Topological Groupoids

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Topological Groupoids Alberto Santini Topological groupoids Kandidatproject Institut for Matematiske Fag, Københavns Universitet. Lektor: Jesper Michael Møller 2 Contents 1Basicconcepts 2 1.1 Introduction to categories ......................... 2 1.2 Groupoids and the fundamental groupoid ................. 8 1.3 Functors ................................... 13 1.4 Pushouts ................................... 18 1.5 Further properties of the fundamental groupoid ............. 22 1.6 The fundamental group of the circle .................... 27 1.7 Fibrations of groupoids and cofibrations of spaces ............ 29 2Productsandquotientsofgroupoids 34 2.1 Universal morphisms and universal groupoids .............. 34 2.2 Free groupoids and free product of groupoids ............... 36 2.3 Quotient groupoids ............................. 40 2.4 Adjunction spaces .............................. 41 2.5 Van Kampen theorem for the fundamental groupoid ........... 43 Index 47 Bibliography 49 1 CHAPTER ONE BASIC CONCEPTS 1.1 Introduction to categories There are basically two ways of approaching groupoids. The first one is algebraically, considering them as a particular generalization of the algebraic structure of group. The second one, that is the one we’ll use and need to prove our results is the category theoretical approach. To do this, we’ll introduce some basic aspects of category theory, with in mind the fact that we’ll always use it as tool for our topological aim. Categories have been introduced by Saunders Mac Lane ([3]) and Samuel Eilenberg as a way to generalize particular dual properties of groups and lattices, but then they have proven useful as a generalization of almost all algebraic structures mathematicians usually deal with. Their basic constituents are objects and morphisms (sometimes called arrows) that satisfy certain axioms, as explained in what follows. Definition 1.1.1. A category is a quadruple A =(Obj(A), Hom, Id, ) where ◦ Obj(A) is a class, whose members are called the objects of A. • For each A, B Obj(A), HomA(A, B) is a set whose elements are called mor- • ∈ f phisms and are denoted as A B;wealsocallA the domain and B the −→ codomain of f. IdA,A For each A Obj(A), IdA,A is a morphism A A,calledtheidentity on A. • ∈ −→ 2 CHAPTER 1. BASIC CONCEPTS f g For each A, B, C, Obj(A) and each A B,B C, g f is a morphism • g f ∈ −→ −→ ◦ A ◦ C; is called a composition law. −→ ◦ such that the following holds: f g h C1 The composition is associative: given A B, B C, C D we have ◦ −→ −→ −→ (f g) h = f (g h). ◦ ◦ ◦ ◦ f C2 The identities IdA,A actually act as identities for the composition: given A B −→ we have that f IdA,A = f and IdA,B f = f. ◦ ◦ C3 The various sets HomA(A, B) are pairwise disjoint. We will sometimes refer to HomA := HomA(A, B) (1.1.1) A,B Obj(A) ∈ HomA(A, ) := HomA(A, B) (1.1.2) − B Obj(A) ∈ HomA( ,B) := HomA(A, B) (1.1.3) − A Obj(A) ∈ (1.1.4) Example 1.1.2. Examples of categories are: Set where the objects are the sets and the morphisms are functions between • them. Pos where the objects are partially ordered sets and the morphisms are the • isomorphisms between posets (i.e. order-preserving maps). Lin where the objects are finite-dimensional K-vector spaces and the morphisms • are the linear maps between them. Grp where the objects are groups and the morphisms are group homomorphisms. • Every monoid M is also a category with just an object, M itself and whose • morphisms are the elements of M (so that the identity is the identity of M and the composition is just the multiplication on M). 