Hume and Human Error Mark Andrew Hooper BA (Hons)

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Hume and Human Error Mark Andrew Hooper BA (Hons) Hume and Human Error Mark Andrew Hooper BA (Hons) A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy at The University of Queensland in 2014 School of History, Philosophy, Religion & Classics i Abstract This work is entitled Hume and Human Error. My hope is that it may be of interest to at least two groups of readers: first, to those who are interested in understanding the philosophy of David Hume himself, and second, to those who are interested in explaining the human mind and our propensity to go wrong. My primary objective is to explain how Hume can account, or does account, for human error. In this sense, I am concerned with exposition, and exposition of a rather neglected section of an otherwise comprehensive body of Hume scholarship. There is a rich philosophical history of attempts to understand and provide solutions to the problems of error. Within this tradition, Hume’s account of error is particularly interesting because it should be understood in the context of his general strategy to completely redraft traditional concepts (e.g. substance, causation, self, power) in a way that does not rely on any metaphysical assumptions that cannot be justified by experience. Hume’s method, I argue, leads him to reject what I call the “common sense” or “correspondence” theory of error, according to which what it means to have a false belief (for example) is to have a belief that does not properly represent mind-independent facts about an external world. Exactly how, and in what sense, Hume rejects the correspondence theory is quite complicated, and touches on many of the issues at the heart of the New Hume Debate. With this debate in mind, I argue that Hume has a general strategy of redrafting traditional concepts in a way that does not rely on the existence of external objects, and that Hume’s Theory of Error should be understood in accordance with this general strategy. This is not to say that Hume denies that we can speak meaningfully about external objects, nor that he denies the existence of external objects. Rather, I argue that Hume’s Theory of Error should be understood along the same lines as his rejection of the traditional account of substance as substrata. I note, for example, that when Hume rejects the traditional conception of substance it is not because he flat-out denies the possibility that a substratum may exist. In fact, he thinks that we cannot help but believe that external objects exist. Rather, Hume denies the traditional account of substance on the grounds that we never perceive any such thing as a substratum1, and he infers from this conclusion that we must not ordinarily mean by “substance” what the metaphysicians had thought we mean2. But Hume does not stop there. He then goes on to provide an alternative theory of substance3 – one that is explained in terms of perceptions and the relations between them, and one that does not rely on the existence of a substratum. Hume’s theory of error should be understood with this same methodology in mind. First, he rejects the traditional correspondence theory of error on the grounds that we cannot perceive any relationship between perceptions and external objects. This does not mean that he must also deny the existence of external objects, or 1 “We have no idea of substance distinct from a collection of particular qualities…” (T, 16) 2 “…nor have we any other meaning when we talk or reasoning concerning it.” (T, 16) 3 “The idea of substance as well as that of a mode, is nothing but a collection of simple ideas, that are united by the imagination, and have a particular name assigned them, but which we are able to recall, either to ourselves of others, that collection.” (T, 16) ii the possibility of a relationship between perceptions and external objects. It is only the sceptical conclusion that since we do not perceive any such thing, there is no rational argument to make a case either way. But this sceptical conclusion is by no means the end of Hume’s story about error. Hume also proposes a positive theory about error – one that he explains in terms of his naturalistic science of man, and one that he intends to replace the traditional conception that he rejects. With this framework established, the remainder of the thesis then goes on to explore the interesting and difficult issues that arise in the attempt to put forward such a theory. This leads us to consider a series of related and under-explored issues in Hume scholarship, including Hume’s treatment of physiology, his account of normativity in natural belief, his idea of the self as created by the passions, and his conception of certainty. Exploring Hume’s conception of human error allows us to see all of these separate accounts as unified in a different way that has seldom been explored. As a result of Hume’s novel methodology, many difficult questions arise with regard to providing an account of error. Here are just a few: If Hume’s theory of error does not rely on the existence of external objects, how can he explain what it means to be fooled by an optical illusion? Surely when we call something an “illusion” what we mean is that the way things seem is different from the way things are. How can Hume help himself to this sort of distinction? Why, if Hume thinks that perceptions are all we can know, does he appeal to physiology as a means to explain how errors of association arise? Given that Hume rejects the traditional conception of the self, how can he possibly explain the activity