Ludwik Fleck and the Art-Of-Fact

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Ludwik Fleck and the Art-Of-Fact 168 Evolutionary Anthropology CROTCHETS & QUIDDITIES Ludwik Fleck and the Art-of-Fact KENNETH WEISS Truth may be beauty, but more in the eye of the beholder than we generally with biological evolution: science acknowledge. Does it matter? works by contingently sorting through available facts or ideas in the context of their own time, but cannot really be In science we routinely assume that bursts of change by which we so often, teleologically heading for truth, be- whatever theory we may have about perhaps so vainly, characterize our cause we have no way to know where them, facts themselves are things that own research or field. Kuhn argued to find it. are—out there in the world to be ob- that a scientific revolution occurs Kuhn was influenced by a little- served. However, it has become rather when a new explanation for the avail- known 1935 book he had stumbled standard for historians and philoso- able data becomes accepted by the across, Genesis and Development of a phers to assert instead that “facts” are body of scientists, a sociocultural phe- Scientific Fact, by a Polish physician human constructs understandable nomenon very different from the pre- named Ludwik Fleck.4 Fleck had antic- only in a particular historical or soci- vailing notion of science as a fact- ipated (or shaped) many of Kuhn’s etal context. They note that scientists driven process. The notion has been ideas. Though rather obscure today, typically argue over very different the- applied, but not without discussion, to Fleck has been called the founder of the ories to interpret the same data. We in all fields of endeavor including an- philosophy of modern medicine. His turn resist this deconstruction by out- thropology.2,3 concern was not so much with revolu- siders who themselves don’t have to A new theory may be more accurate tions but with the way that even the face the struggles of understanding in some ways, or account for more supposed facts of science are driven by Nature. Nonetheless, there may have facts, but Kuhn’s notion of a paradigm context. He stresses that “concepts are been more than idle poetry in Keats’ shift was not about contests between not spontaneously created but are de- assertion that “truth is beauty and different ways to apply an existing termined by their ‘ancestors’.” Fleck’s that is all ye need to know.” Facts may theory, like that of evolution, to the term comparable to Kuhn’s “paradigm” be more determined by the theoretical available facts, such as fights between was thought collective (we might say lenses through which we view the cladists and phenetic systematists, or “school of thought”) and his objective world than we like to think. out-of-Africa versus regional continu- was to understand how an unorches- ity models of evolution. Rather, a par- trated community of scientists estab- lishes what are considered facts around TRUTH AND PROGRESS IN adigm shift is a gestalt change in which a new interpretation of the a theory that necessarily grows out of SCIENCE: “THE BONDS OF body of existing facts replaces, and is historical roots. What counts as fact HISTORY CAN NEVER BE CUT” incommensurable with, an existing varies with time and context. Fleck lik- Thomas Kuhn’s famous book The theory. Evolution contrasts with cre- ens science to troops on the march, a Structure of Scientific Revolutions1 ationism in this respect, for example. small vanguard followed by a main had a transforming effect across both Most scientists strongly assert—be- body. New observations provide some the academic and popular culture lieve—that such changes constitute corrective, but which of the vanguards landscapes. It gave us the satisfying progress in the sense of major steps the main troops follow is unpredictable, term “paradigm shift” for the episodic closer to understanding the truth that and affected—or determined—by so- we assume is out there to be found. ciopolitical and cultural factors. However, it is perhaps not sufficiently This challenges our cherished my- appreciated that scientific theories are thology that we are doing “original” almost always inconsistent even with research. Most of us are not as origi- Kenneth Weiss is Evan Pugh Professor of some of the established facts of their nal nor independent as we may fancy. Anthropology and Genetics at Penn State University. time, and this was true of the victors Without a herdlike ideological coher- in classical Kuhnian “revolutions,” in- ence, science as the public enterprise cluding even the archetypal Coperni- we know today might not be possible, Evolutionary Anthropology 12:168–172 (2003) can one. Whether this is progress to- since any individual can only see or do DOI 10.1002/evan.10118 Published online in Wiley InterScience ward truth is harder to answer than so much. But the herd itself defines (www.interscience.wiley.com). we