3 CHAPTER 1. BASIC CONCEPTS Top where the objects are topological spaces and the morphisms are continuous • functions between them. Given a topological space X,wedefinethecategoryP X;theobjectsarethe • points of X and the morphisms are the paths between them (a path from x X ∈ to y X is a continuous function px,y :[0, 1] X such that px,y(0) = x and ∈ → px,y(1) = y). The identity for x X is the null-path i.e. the constant function ∈ px,x(t)=x t [0, 1] and the composition is the concatenation of paths. ∀ ∈ Definition 1.1.3. Given two categories A and B we say that B is a subcategory of A if Obj(B) Obj(A). • ⊆ Given two objects A, B Obj(B) we have that HomB(A, B) HomA(A, B). • ∈ ⊆ Composition in B is the same as the one in A. • For each A Obj(B) we have IdB,A =IdA,A. • ∈ B is said to be wide if it has exactly the same objects as A, while it is said to be full if each couple of objects of B has the same morphisms both in A and B. f g Definition 1.1.4. Given two morphisms A B and B A,wesaythatthey −→ −→ are respectively a co-retraction and a retraction if g f =IdA,A.Sometimeswe ◦ say that g is a left-inverse of f and f is a right-inverse of g. The following theorem will show that, fixed a morphism that has both a left and right inverse, it is legitimate to simply refer to its inverse without specifying if left or right. We will call such a morphism invertible or an isomorphism. f g h Theorem 1.1.5. Given A B and B A, B A,ifg f =IdA,B and −→ −→ −→ ◦ f h =IdA,A,theng = h. ◦ Proof. g = g IdA,A = g (f h)=(g f) h =IdA,B h = h (1.1.5) ◦ ◦ ◦ ◦ ◦ ◦ 4 CHAPTER 1. BASIC CONCEPTS Definition 1.1.6. Two objects A, B Obj(A) are called isomorphic if there exists f ∈ an isomorphism A B.It’strivialtoprovethattherelation“is isomorphic to”is −→ an equivalence relation on Obj(A),ifthisisaset. Exercise 1.1.7. An object Oi Obj(C) is said to be initial if HomC(Oi,A) =1for ∈ | | all A Obj(C).AnalogouslyOf Obj(C) is called final if HomC(A, Of ) =1for ∈ ∈ | | all A Obj(C).Anobjectthatisbothinitialandfinaliscalledazero object. ∈ Prove that all initial objects are isomorphic as are all final objects. • Prove that Set and Top have initial and final objects but no zero object. • Prove that Grp has a zero object. • Proof. Let A, B Obj(C) be two initial objects. By hypothesis there are unique mor- • ∈ f A g f phisms A B and B ,sothereisamorphismA ◦ A.ButsinceA is −→ −→ −→ initial HomC(A, A) has only one element, so we must have that g f =IdC,A ◦ and analogously f g =IdC,B,soA and B are isomorphic. An entirely similar ◦ reasoning may be applied to final objects. Since functions can have empty domains, but can’t have empty codomains it’s • clear that the only initial object in Set is .Ontheotherhand,theonlyobject ∅ that allow only one map to be constructed such that it has the object as codomain, must have only one element and so the final objects are the singletons. Hence it’s clear then there is no zero object in Set.Reasoningintheexactsamewayone can find that the empty space is the only initial object of Top and that one-point space are its only final objects. Consider any group G = eG .Bytheverydefinition,thereisjustonehomomor- • { } phism from G to any other group H (and it is eG eH )andonehomomorphism → from H to G (and it is h eG for all h H). → ∈ f Exercise 1.1.8. AmorphismA B of C is called a monomorphism if −→ C Obj(C) g, h HomC(C, A) f g = f h g = h (1.1.6) ∀ ∈ ∀ ∈ ◦ ◦ ⇒ 5 CHAPTER 1. BASIC CONCEPTS Analogously it is called an epimorphism if C Obj(C) g, h HomC(B,C) g f = h f g = h (1.1.7) ∀ ∈ ∀ ∈ ◦ ◦ ⇒ f f We write monomorphisms as A B and epimorphisms as A B. Prove that a morphism of Set is a monomorphism if and only if it is injective. • Prove that a morphism of Set is an epimorphism if and only if it is surjective. • Prove that every isomorphism is both a monomorphism and an epimorphism. • Give an example of a category that has a morphism that is both an epimorphism • and a monomorphism, but not an isomorphism. Proof. f Given A B and a, a A with a = a,considerasingleton s Obj(Set) • ∈ { } ∈ and the functions fa,fa : s A : fa(x)=a fa (x)=a (1.1.8) { } → ∧ Since f is a monomorphism, we have that a = a f fa = f fa and so ⇒ ◦ ◦ f(a)=f(fa(x)) = f(fa (x)) = f(a) (1.1.9) On the other hand, if f is injective, given g, h : C A with g = h,letc C → ∈ be a point such that g(c) = h(c). Then by injectivity f(g(c)) = f(h(c)) and so f g = f h. ◦ ◦ f Given A B, consider a set with two elements s, t Obj(Set) and the • { } ∈ functions g,h B s, t (1.1.10) −→ { } g(x)=s x B (1.1.11) ∀ ∈ s if x f(A) h(x)= ∈ (1.1.12) t if x f(A) ∈ 6 CHAPTER 1. BASIC CONCEPTS Now notice that a A we have that g(f(a)) = s and h(f(a)) = s,sog f = h f ∀ ∈ ◦ ◦ and since f is an epimorphism this implies that g = h,thatistosaythat x Bx f(A) and so f is injective. On the other hand, given the injection ∀ ∈f ∈ g,h A B,considerC Obj C and the morphisms B C such that g f = h f. −→ ∈ −→ ◦ ◦ By surjectivity, each b B can be written as f(a) for some a A.Sowehave ∈ ∈ that g(b)=g(f(a)) = (g f)(a)=(h f)(a)=h(f(a)) = h(b) b B (1.1.13) ◦ ◦ ∀ ∈ ans so g = h,thatistosayf is an epimorphism.
