to Kate Stith, Abbe Gluck, and Haynie Wheeler for 25. 42 C.F.R. § 8.11(f)(1). making this article possible. The authors also benefitted greatly 26. 21 C.F.R. § 1301.28. from comments and suggestions by John Collins, Alejandro 27. See P. R. Keefe, The Family That Built an Empire of Pain, Madrazo Lajous, Gregg Gonsalves, Nina Cohen, Kate Redburn, New Yorker, Oct. 30, 2017. Nathan Guevremont, Lisa Erickson, and Barbara Selvin. The 28. 21 C.F.R. § 1306.04. authors would also like to thank the participants of the work- 29. See J. A. del Real, “Opioid Addiction Knows No Color, but its shop on opioid regulation at the Yale Center for the Study of Treatment Does,” New York Times, January 12, 2018. Globalization. 30. H. Hansen, C. Siegel, et al., “Buprenorphine and Methadone Treatment for Opioid Dependence by Income, Ethnicity and Race of Neighborhoods in New York City,” Drug and Alcohol References Dependence 164 (2016): 14-21. 1. Global Commission on Drug Policy, Advancing Drug Policy 31. S. C. Sigmon, “Access to Treatment for Opioid Dependence Reform: A New Approach to Decriminalization, 2016, avail- in Rural America: Challenges and Future Directions,” JAMA able at Psychiatry 71, no. 4 (2014): 359-360. (last visited April 25, 2018). 32. E. Peles et al., “Opiate-Dependent Patients on a Waiting List 2. See, e.g., G. F. Koob and N. D. Volkow, “Neurocircuitry of for Methadone Maintenance Treatment are at High Risk for Addiction,” Neuropsychopharmacology 35, no. 1 (2010): Mortality until Treatment Entry,” Journal of Addiction Medi- 217–238. cine 7, no. 3 (2013): 177–182. 3. J. Katz and A. Goodnough, “The Opioid Crisis Is Getting 33. See Robinson v. California, 370 U.S. 660, 666–67 (1962). Worse, Particularly for Black Americans,” New York Times, 34. H. Matusow et al., “Medication Assisted Treatment in US Dec. 22, 2017. Drug Courts: Results from a Nationwide Survey of Availabil- 4. See K. James and A. Jordan, “The Opioid Crisis in Black ity, Barriers and Attitudes,” Journal of Substance Abuse Treat- Communities,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 46, no. 2 ment 44, no. 5 (2013): 473–480. (2018): 404-421. 35. C. Warbuton, “Economic Results of Prohibition,” (New York: 5. See Title II, § 6, Volstead Act, Pub. L. 66-66 at 311 (exception Columbia University Press, 1932): at 260; See also J. A. Miron for sacramental wine) & Title II, § 33 Pub. L. 66-66 at 317 and J. Zwiebel, “Alcohol Consumption During Prohibition,” (exception for possession and personal consumption of pre- American Economic Review 81, no. 2 (1991): 242–247, at 242. Prohibition liquor in one’s dwelling). 36. Miron and Zwiebel, supra note 35, at 242. 6. See Id., § 7. 37. R. Cowan, “How the Narcs Created Crack,” National Review, 7. See L. McGirr, War on Alcohol (New York: W. W. Norton & December 5, 1986, at 26, 27. Co., 2015). 38. S. Duke, “Drug Prohibition: An Unnatural Disaster,” Con- 8. D. F. Musto, The American Disease, 3d ed. (Oxford: Oxford necticut Law Review 27 (1995): 571–612, n. 104 at 598. U.P., 1999): 122–23. 39. Warburton, supra note 35, at 260 (comparing consumption 9. 249 U.S. 96, 99 (1919). from 1927–1930 with that from 1911–1914). 10. Id. 40. L. Beletsky and C. S. Davis, “Today’s Fentanyl Crisis: Prohi- 11. See generally W. van den Brink and C. Haasen, “Evidence- bition’s Iron Law, Revisited,” International Journal of Drug Based Treatment of Opioid-Dependent Patients” The Cana- Policy 46 (2017) 156–159, at 157. dian Journal of Psychiatry 51, no. 10 (2006): 635-646. 41. Id. 12. K. L. Sees et al., “Methadone Maintenance vs. 180-Day Psy- 42. Id. chosocially Enriched Detoxification for Treatment of Opioid 43. S. L. Ziegler, “The Ocular Menace of Wood Alcohol Poison- Dependence: A Randomized Controlled Trial,” JAMA 283 ing,” British Journal of Ophthalmology 5, no. 8 (1921): 365– (2000): 1303–1310; See also D. Polsky et al., “Cost and Cost- 373, at 368. Effectiveness of Standard Methadone Maintenance Treat- 44. D. Blum, The Poisoner’s Handbook (New York: Penguin Press, 2010), at 154–156.