may think. Kuhn drew an analogy what progress is, and the more who CROTCHETS & QUIDDITIES Evolutionary Anthropology 169 als, and other diseases such as leprosy also generated a positive test reactions as well as similar symptoms. Under these conditions, whether it was a “fact” that someone had syphilis or not was not purely objective but de- pended on the assumptions about its particular cause. Many investigators— the “thought collective”—worked, if only in a loosely coordinated way, to find a syphilis blood test. In 1906, Au- gust von Wassermann and colleagues developed the famous reaction that bore his name. On the assumption that the test directly detected bacterial anti- gens, a positive Wassermann reaction Figure 1. A. Thomas Kuhn (http://www.malaspina.com/site/person_733.asp); B. Ludwik Fleck (reprinted with permission, from Polish Philosophy web site: http://www.fmag.unict.it/PolPhil/ was used to define syphilis, separating it Fleck/Fleck.html). by this single criterion from other dis- eases with similar symptoms. Despite these elements of what seemed like “truth,” the inferences participate the stronger and more re- ON BECOMING FACT: THE from experiments leading to the Was- sistant to displacement (creative or WASSERMANN TEST FOR sermann test were incorrect or purely free thinking) it becomes, and the pre- SYPHILIS empirical in essential ways. The theo- vailing thought collective becomes a retical understanding of the reaction thought constraint. “Whole eras” can The predominant medical problem was in fact wrong. A positive reaction be ruled by a thought constraint. Her- of the time was infectious disease, and was interpreted as proving spirochete etics are not well tolerated; we don’t Fleck exemplified his ideas by show- causation because the theory was that burn them at the stake but the Ly- ing how concepts of syphilis, growing antigen-antibody reactions were spe- senko era showed that we may send from earlier notions of causation, led cific. The method to detect the pres- them to freeze to death in labor to the development of the Wasser- ence of antigen produced by the spi- camps, and today we freeze them out mann test to detect the disease. Syph- rochete is known as complement of research funds. As with any ideol- ilis had long been viewed primarily in fixation (Figure 2). In the first step, ogy, defendants of the thought collec- moral dimensions, a “carnal scourge.” syphilitic tissue used as a source of tive argue that they defend it because In part a legacy of the age-old humeral antigen was mixed with blood from theory, diseases of generalized or it’s true. the person being tested. In an infected vague symptomatology were assumed Ludwik Fleck worked in the pre- person, the antigen binds to antibody, to be due to fouling of the blood. This World War II era in his native Poland. and complement (a component of the notion grew to the point that the early Poland was intimately involved in immune system) is fixed to the anti- 20th Century demanded a “blood test” conflicts in that region, including the gen-antibody complex. A properly to detect the disease. Infectious mi- Communist revolution in neighboring prepared reagent, like red blood cells croorganisms were known by then, Russia. Social, historical, evolution- (rbc’s), is then added. This causes no and Pasteur had recently organized ary, and contextual analysis of human reaction in samples from infected per- (and orchestrated) the scientific and affairs was part of the intellectual life sons that at this state no longer con- bureaucratic machinery in France tain free complement, but the un- of that era in Europe. Fleck’s choice of around the concept of infectious dis- bound complement in the blood of an the term “thought collective” seems to ease causation.5 European nations uninfected person binds to the rbc’s, reflect that context, and he states a scrambled not to be left scientifically producing an easily detected hemo- rather classically Hegelian or Marxist behind in this endeavor. However, lytic reaction. assessment of conflict in science, as symptoms, specificity, and sensitivity Much of Fleck’s book is an account being between opposed theoretical of known reactions and available tests of the many ways this process was a views that resolve into a new consen- made both the disease and its diagno- prisoner of its history and the sus. Fleck says that “after the change sis problematic. Symptoms of syphilis thought-collective’s erroneous choice in thought style, the earlier problem is were not coincident with the visual of assumptions: “It is only after the no longer completely comprehensi- (microscopically detectable) presence choice has been made that the associ- ble.” This contrasts a bit with Kuhn’s of the spirochete bacterium Trepo- ations produced by it are seen as nec- idea, because a problem is not identi- nema pallidum, though people were essary.” I can’t give the details here, cal to an explanatory framework.