Recommended publications
  • On Stratifiable Spaces
    Pacific Journal of Mathematics ON STRATIFIABLE SPACES CARLOS JORGE DO REGO BORGES Vol. 17, No. 1 January 1966 PACIFIC JOURNAL OF MATHEMATICS Vol. 17, No. 1, 1966 ON STRATIFIABLE SPACES CARLOS J. R. BORGES In the enclosed paper, it is shown that (a) the closed continuous image of a stratifiable space is stratifiable (b) the well-known extension theorem of Dugundji remains valid for stratifiable spaces (see Theorem 4.1, Pacific J. Math., 1 (1951), 353-367) (c) stratifiable spaces can be completely characterized in terms of continuous real-valued functions (d) the adjunction space of two stratifiable spaces is stratifiable (e) a topological space is stratifiable if and only if it is dominated by a collection of stratifiable subsets (f) a stratifiable space is metrizable if and only if it can be mapped to a metrizable space by a perfect map. In [4], J. G. Ceder studied various classes of topological spaces, called MΓspaces (ί = 1, 2, 3), obtaining excellent results, but leaving questions of major importance without satisfactory solutions. Here we propose to solve, in full generality, two of the most important questions to which he gave partial solutions (see Theorems 3.2 and 7.6 in [4]), as well as obtain new results.1 We will thus establish that Ceder's ikf3-spaces are important enough to deserve a better name and we propose to call them, henceforth, STRATIFIABLE spaces. Since we will exclusively work with stratifiable spaces, we now ex- hibit their definition. DEFINITION 1.1. A topological space X is a stratifiable space if X is T1 and, to each open UaX, one can assign a sequence {i7Λ}»=i of open subsets of X such that (a) U cU, (b) Un~=1Un=U, ( c ) Un c Vn whenever UczV.
    [Show full text]
  • A Few Points in Topos Theory
    A few points in topos theory Sam Zoghaib∗ Abstract This paper deals with two problems in topos theory; the construction of finite pseudo-limits and pseudo-colimits in appropriate sub-2-categories of the 2-category of toposes, and the definition and construction of the fundamental groupoid of a topos, in the context of the Galois theory of coverings; we will take results on the fundamental group of étale coverings in [1] as a starting example for the latter. We work in the more general context of bounded toposes over Set (instead of starting with an effec- tive descent morphism of schemes). Questions regarding the existence of limits and colimits of diagram of toposes arise while studying this prob- lem, but their general relevance makes it worth to study them separately. We expose mainly known constructions, but give some new insight on the assumptions and work out an explicit description of a functor in a coequalizer diagram which was as far as the author is aware unknown, which we believe can be generalised. This is essentially an overview of study and research conducted at dpmms, University of Cambridge, Great Britain, between March and Au- gust 2006, under the supervision of Martin Hyland. Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 General knowledge 3 3 On (co)limits of toposes 6 3.1 The construction of finite limits in BTop/S ............ 7 3.2 The construction of finite colimits in BTop/S ........... 9 4 The fundamental groupoid of a topos 12 4.1 The fundamental group of an atomic topos with a point . 13 4.2 The fundamental groupoid of an unpointed locally connected topos 15 5 Conclusion and future work 17 References 17 ∗e-mail: [email protected] 1 1 Introduction Toposes were first conceived ([2]) as kinds of “generalised spaces” which could serve as frameworks for cohomology theories; that is, mapping topological or geometrical invariants with an algebraic structure to topological spaces.