340 journal of law, medicine & ethics The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s) Werle and Zedillo

45. Id. at 161–162. AnestheticAndAnalgesicDrugProductsAdvisoryCommittee/ 46. Ziegler, supra note 43, at 365. UCM547237.pdf> (last visited Jan. 23, 2018). 47. Blum, supra note 44, at 157–8. 72. S. A. Strathdee and C. Beyrer, “Threading the Needle—How 48. McGirr, supra note 7, at 59. to Stop the HIV Outbreak in Rural Indiana,” New 49. Id. Journal of Medicine 373, no. 5 (2015): 397-399. 50. J. Katz, “The First Count of Fentanyl Deaths in 2016: Up 73. Ind. Code § 16-42-19-18 (2017). 540% in Three Years,” New York Times, September 2, 2017. 74. Ind. Code § 16-41-7.5-5 (2017). 51. H. Smith, “A Comprehensive Review of Rapid-Onset Opioids 75. Curtis Hill, Indiana Attorney General, Facebook, Oct. 19, for Breakthrough Pain,” CNS Drugs 26, no. 6 (2012): 509–535, 2017, available at (last visited May 2, Deadly Drugs by Mail, New York Times, June 10, 2017. 2018). 53. DEA Intelligence Brief, “Counterfeit Prescription Pills Con- 76. S. Burris et al., “Federalism, Policy Learning, and Local Inno- taining : A Global Threat,” DEA-DCT-DIB-021-16, vation in Public Health: The Case of the Supervised Injec- (July, 2016) at 4. tion Facility,” St. Louis University Law Journal 53 (2008): 54. European Monitoring Centre for Drugs and Drug Addiction, 1089–1154. “Fentanyl Drug Profile,”available at (last visited of the U.S. Attorney’s Office concerning Proposed Injection January 23, 2017). Sites, December 13, 2017, available at (last visited May 2, 2018). Norteamérica 10, no. 2 (2015): 47–67, 50–53 (describing his- 78. A. R. Bazazi, et al., “Preventing Opiate Overdose Deaths: tory of U.S. interdiction efforts at the U.S.–Mexico border). Examining Objections to Take-Home Naloxone,” Journal of 56. S. O’Connor, U.S.-China Economic and Security Review Health Care for the Poor and Underserved 21, no. 4 (2010): Commission, “Fentanyl: China’s Deadly Export to the United 1108–1113. States,” February 1, 2017, available at (last visited May 2, 2018) 80. See FDA, “General Principles for Evaluating the Abuse Deter- 57. See A. Ahmed, “Drug That Killed Prince is Making Mexican rence of Generic Solid Oral Opioid Drug Products Guidance Cartels Richer, U.S. Says,” New York Times, June 9, 2016. for Industry,” November 2017, available at (last visited Mary 2, 59. DEA, “United States: Areas of Influence of Major Mexi- 2018) (“applicant should evaluate its proposed generic drug can Transnational Criminal Organizations,” DEA-DCT- to show that it is no less abuse deterrent than the RLD with DIR-065-15, July 2015. respect to all of the potential routes of abuse.”) 60. See H. A. Pollack and P. Reuter, “Does Tougher Enforcement 81. See W. N. Evans, E. Lieber, and P. Power, “How the Refor- Make Drugs More Expensive?” Addiction 109, no. 12 (2014): mulation of OxyContin Ignited the Heroin Epidemic,” Notre 1959–1966. Dame Department of Economics Working Papers, June 1, 61. See G. S. Becker and K. M. Murphy, “A Theory of Rational 2017, available at (last visited May 2, 2018). 675–700. 82. See A. Alpert, D. Powell, and R. L. Pacula, “Supply-Side Drug 62. Id., at 692-693. Policy in the Presence of Substitutes: Evidence from the 63. See, e.g., G, Faruk, and W. Pesendorfer, “Harmful Addic- Introduction of Abuse-Deterrent Opioids,” National Bureau tion,” Review of Economic Studies 74, no. 1 (2007): 147–172. of Economic Research, working paper No. 23031, (2017). 