Recommended publications
  • Download Download
    Ethics in Progress (ISSN 2084-9257). Vol. 11 (2020). No. 1, Art. #1, pp. 4-19. DOI:10.14746/eip.2020.1.1 Typhus in Buchenwald: Can the Story Be Told? Ilana Löwy (CERMES; Paris; [email protected]) ORCID: 0000-0001-6963-0578 Fleck in Buchenwald In a 1948 Ludwik Fleck published an article “On experiments on human beings” which discussed the regulation of such experiments (Fleck 1948, 1052-1054). He pu- blished this text shortly after testifying at the Nuremberg trial about experiments which involved deliberate infection of healthy people with typhus (Flecks’ testimony at the knowledge of German war research on this disease. He spent the last part of World War I.G. Farben trial in Nuremberg, February 12, 1948/2007). Fleck himself has a first-hand II in Block 50 in the Buchenwald camp, where he and other prisoners produced a typhus vaccine for the German army. Block 50 was in the immediate vicinity of the infamous block 46, where Nazi doctors – the same who were responsible for the vaccine produc- tion – conducted experiments on human beings. “Experiments” may be an inaccurate word. Buchenwald was a criminal endeavor of a criminal state in an insane world whe- re no normal rules applied. The so-called “medical experiments” conducted in Block 46 had very distant relation to medical research, and very strong links with mass murder. On the other hand, the insane world of the concentration camp contained ele- ments which linked it to a more “conventional” science. Nazi doctors who conduc- ted barbarous experiments on prisoners aspired to a conventional professional ca- employed absolutely unacceptable means (read, assassination), but might have still reer.
    [Show full text]
  • Conventions, Styles of Thinking and Relativism
    S t udia Philosophica Wratislaviensia Supplementary Volume, English Edition 2012 KRZYSZTOF SZLACHCIC University of Wrocław Conventions, Styles of Thinking and Relativism. Some Remarks on the Dispute between I. Dąmbska and L. Fleck* Abstract My comments are focused on the debate between Izydora Dąmbska and Ludwik Fleck. In the course of their debate, which took place in the 1930’s, they discussed some basic issues of epistemology, focusing on the problems of the sources of scientific knowledge, objectivity of knowledge, and truth. The aim of the paper is to place their debate in a the historical context and to demonstrate the novelty of Fleck’s arguments, especially in comparison with Thomas S. Kuhn’s later contribution. I also examine the dominant interpretations of Fleck’s theory of knowledge, as well as the reasons for which his philosophical ideas, especially Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache (1935) have fallen into the philosophical obliv- ion. I argue that Fleck’s views, although innovative, were less radical than it is commonly thought. My comments focus on the polemic that ensued in the 1930s between Izydora Dąmbska and Ludwik Fleck. The authors involved in it either directly or indirectly referred to the fundamental questions of the theory of cognition: the question of the sources of scientific knowledge, objectivity of knowledge (its communicabil- ity), relative nature of scientific knowledge, truth. The small total volume of texts which directly referred to the views of the adversaries as well as the place where the dispute occurred (Lvov, a geographically peripheral part of the “civilised world” at the time) could suggest that this was just a minor episode in the history of thought, not worth mentioning.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ideas of Ludwik Fleck and Their Application to the Eukaryotic Cell