    [Show full text]
  • Picard Groupoids and $\Gamma $-Categories
    PICARD GROUPOIDS AND Γ-CATEGORIES AMIT SHARMA Abstract. In this paper we construct a symmetric monoidal closed model category of coherently commutative Picard groupoids. We construct another model category structure on the category of (small) permutative categories whose fibrant objects are (permutative) Picard groupoids. The main result is that the Segal’s nerve functor induces a Quillen equivalence between the two aforementioned model categories. Our main result implies the classical result that Picard groupoids model stable homotopy one-types. Contents 1. Introduction 2 2. The Setup 4 2.1. Review of Permutative categories 4 2.2. Review of Γ- categories 6 2.3. The model category structure of groupoids on Cat 7 3. Two model category structures on Perm 12 3.1. ThemodelcategorystructureofPermutativegroupoids 12 3.2. ThemodelcategoryofPicardgroupoids 15 4. The model category of coherently commutatve monoidal groupoids 20 4.1. The model category of coherently commutative monoidal groupoids 24 5. Coherently commutative Picard groupoids 27 6. The Quillen equivalences 30 7. Stable homotopy one-types 36 Appendix A. Some constructions on categories 40 AppendixB. Monoidalmodelcategories 42 Appendix C. Localization in model categories 43 Appendix D. Tranfer model structure on locally presentable categories 46 References 47 arXiv:2002.05811v2 [math.CT] 12 Mar 2020 Date: Dec. 14, 2019. 1 2 A. SHARMA 1. Introduction Picard groupoids are interesting objects both in topology and algebra. A major reason for interest in topology is because they classify stable homotopy 1-types which is a classical result appearing in various parts of the literature [JO12][Pat12][GK11]. The category of Picard groupoids is the archetype exam- ple of a 2-Abelian category, see [Dup08].
    [Show full text]
  • Zuoqin Wang Time: March 25, 2021 the QUOTIENT TOPOLOGY 1. The
    Topology (H) Lecture 6 Lecturer: Zuoqin Wang Time: March 25, 2021 THE QUOTIENT TOPOLOGY 1. The quotient topology { The quotient topology. Last time we introduced several abstract methods to construct topologies on ab- stract spaces (which is widely used in point-set topology and analysis). Today we will introduce another way to construct topological spaces: the quotient topology. In fact the quotient topology is not a brand new method to construct topology. It is merely a simple special case of the co-induced topology that we introduced last time. However, since it is very concrete and \visible", it is widely used in geometry and algebraic topology. Here is the definition: Definition 1.1 (The quotient topology). (1) Let (X; TX ) be a topological space, Y be a set, and p : X ! Y be a surjective map. The co-induced topology on Y induced by the map p is called the quotient topology on Y . In other words, −1 a set V ⊂ Y is open if and only if p (V ) is open in (X; TX ). (2) A continuous surjective map p :(X; TX ) ! (Y; TY ) is called a quotient map, and Y is called the quotient space of X if TY coincides with the quotient topology on Y induced by p. (3) Given a quotient map p, we call p−1(y) the fiber of p over the point y 2 Y . Note: by definition, the composition of two quotient maps is again a quotient map. Here is a typical way to construct quotient maps/quotient topology: Start with a topological space (X; TX ), and define an equivalent relation ∼ on X.