64. See, e.g., B. D. Bernheim and A. Rangel, “Addiction and Cue- 83. See e.g., S. Gottlieb, “FDA Takes Important Steps to Stem the Triggered Decision Processes,” American Economic Review 94, Tide of Opioid Misuse and Abuse,” FDA Voice by Commis- no. 5 (2004): 1558–1590. sioner Scott Gottlieb, M.D., September 28, 2017, available 65. See, e.g., T. O’Donoghue and M. Rabin. “Self-Awareness and at (last visited May 2, 2018). tives on Intertemporal Choice, (New York: Russel Sage Foun- 84. National Alliance for Model State Drug Laws, Compilation of dation, 2003): 217–244. Prescription Monitoring Program Maps, May 2016, available 66. See I. A. Binswanger et al., “Release from Prison-A High Risk at (last visited May 2, 2018) (hereinafter cine 356, no. 2 (2007): 157–165. NAMSDL), at 2. 67. “Government to Double Alcohol Poison Content and Also 85. Id., at 18. Add Benzine,” New York Times, December 29, 1926, at 1. 86. Y. Bao et al., “Prescription Drug Monitoring Programs are 68. Blum, supra note 47, 158–159. Associated with Sustained Reductions in Opioid Prescribing 69. Institute of Medicine, Preventing HIV Infection Among by Physicians,” Health Affairs 35, no. 6 (2016) 1045–1051, at Injecting Drug Users in High-Risk Countries. An Assessment 1048. of the Evidence (, D.C.: National Academies Press, 87. See T. C. Buchmueller and C. Carey, “The Effect of Prescrip- 2006). tion Drug Monitoring Programs on Opioid Utilization in 70. R. Heimer, “Can Syringe Exchange Serve as a Conduit to Sub- Medicare,” National Bureau of Economic Research working stance Abuse Treatment?” Journal of Substance Abuse Treat- paper, No. w23148, (2017); NAMSDL, supra note 84. ment 15, no. 3 (1998): 183–191. 88. CDC, Opioid Overdose: State Successes, available at (last vis- ER 19, presentation at Joint Meeting of the Drug Safety and ited Jan. 23, 2018). Risk Management Advisory Committee and the Anesthetic 89. J. Mallatt, “The Effect of Prescription Drug Monitoring Pro- and Analgesic Drug Products Advisory Committee, March grams on Opioid Prescriptions and Heroin Crime Rates,” 13, 2017, available at

90. Id. 11-12, available at dose Mortality,” Injury Epidemiology 1, no. 1 (2014) at 3. (last visited May 3, 2018). 92. S. W. Patrick et al., “Implementation of Prescription Drug 110. J. Emmanuelli and J. C. Desenclos, “Harm Reduction Inter- Monitoring Programs Associated with Reductions in Opi- ventions, Behaviours and Associated Health Outcomes in oid-Related Death Rates,” Health Affairs 35, no. 7 (2016): France, 1996–2003,” Addiction 100, no. 11 (2005): 1690–700, 1324–1332. at 1696–1699. 93. M. A. Bachhuber et al., “Medical Cannabis Laws and Opioid 111. Hong Kong Legislative Council, “Methadone Treatment Pro- Analgesic Overdose Mortality in the United States, 1999- grammes in Hong Kong and Selected Countries,” RP12/95- 2010, ” JAMA Internal Medicine 174, no. 10 (2014) 1668–1673, 96, March 1996, at 5–10, available at (last visited 94. M. D. Livingston et al., “Recreational Cannabis Legalization May 3, 2018). and Opioid-Related Deaths in Colorado, 2000–2015,” Ameri- 112. Hong Kong Department of Health, “Methadone Clinics,” May can Journal of Public Health 107, no. 11 (2017) 1827–1829, at 16, 2017, available at http://www.dh.gov.hk/english/main/ 1829. main_mc/main_mc.html, (last visited Jan. 23, 2018). 95. SAMHSA, Results From The 2016 National Survey On Drug 113. See H. N. Plomp et al., “The Amsterdam Methadone Dis- Use And Health: Detailed Tables, September 7, 2017, at Table pensing Circuit: Genesis and Effectiveness of a Public Health 5.2A, available at (last visited May 3, 2018). 114. H. Waal et al., “Open Drug Scenes: Responses of Five - 96. S. E. Collins et al., “Seattle’s Law Enforcement Assisted pean Cities,” BMC Public Health 14, no. 1 (2014): 853, at 7. Diversion (LEAD): Program Effects on Recidivism Out- 115. B. Fischer et al., “Heroin‐Assisted Treatment as a Response comes,” Evaluation and Program Planning 64 (2017) 49-56, to the Public Health Problem of Opiate Dependence,” Euro- at 53. pean Journal of Public Health 12, no. 3 (2012): 228–234, at 97. B. Andraka-Christou, “What Is Treatment for Opioid Addic- 229. tion in Problem-Solving Courts: A Study of 20 Indiana Drug 116. See