    The Ideas of Ludwik Fleck and Their Application to the Eukaryotic Cell Cycle, the Restriction Point, and G1-phase Control Stephen Cooper Department of Microbiology and Immunology, University of Michigan Medical School Ann Arbor Michigan 48109-0620 e-mail: [email protected] Abstract The ideas of Ludwik Fleck (1896-1961) analyzing the conservative nature of scientific ideas are discussed and applied to the proposed G1-phase restriction point as a regulatory element of the mammalian cell cycle. Fleck proposed that ideas become fixed and difficult to change because criticisms of current and dominant models are either ignored or turned to support of the current model. The idea of a thought-collective leading to the stability of ideas is a central theme of the ideas of Ludwik Fleck. 1 Evidence conforms to conceptions just as often as conceptions conform to evidence. Ludwik Fleck, 1935 Introduction The continuum model of eukaryotic cell-cycle control is now almost 25 years old (1,2). This alternative view was actually generated a number of years earlier based on studies of the bacterial cell cycle (3). Since its first proposal, the continuum model has not made much headway against what may be called the G1-phase control model of the cell cycle, a model that is current, dominant, and accepted by a broad consensus of researchers in the field of eukaryotic cell-cycle studies. It is important to understand how the G1-phase control model has remained so dominant despite the success of the alternative continuum model view of the cell cycle in explaining myriad published experimental results on the cell cycle.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Sociologies of Knowledge. L. Fleck—T
    Stefan Symotiuk (Lublin) TWO SOCIOLOGIES OF KNOWLEDGE. L. FLECK — T. BILIKIEWICZ CONTROVERSY Tadeusz Bilikiewicz, a scholar now somewhat forgotten, was in the 1930s active as an sociologist of knowledge. In 1931 he published a book entitled Jan Jonston, 1603—1677, Żywot i działalność lekarska (His Life and Medical Activity), Warsaw 1931, and a year later Die Embryologie im Zeitalter des Barock und des Rococo, Leipzig 1932. He was also author of many articles, still to be properly investigated. His theory of knowledge he himself called 'perspectivism'. In the Summer issue of the journal 'Przegląd Współczesny' of 1939, an argument was published between Fleck and Bilikiewicz which was overlooked by those concerned because of the outbreak of war, and which has not been taken note of by the bibliographies of Fleck's work. Yet this is an extremely interesting polemic, considering that Bilikie- wicz was an exponent of 'the naive epistemology' seeing the relation between subject and object as being of a 'reflective' nature and accepting only the 'heuristic' influence of environment upon science. He flatly rejected Fleck's conceptions describing it as subjective idealism, agno- sticism, relativism. My intention here is to recall briefly that polemic. I. THE CIRCUMSTANCES OF THE DISPUTE L. Fleck began to be interested in epistemology soon after his stay in Vienna when he published his Zur Krise der 'Wirklichkeit'i. Still he main phase of his work was in 1935 when his book appeared together 1 'Die Naturwissenschaften' Vol. 17:1929, 23, p. 425—430. 570 S. Symotiuk with a series of articles in Polish and foreign journals.