    [Show full text]
  • INTRODUCTION to ALGEBRAIC TOPOLOGY 1 Category And
    INTRODUCTION TO ALGEBRAIC TOPOLOGY (UPDATED June 2, 2020) SI LI AND YU QIU CONTENTS 1 Category and Functor 2 Fundamental Groupoid 3 Covering and fibration 4 Classification of covering 5 Limit and colimit 6 Seifert-van Kampen Theorem 7 A Convenient category of spaces 8 Group object and Loop space 9 Fiber homotopy and homotopy fiber 10 Exact Puppe sequence 11 Cofibration 12 CW complex 13 Whitehead Theorem and CW Approximation 14 Eilenberg-MacLane Space 15 Singular Homology 16 Exact homology sequence 17 Barycentric Subdivision and Excision 18 Cellular homology 19 Cohomology and Universal Coefficient Theorem 20 Hurewicz Theorem 21 Spectral sequence 22 Eilenberg-Zilber Theorem and Kunneth¨ formula 23 Cup and Cap product 24 Poincare´ duality 25 Lefschetz Fixed Point Theorem 1 1 CATEGORY AND FUNCTOR 1 CATEGORY AND FUNCTOR Category In category theory, we will encounter many presentations in terms of diagrams. Roughly speaking, a diagram is a collection of ‘objects’ denoted by A, B, C, X, Y, ··· , and ‘arrows‘ between them denoted by f , g, ··· , as in the examples f f1 A / B X / Y g g1 f2 h g2 C Z / W We will always have an operation ◦ to compose arrows. The diagram is called commutative if all the composite paths between two objects ultimately compose to give the same arrow. For the above examples, they are commutative if h = g ◦ f f2 ◦ f1 = g2 ◦ g1. Definition 1.1. A category C consists of 1◦. A class of objects: Obj(C) (a category is called small if its objects form a set). We will write both A 2 Obj(C) and A 2 C for an object A in C.
    [Show full text]
  • Classification of Compact 2-Manifolds
    Virginia Commonwealth University VCU Scholars Compass Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 2016 Classification of Compact 2-manifolds George H. Winslow Virginia Commonwealth University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarscompass.vcu.edu/etd Part of the Geometry and Topology Commons © The Author Downloaded from https://scholarscompass.vcu.edu/etd/4291 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at VCU Scholars Compass. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of VCU Scholars Compass. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Abstract Classification of Compact 2-manifolds George Winslow It is said that a topologist is a mathematician who can not tell the difference between a doughnut and a coffee cup. The surfaces of the two objects, viewed as topological spaces, are homeomorphic to each other, which is to say that they are topologically equivalent. In this thesis, we acknowledge some of the most well-known examples of surfaces: the sphere, the torus, and the projective plane. We then ob- serve that all surfaces are, in fact, homeomorphic to either the sphere, the torus, a connected sum of tori, a projective plane, or a connected sum of projective planes. Finally, we delve into algebraic topology to determine that the aforementioned sur- faces are not homeomorphic to one another, and thus we can place each surface into exactly one of these equivalence classes. Thesis Director: Dr. Marco Aldi Classification of Compact 2-manifolds by George Winslow Bachelor of Science University of Mary Washington Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Science in the Department of Mathematics Virginia Commonwealth University 2016 Dedication For Lily ii Abstract It is said that a topologist is a mathematician who can not tell the difference between a doughnut and a coffee cup.
    [Show full text]
  • Groupoids and Local Cartesian Closure
    Groupoids and local cartesian closure Erik Palmgren∗ Department of Mathematics, Uppsala University July 2, 2003 Abstract The 2-category of groupoids, functors and natural isomorphisms is shown to be locally cartesian closed in a weak sense of a pseudo- adjunction. Key words: groupoids, 2-categories, local cartesian closure. Mathematics Subject Classification 2000: 18B40, 18D05, 18A40. 1 Introduction A groupoid is a category in which each morphism is invertible. The notion may be considered as a common generalisation of the notions of group and equivalence relation. A group is a one-object groupoid. Every equivalence relation on a set, viewed as a directed graph, is a groupoid. A recent indepen- dence proof in logic used groupoids. Hofmann and Streicher [8] showed that groupoids arise from a construction in Martin-Löf type theory. This is the so-called identity type construction, which applied to a type gives a groupoid turning the type into a projective object, in the category of types with equiv- alence relations. As a consequence there are plenty of choice objects in this category: every object has a projective cover [12] — a property which seems essential for doing constructive mathematics according to Bishop [1] inter- nally to the category. For some time the groupoids associated with types were believed to be discrete. However, in [8] a model of type theory was given using fibrations over groupoids, showing that this need not be the case. The purpose of this article is to draw some further conclusions for group- oids from the idea of Hofmann and Streicher. Since type theory has a Π- construction, one could expect that some kind of (weak) local cartesian clo- sure should hold for groupoids.