and agency involved in error? Errors don’t simply occur; errors are made by agents who could and should have done otherwise. In other words, we think of error as a normative notion. If Hume rejects the idea of the self as an active and unified substance, how can he account for the agency without which an explanation of error would appear impossible? Does Hume think that any if our beliefs are immune to error? Are we certain of anything? At some points he suggests that relations of ideas (for example simple mathematical truths) are absolutely certain, but at other times he says that all knowledge resolves into mere probability. By examining Hume’s own body of work, and by discussing this work in the context of the tradition to which Hume responds, I attempt to resolve all of these questions, and others. Of course, there are many different kinds of errors, and I do not attempt to provide an account of all of them. I do, however, strive to provide a sort of general framework by which all errors, on Hume’s view, might be explained. iii Ultimately, for all its difficulties, I argue that Hume can indeed provide a very rich and fruitful account of error in his own naturalistic terms. According to this account, error must always be explained in terms of the features of perceptions themselves and the relations between them. If we want to know what any particular error involves, we must ask about the observable conditions that tend to accompany those errors, or how those errors “strike the mind”. Hume’s is a naturalistic theory of error which, like that of the Epicureans, locates error at the level of judgement rather than immediate sensation. But unlike the Epicurean tradition, Hume’s conception of judgment is not explained as the function of a free will or even as the product of an independent mental faculty, but rather as the outcome of the naturally occurring laws that govern perceptions. The pressure to avoid error is also naturalised – it comes from the tendency of creatures like us to avoid the cognitive dissonance that arises from incoherence or contradiction. For those who want a more robust or absolute sense of error, Hume’s account may well prove unsatisfying, but Hume’s is one of the earliest attempts to demystify error – to rid it of metaphysical assumptions – and so it is interesting and important for that reason, if for no other. iv Declaration by author This thesis is composed of my original work, and contains no material previously published or written by another person except where due reference has been made in the text. I have clearly stated the contribution by others to jointly-authored works that I have included in my thesis. I have clearly stated the contribution of others to my thesis as a whole, including statistical assistance, survey design, data analysis, significant technical procedures, professional editorial advice, and any other original research work used or reported in my thesis. The content of my thesis is the result of work I have carried out since the commencement of my research higher degree candidature and does not include a substantial part of work that has been submitted to qualify for the award of any other degree or diploma in any university or other tertiary institution. I have clearly stated which parts of my thesis, if any, have been submitted to qualify for another award. I acknowledge that an electronic copy of my thesis must be lodged with the University Library and, subject to the General Award Rules of The University of Queensland, immediately made available for research and study in accordance with the Copyright Act 1968. I acknowledge that copyright of all material contained in my thesis resides with the copyright holder(s) of that material. Where appropriate I have obtained copyright permission from the copyright holder to reproduce material in this thesis.
Recommended publications
  • Promoting a New Synthesis of Fa Ith and Reason
    March • April 2008 • Volume 40 • Number 2 Body and Soul – Rediscovering Catholic Orthodoxy AND SYNTHESIS NEW PROMOTING A Editorial Aquinas on the Subsistent Soul Kevin Flannery The Soul: Aquinas contra some Thomists et al REASON Francis Selman The Goodness of the Human Body Jeffrey Kirby OF Our regular features Diagnosis The soul and Pullman’s influence: The Truth Will Set You Free FAITH FAITH Shared shock at episcopal teaching: Comment on the Comments Prospects for heterodoxy: Notes from across the Atlantic Debate The value of discussing God and the soul: Road from Regensburg The nature of science: Cutting Edge Letting go of catholicity at a Catholic hospital: Other Angles Also Price: £4 Reviewing Newman: Bishop Philip Boyce Post-modernism: Margeurite Peeters and Letters Fit for Mission? What next?: William Oddie, James Arthur and the Editor www.faith.org.uk MAY PRICE INCREASE Due to further increases in costs regrettably annual faith we will be increasing the basic subscription rate to £25 and the cover price to £4.50 for the May summer session issue. Other rates will increase accordingly. We hope you will still find our full, frank and quality content very good value for money. Thank you for your continued support of our apostolate. Catholicism a new synthesis by Edward Holloway Monday 4th to Friday 8th August 2008 Pope John Paul II gave the blueprint for at Woldingham School catechetical renewal with the Catechism of the Catholic Church. Catholicism: A New Synthesis Four days of lectures, discussion seeks to show why such teaching makes perfect and seminars around a particular theme, sense in a world which has come of age in in a relaxed holiday environment, scientific understanding.