    [Show full text]
  • Ludwik Fleck And His 'Thought Collectives'
    Ludwik Fleck and His 'Thought Collectives' 11–14 April 2019 Program Venue: Center for Urban History of East Central Europe The workshop Ludwik Fleck and His 'Thought Collectives' aims at bringing together a person and the city/places/spaces, Ludwik Fleck (1896-1961) and Lviv where he was born, studied, worked, debated, contemplated, and wrote his philosophical and medical texts. It is focusing on the philosophic legacy of Fleck and on the historical context that generated his ideas. Workshop participants explore in details the social landscape of the interwar Lviv where different ethnic, linguistic, and religious groups co-existed and co-created; where various art communities and scientific collectives worked together. They trace changes and adaptations of his legacy in various disciplines and geographies. This scientific meeting will actualize the legacy of Ludwik Fleck, and open opportunities for its further application in the academic and extra-academic contexts. Organization: Heidelberg Academy of Sciences and Humanities Center for Urban History of East Central Europe Ukrainian Catholic University Support: Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft Collegium Helveticum / Ludwik-Fleck-Zentrum, Zürich Support of public program: The Institute for Human Sciences (IWM, Vienna) Lviv City Council Thursday, From 17:00 Arrival to the Center for Urban History of East Central Europe 1 April 11, 2019 Registration & Welcoming round From 19:00 Reception Friday, 9:00-9:30 Opening ceremony April 12, 2019 9:30-11:30 Panel 1. Cultural and Intellectual Milieus
    [Show full text]
  • LD5655.V855 1993.C655.Pdf (11.60Mb)
    SCIENTIFIC DISCOURSE, SOCIOLOGICALT HEORY, AND THE STRUCTURE OF RHETORIC by James H. Collier Thesis submitted to the Faculty of the Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF SCIENCE in Science and Technology Studies APPROVED: Y— Joseph C. Pitt, Chair Aone ble EtaaT hone, Steve Fuller Elisworth Fuhrman April, 1993 Blacksburg, VA LD S635 VE5S , DaQa cose} aM’~ Scientific Discourse, Sociological Theory, and the Structure of Rhetoric James H. Collier Graduate Program in Science and Technology Studies Chair: Joseph C. Pitt (ABSTRACT) This thesis examines the rhetorical, analytical and critical efficacy of reflexivity and sociological theory as means for reconciling the normative and descriptive functions of the rhetoric of science. In attempting to define a separate research domain within Science Studies, rhetoric of science has borrowed Strong Program and constructivist principles and descriptions of scientific practice from the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge (SSK) as a basis for analyzing scientific discourse. While epistemological claims in the social sciences have been considered inherently self-referential and subject to reflexive analysis and critique, rhetoricians have generally taken these claims on face value and applied them to a treatment of scientific practice. Accordingly, rhetoricians have maintained a natural ontological attitude to sociological theories and descriptions supporting an understanding of scientific discourse as implicitly rhetorical. Recently, however, the concept of "rhetoric" in rhetoric of science has come under scrutiny. This thesis will connect arguments involving the relation of the "irreducibly social" nature of science, to a concept of scientific discourse as rhetorical "without remainder,” to the philosophical commitments of reflexive analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • Re-Thinking Ludwik Fleck's Concept of The
    1 How archaeological communities think: re-thinking Ludwik Fleck’s concept of the thought-collective according to the case of Serbian archaeology Monika Milosavljevi´c Both thinking and facts are changeable, if only because changes in think- ing manifest themselves in changed facts. Conversely, fundamentally new facts can be discovered only through new thinking. (Fleck, 1981: 50–51; translated by Fred Bradley and Thaddeus J. Trenn). Introduction Serbian archaeology offers fertile ground in which to apply Fleck’s con- cepts of thought-collectives and thought-style.1 To this end, this chapter seeks to delve into Fleck’s theories on knowledge production to study how they function in practice in the history of archaeology, as based on empirical data consisting of various texts and citation relations that are used to track a particular thought-collective in a clearer, more visual