P. Blanken et al., “Heroin-Assisted Treatment in the Neth- and Veterans Courts,” Stanford Journal of Civil Rights and erlands: History, Findings, and International Context,” Euro- Civil Liberties 13 (2017) 189–254, at 230. pean Neuropsychopharmacology 20, Supplement 2 (2010): 98. European Monitoring Centre for Drugs and Drug Addiction, S105–S158. Drug Consumption Rooms: An Overview of Provision and 117 P. Blanken et al., “Craving and Illicit Heroin use Among Evidence (Lisbon: European Monitoring Centre for Drugs Patients in Heroin-Assisted Treatment,” Drug and Alcohol and Drug Addiction, 2015). Dependence 120, no. 1 (2012): 74-80, at 77–78. 99. See A. H. Kral and P. J. Davidson, “Addressing the Nation’s 118. E. Oviedo-Joekes et al., “Diacetylmorphine versus Methadone Opioid Epidemic: Lessons from an Unsanctioned Supervised for the Treatment of Opioid Addiction,” New England Journal Injection Site in the US,” American Journal of Preventive of Medicine 361, no. 8 (2009) 777–786. Medicine 53, no. 6 (2017): 919–922. 119. I. Demaret and E. Quertemont, “Loss of Treatment Ben- 100. C. Potier et al., “Supervised Injection Services: What has been efit when Heroin-Assisted Treatment is Stopped after 12 Demonstrated? A Systematic Literature Review,” Drug and Months,” Journal of Substance Abuse Treatment 69 (2016): Alcohol Dependence 145 (2014): 48–68, at 63. 72–75. 101. Id. 120. See C. Nordt and R. Stohler, “Low-Threshold Methadone 102. B. D. Marshall et al., “Reduction in Overdose Mortality after Treatment, Heroin Price, Police Activity and Incidence of the Opening of North America’s First Medically Supervised Heroin Use: The Zurich Experience,” International Journal Safer Injecting Facility: A Retrospective Population-Based of Drug Policy 20, no. 6 (2009): 497–501. Study,” Lancet 377, no. 9775 (2011) 1429–1437. 121. F. Zobel et al., Le Marché des Stupéfiants dans le Canton de 103. A. M. Salmon et al., “The Impact of a Supervised Injecting Vaud. Partie 1 : Les Opioids (Lausanne: Addiction Suisse, Facility on Ambulance Call-Outs in Sydney, Australia,” Addic- 2017) at 38–60, 70-90. tion 105, no. 4 (2010): 676–683. 122. T. J. Cicero et al., “Increased use of Heroin as an Initiat- 104. Potier, supra note 100, at 62. ing Opioid of Abuse,” Addictive Behaviors (2017): 63–66, at 105. Canada (Attorney General) v. PHS Community Services Soci- 64–65. ety, [2011] S.C.C. 44 (Can.). 123. See, e.g., R. VerBruggen, “What the Opioid Crisis Can Teach 106. D. K. Padgett et al., Housing First: Ending Homelessness, Us about the ,” Law and Liberty, November Transforming Systems, and Changing Lives (Oxford: Oxford 1, 2017, available at (last visited May 3, 2018). less Clients with Serious Mental Illness: Comparing Housing 124. See J. Whalen and L. Cooper, “Private-Equity Pours Cash into First with Treatment First Programs,” Community Mental Opioid-Treatment Sector,” Wall Street Journal, September 2, Health Journal 47, no. 2 (2011) 227–232, at 230. 2017. 108. M. M. Islam et al., “Defining a Service for People who use 125. See D. Segal, “City of Addict Entrepreneurs,” New York Times, Drugs as ‘Low-Threshold’: What Should be the Crite- January 3, 2018; A. J. Harris and S. Walter, “They Thought ria?,” International Journal of Drug Policy 24, no. 3 (2013): They were Going to Rehab. They Ended up in Chicken 220–222. Plants,” Reveal News, (October 4, 2017). 109. International Harm Reduction Development Program, Open 126. See R. Duncan, Pubs and Patriots: The Drink Crisis in Brit- Society Institute, “Lowering the Threshold: Models of Acces- ain during World War One (Liverpool, UK: Liverpool Univer- sible Methadone and Buprenorphine Treatment,” (2010) at sity Press, 2013): 121–149.

342 journal of law, medicine & ethics The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 46 (2018): 325-342. © 2018 The Author(s)