    [Show full text]
  • Application of Human Factors in Reducing Human Error in Existing Offshore Facilities
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln United States Department of Transportation -- Publications & Papers U.S. Department of Transportation 2002 Application of Human Factors in Reducing Human Error in Existing Offshore Facilities Jeffrey Thomas ExxonMobil, [email protected] Clifford C. Baker American Bureau of Shipping Thomas B. Malone Carlow International Incorporated, [email protected] John T. Malone Carlow Associates, [email protected] Christina L. Hard BP America Inc., [email protected] See next page for additional authors Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/usdot Part of the Civil and Environmental Engineering Commons Thomas, Jeffrey; Baker, Clifford C.; Malone, Thomas B.; Malone, John T.; Hard, Christina L.; Rezende, Ivan C. L.; Caruana, Sally; and Witten, Mark, "Application of Human Factors in Reducing Human Error in Existing Offshore Facilities" (2002). United States Department of Transportation -- Publications & Papers. 34. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/usdot/34 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the U.S. Department of Transportation at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in United States Department of Transportation -- Publications & Papers by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. Authors Jeffrey Thomas, Clifford C. Baker, Thomas B. Malone, John T. Malone, Christina L. Hard, Ivan C. L. Rezende, Sally Caruana, and Mark Witten This article is available at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/usdot/ 34 Application of Human Factors Engineering in Reducing Human Error in Existing Offshore Systems WORKING GROUP 3 2ND INTERNATIONAL WORKSHOP ON HUMAN FACTORS IN OFFSHORE OPERATIONS (HFW2002) APPLICATION OF HUMAN FACTORS ENGINEERING IN REDUCING HUMAN ERROR IN EXISTING OFFSHORE SYSTEMS Jeffrey Thomas ExxonMobil Houston, TX USA [email protected] Clifford C.
    [Show full text]
  • The Power of Principles: Physics Revealed
    The Passions of Logic: Appreciating Analytic Philosophy A CONVERSATION WITH Scott Soames This eBook is based on a conversation between Scott Soames of University of Southern California (USC) and Howard Burton that took place on September 18, 2014. Chapters 4a, 5a, and 7a are not included in the video version. Edited by Howard Burton Open Agenda Publishing © 2015. All rights reserved. Table of Contents Biography 4 Introductory Essay The Utility of Philosophy 6 The Conversation 1. Analytic Sociology 9 2. Mathematical Underpinnings 15 3. What is Logic? 20 4. Creating Modernity 23 4a. Understanding Language 27 5. Stumbling Blocks 30 5a. Re-examining Information 33 6. Legal Applications 38 7. Changing the Culture 44 7a. Gödelian Challenges 47 Questions for Discussion 52 Topics for Further Investigation 55 Ideas Roadshow • Scott Soames • The Passions of Logic Biography Scott Soames is Distinguished Professor of Philosophy and Director of the School of Philosophy at the University of Southern California (USC). Following his BA from Stanford University (1968) and Ph.D. from M.I.T. (1976), Scott held professorships at Yale (1976-1980) and Princeton (1980-204), before moving to USC in 2004. Scott’s numerous awards and fellowships include USC’s Albert S. Raubenheimer Award, a John Simon Guggenheim Memorial Foun- dation Fellowship, Princeton University’s Class of 1936 Bicentennial Preceptorship and a National Endowment for the Humanities Research Fellowship. His visiting positions include University of Washington, City University of New York and the Catholic Pontifical University of Peru. He was elected to the American Academy of Arts and Sciences in 2010. In addition to a wide array of peer-reviewed articles, Scott has authored or co-authored numerous books, including Rethinking Language, Mind and Meaning (Carl G.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz and China: a Commerce of Light Franklin Perkins Frontmatter More Information