manner. In doing this, a further aim of this chapter is to introduce new theoretical tools for the history of ideas as well as how they may be implemented as inherent to specific methodological strategies. Kuhn’s concept of a paradigm is limited in its applications since its broad expanse proves too unwieldy to apply to all aspects of a localised phenomenon. Paradigm shift is an appropriate term to describe significant changes that encompass totalities, but not for analysing the specifics of one non-generalised change (Kuhn, 1970). As a matter of consequence, in order to take an initial step into researching the history of localised ideas (such as the history of archaeology), it is necessary to find an approach adequate to understanding the sociology of knowl- edge production and archaeological epistemology.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    Transversal: International Journal for the Historiography of Science, 1 (2016) 3 1-45 ISSN 2526 -2270 www.historiographyofscience.org © The Author 2016 — This is an open access article Dossier Ludwik Flec k Tadeusz Bilikiewicz’s Background in the debate with Ludwik Fleck Artur Koterski 1 Abstract: One of the factors that adversely influenced the worldwide reception of Fleck was the rather narrow critical interest that his ideas had aroused in Poland. Apart from a few reviews of his book (1935), only two polemics were published before WWII, and these likewise fell into oblivion. The philosophical views of one of those polemists, Tadeusz Bilikiewicz, shared the same fate. Since an acquaintance with Bilikiewicz’s background 31 would seem to be a necessary condition for a (full) understanding of his controversy with Fleck, the aim of this paper is to sketch his views on the history and sociology of science, and to clarify certain errors regarding the facts of his life. Keywords: Tadeusz Bilikiewicz; history of medicine; sociology of science; realism; constructivism Received: 30 August 2016. Accepted: 30 October 2016. ____________________________________________________________________________________ Introduction Bilikiewicz is mainly remembered by his psychiatry students, and a fairly narrow group of medical historians and philosophers — predominantly Fleck scholars — for a dispute with Ludwik Fleck, which began in 1939, following Fleck’s critical remarks on Bilikiewicz’s approach to history. As his polemics with Fleck attracted attention, his contribution has been invariably used as a pretext to scrutinize and explain Fleck’s views. Accordingly, Bilikiewicz’s position, as formulated in his book on the history of embryology (1932), and his numerous papers from the 1930s, have been ignored and remain virtually unknown.
    [Show full text]
  • Historyka T 48-18.Indd
    HISTORYKA. Studia Metodologiczne T. 48, 2018 PL ISSN 0073-277X DOI 10.24425/hsm.2018.125792 s. 483–489 VERENA BUNKUS Gotha Research Centre of the University of Erfurt CHRISTOPH MAISCH European University Viadrina “POLITICAL EPISTEMOLOGIES OF EASTERN EUROPE”. REPORT ON INTERNATIONAL WORKSHOP (ERFURT, 24–25.11.2017) The conference on Political Epistemologies of Eastern Europe1, which took place in November 2017 in Erfurt, inaugurated a broadly conceived program on the investigation of Eastern and Central Europe. Political epistemology, an approach originating from historical epistemology and investigating different epistemological lines in their political entanglements, should bring forward the so far unnoticed or marginally noticed approaches from the history of sci- ence originating in the region. With further events already planned (confer- ence “Soviet States and Beyond: Political Epistemologies of/and Marxism 1917–1945–1968” in Moscow in June 2018 and conference “A New Culture of Truth? On the Transformation of Political Epistemologies since the 1960s” in Erfurt in October 2018), the program of investigation of political epistemolo- gies should move beyond Eastern and Central Europe and aim also at a com- 1 Political Epistemologies of Eastern Europe, Kleine Synagoge Erfurt / Max-Weber-Kolleg, University of Erfurt, 24.11.2017–25.11.2017. Organized by Friedrich Cain (University of Er- furt, Max Weber Center for Advanced Cultural and Social Studies), Dietlind Hüchtker (Leibniz Institute for the History and Culture of Eastern Europe, GWZO, Leipzig), Bernhard Kleeberg (University of Erfurt, Max Weber Center for Advanced Cultural and Social Studies), and Jan Surman (IGITI Higher School of Economics, Moscow / IFK Vienna, Kunstuniversität Linz).