    [Show full text]
  • When Is the Natural Map a a Cofibration? Í22a
    transactions of the american mathematical society Volume 273, Number 1, September 1982 WHEN IS THE NATURAL MAP A Í22A A COFIBRATION? BY L. GAUNCE LEWIS, JR. Abstract. It is shown that a map/: X — F(A, W) is a cofibration if its adjoint/: X A A -» W is a cofibration and X and A are locally equiconnected (LEC) based spaces with A compact and nontrivial. Thus, the suspension map r¡: X -» Ü1X is a cofibration if X is LEC. Also included is a new, simpler proof that C.W. complexes are LEC. Equivariant generalizations of these results are described. In answer to our title question, asked many years ago by John Moore, we show that 7j: X -> Í22A is a cofibration if A is locally equiconnected (LEC)—that is, the inclusion of the diagonal in A X X is a cofibration [2,3]. An equivariant extension of this result, applicable to actions by any compact Lie group and suspensions by an arbitrary finite-dimensional representation, is also given. Both of these results have important implications for stable homotopy theory where colimits over sequences of maps derived from r¡ appear unbiquitously (e.g., [1]). The force of our solution comes from the Dyer-Eilenberg adjunction theorem for LEC spaces [3] which implies that C.W. complexes are LEC. Via Corollary 2.4(b) below, this adjunction theorem also has some implications (exploited in [1]) for the geometry of the total spaces of the universal spherical fibrations of May [6]. We give a simpler, more conceptual proof of the Dyer-Eilenberg result which is equally applicable in the equivariant context and therefore gives force to our equivariant cofibration condition.
    [Show full text]
  • Stone-Cech Compactifications Via Adjunctions
    PROCEEDINGS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume St. April 1976 STONE-CECH COMPACTIFICATIONS VIA ADJUNCTIONS R. C. WALKER Abstract. The Stone-Cech compactification of a space X is described by adjoining to X continuous images of the Stone-tech growths of a comple- mentary pair of subspaces of X. The compactification of an example of Potoczny from [P] is described in detail. The Stone-Cech compactification of a completely regular space X is a compact Hausdorff space ßX in which X is dense and C*-embedded, i.e. every bounded real-valued mapping on X extends to ßX. Here we describe BX in terms of the Stone-Cech compactification of one or more subspaces by utilizing adjunctions and completely regular reflections. All spaces mentioned will be presumed to be completely regular. If A is a closed subspace of X and /maps A into Y, then the adjunction space X Of Y is the quotient space of the topological sum X © Y obtained by identifying each point of A with its image in Y. We modify this standard definition by allowing A to be an arbitrary subspace of X and by requiring / to be a C*-embedding of A into Y. The completely regular reflection of an arbitrary space y is a completely regular space pY which is a continuous image of Y and is such that any real- valued mapping on Y factors uniquely through p Y. The underlying set of p Y is obtained by identifying two points of Y if they are not separated by some real-valued mapping on Y.