    [Show full text]
  • Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact Edited by Thaddeus J
    Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact Edited by Thaddeus J. Trenn Genesis and and Robert K. Merton ii 'I Translated by Fred Bradley ·1 Development of a •I and Thaddeus J. Trenn :! Scientific Fact Foreword by Thomas S. Kuhn Ludwik Fleck The University of Chicago Press Chicago and London Originally published as Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache: Einfiihrung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollektiv, © 1935 by Benno Schwabe & Co., Basel, Switzerland. Contents The University of Chicago Press, Chicago 60637 The University of Chicago Press, Ltd., London © 1979 by The University of Chicago All rights reserved. Published 1979 Paperback edition 1981 Printed in the United States of America Foreword Vil 19 18 17 16 15 14 13 12 11 10 12 13 14 15 16 Preface xiii ISBN-13: 978-0-226-25325-1 ISBN-10: 0-226-25325-2 Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Overview of Contents xxiii Fleck, Ludwik. Prologue xxvii Genesis and development of a scientific fact. One How the Modern Concept of Syphilis Originated Translation of Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache. Two Epistemological Conclusions from the Bibliography: p. Established History of a Concept 20 Includes index. Three The Wassermann Reaction and 1. Science-Social aspects. 2. Science-Philosophy. Its Discovery 53 3. Syphilis-Diagnosis-Wassermann reaction. 4. Knowledge, Sociology of. I. Title. Four Epistemological Considerations Concerning Ql 75.5.F5913 507' .2 79-12521 the History of the
    [Show full text]
  • Ludwik Fleck: a Message to Start a New Discourse Ewa Solska
    Curr. Issues Pharm. Med. Sci., Vol. 28, No. 1, Pages 60-62 Current Issues in Pharmacy and Medical Sciences Formerly ANNALES UNIVERSITATIS MARIAE CURIE-SKLODOWSKA, SECTIO DDD, PHARMACIA journal homepage: http://www.curipms.umlub.pl/ Ludwik Fleck: a message to start a new discourse Ewa Solska Department of the Methodology of History, Institute of History, Maria Curie-Skłodowska University in Lublin, Poland ARTICLE INFO ABSTRACT Received 16 March 2015 The goal of the present article is to initiate a series of papers on Ludwik Fleck’s theories of Accepted 26 March 2015 medical cognition and their contribution to contemporary research on science. I would like, however, to begin with the last statement, in which he signaled, almost half a century Keywords: ahead of time, the current issues concerning scientific discourse in the socio-cultural Ludwik Fleck, dimension. theory of science, sociology of knowledge, thought styles, human dimension. INTRODUCTION This year marks the 70th anniversary of Ludwik Fleck’s the circle of his associates, which would be the foundation invitation to become Head of the Department of Medical for developing the sociological aspect of a new theory of Microbiology at the then UMCS [Maria Curie-Skłodowska science, which he continued to carry on during the whole University] Medical Faculty. Ludwik Fleck is a scholar who of his time in Lublin (1945-52) [1]. is well-known in the world as a philosopher of science and a pioneer of the sociology of knowledge. From the stand- point of history of medicine, it is impossible to disregard the importance of his work as a physician and microbiologist.
    [Show full text]
  • Finding Doctor Fleck Essay Presented Before the Chit Chat Club on September 10, 2019 Michael Thaler
    Finding Doctor Fleck Essay presented before the Chit Chat Club on September 10, 2019 Michael Thaler Some 40 years ago, I sat in my lab at the University of California in San Francisco thumbing through that week’s issue of the journal Science. As it happened, that esteemed publication reported on my research using pregnant rats with an inherited defect which made them jaundiced and brain-damaged. The idea was to study the effect of an abnormal maternal environment on the development of the affected metabolic pathway in the normal and genetically defective fetuses in the litter. The journal’s reviewers saw my experimental design as an “elegant” application of an “experiment of nature” (a pathological mutant) for the investigation of intrauterine development. The reviewers also noted that an additional advantage of the approach was that a parallel experiment using the normal strain of rats provided a perfect control. Best of all, I thought, was that the experiment had produced a clear-cut result. I had no doubt that the data proved a “fact” that existed in the “real” world, but I had a lingering reservation about whether a fetus gestating in an “abnormal” mother could be considered as entirely “normal”. Perhaps because I was thinking about the validity of the conclusions that I derived from my experiment, my eye fell on the title of a recently published monograph, “The Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact”. Normally, I would have had zero interest in what seemed like a grandiose and misguided philosophical dissertation on a self-evident truth that had nothing to do with science.
    [Show full text]