    [Show full text]
  • Correspondences and Groupoids 1 Introduction
    Proceedings of the IX Fall Workshop on Geometry and Physics, Vilanova i la Geltr´u, 2000 Publicaciones de la RSME, vol. X, pp. 1–6. Correspondences and groupoids 1Marta Macho-Stadler and 2Moto O’uchi 1Departamento de Matem´aticas, Universidad del Pa´ıs Vasco-Euskal Herriko Unibertsitatea 2Department of Applied Mathematics, Osaka Women’s University emails: [email protected], [email protected] Abstract Our definition of correspondence between groupoids (which generali- zes the notion of homomorphism) is obtained by weakening the conditions in the definition of equivalence of groupoids in [5]. We prove that such a correspondence induces another one between the associated C*-algebras, and in some cases besides a Kasparov element. We wish to apply the results obtained in the particular case of K-oriented maps of leaf spaces in the sense of [3]. Key words: Groupoid, C*-algebra, correspondence, KK-group. MSC 2000: 46L80, 46L89 1Introduction A. Connes introduced in [1] the notion of correspondence in the theory of Von Neumann algebras. It is a concept of morphism, which gives the well known notion of correspondence of C*-algebras. In [5], P.S. Mulhy, J.N. Re- nault and D. Williams defined the notion of equivalence of groupoids and showed that if two groupoids are equivalent, then the associated C*-algebras are Morita-equivalent. But, this notion is too strong: here we give a definition of correspondence of groupoids,byweakening the conditions of equivalence in [5]. We prove that such a correspondence induces another one (in the sense of A. Connes) between the associated reduced C*-algebras.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Symmetric Cube of a Sphere
    transactions of the american mathematical society Volume 151, October 1970 ON THE SYMMETRIC CUBE OF A SPHERE BY JACK UCCI 1. Introduction. Let Xm denote the cartesian product Xx ■■ ■ x X (m factors) of the based space X. The full symmetric group S(m) acts on Xm by permutation homeomorphisms and the quotient space Xm/S(m) is defined to be the wi-fold symmetric product SPmX of X. Now let X=Sn, the «-sphere. A map/: SPmSn -* Sn is of type r if the composite Sn —U SPmSn -+-+ Sn has degree r. Here /(x) = [x, e,..., e] where e is the basepoint of 5". For given n and m an elementary result of James asserts that the set of all "realizable types" is an ideal (km,n)^Z in the ring of integers—whence the problem of determining the generator km,n. The main results of [1] and [6] determine k2-n: Theorem 1.1. (i) k2-2i= 0; (ii) &2,2(+ i_2«>(2¡) wnere c,(¿) ¡s the number of integers 0<a^b with a = 0, 1,2 or 4 mod 8. In [7] we obtained a lower bound for km,n for all m. Our main result in this paper asserts that this lower bound is best possible when m = 3, i.e. k3-" is determined as follows: Theorem 1.2. (i) ka-2t = 0; (ii) k3-2t+ 1 = 2«'i2n-3K 1.2(i) is of course a simple consequence of l.l(i). Moreover the main result of [7] implies that 2«'(2í)-3í|£3'2t+ 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Metrizability of Adjunction Spaces
    METRIZABILITY OF ADJUNCTION SPACES CARLOS J. R. BORGES1 In a recent conversation with E. A. Michael and D. Hyman the following natural question was raised: Are the Af-spaces of Hyman (see Definition 3.1) metrizable whenever they are first countable? We will answer this question affirmatively. Indeed, we will prove the somewhat stronger result that the Tkf-spaces of Hyman are metrizable whenever they are of pointwise countable type (see Definition 1.1 and ensuing paragraph). It turns out that to answer the preceding question the major diffi- culty involves the metrizability of adjunction spaces. All our spaces are assumed to be Pi. 1. Preliminary analysis. Definition 1.1 (Arhangel'skii). A topological space X is said to be of pointwise countable type if each point pEX is contained in a compact subset Cv of X of countable character (i.e. Cp has a countable neighborhood base in X). Clearly all first countable spaces are of pointwise countable type. Furthermore, the p-spaces of Arhangel'skii (hence, the topologically complete spaces in the sense of Cech) are also of pointwise countable type (see Theorem 9 and the corollary to Theorem 8 in [l]). Finally, Arhangel'skii has proved that, in the presence of paracompactness, the r-spaces of Michael [7] are equivalent to the g-spaces of Michael [6] as well as to the spaces of pointwise countable type (see the first paragraph of §3 of [7]). Our work in §§2 and 3 will depend heavily on the following result, which is essentially due to Arhangel'skii [2]. Proposition 1.2.
    [Show full text]