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-83024-9 - Leibniz and China: A Commerce of Light Franklin Perkins Frontmatter More information LEIBNIZ AND CHINA Why was Leibniz so fascinated by Chinese philosophy and culture? What specific forms did his interest take? How did his interest com- pare with the relative indifference of his philosophical contemporaries and near-contemporaries such as Spinoza and Locke? In this highly original book, Franklin Perkins examines Leibniz’s voluminous writ- ings on the subject and suggests that his interest was founded in his own philosophy: the nature of his metaphysical and theological views required him to take Chinese thought seriously. Leibniz was unusual in holding enlightened views about the intellectual profitability of cultural exchange, and in a broad-ranging discussion Perkins charts these views, their historical context, and their social and philosophical ramifications. The result is an illuminating philosophical study which also raises wider questions about the perils and rewards of trying to understand and learn from a different culture. franklin perkins is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at DePaul University, Chicago. He has published in early modern European philosophy, early Chinese philosophy, and comparative philosophy, with articles appearing in the Journal of the History of Ideas, the Journal of Chinese Philosophy, and the Leibniz Review. © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-83024-9 - Leibniz and China: A Commerce of Light
    [Show full text]
  • A New History of Western Philosophy Ebook Free Download
    A NEW HISTORY OF WESTERN PHILOSOPHY PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Anthony Kenny | 1088 pages | 15 Oct 2012 | Oxford University Press | 9780199656493 | English | Oxford, United Kingdom A New History of Western Philosophy PDF Book Namespaces Article Talk. Politics Learn how to enable JavaScript on your browser. It is obvious that they This approach leads to a thoroughly engaging overview for anyone interested in Western philosophy. Choose your country or region Close. Many more analytically-minded philosophers are unlikely to be very familiar with the views of Schopenhauer, and many of any stripe tend not to be up on the sometimes very odd details of Peirce's views. Schools of Thought: From Aristotle to Augustine 3. Sign in to Purchase Instantly. Philosophy Break is a social enterprise dedicated to getting more people engaged with philosophy. Politics Though critics claim Kenny's account of philosophy, while generally good, is quite limited in the Islamic world, focusing only on those works that became important in the Latin tradition. The title of the first chapter -- "Bentham to Nietzsche" -- is indicative of this cosmopolitan approach, as is the inclusion of thinkers as diverse as Schopenhauer and Mill in one chapter. Follow Philosophy Break. God Chronology. He has published more than forty books on philosophy and history. A New History of Western Philosophy is a stimulating chronicle of the intellectual development of Western civilization, allowing readers to trace the birth and growth of philosophy from antiquity to the present day. Knowledge and its Limits 5. Enabling JavaScript in your browser will allow you to experience all the features of our site.
    [Show full text]
  • Historical Essays in Philosophy by Anthony Kenny Owen Goldin Marquette University, [email protected]
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 1-1-2009 Review of From Empedocles to Wittgenstein: Historical Essays in Philosophy by Anthony Kenny Owen Goldin Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, Vol. 3, No. 9 (2009). Permalink. © 2009 University of Notre Dame Philosophy Department. Used with permission. Anthony Kenny From Empedocles to Wittgenstein: Historical Essays in Philosophy Anthony Kenny, From Empedocles to Wittgenstein: Historical Essays in Philosophy, Oxford University Press, 2008, 218pp., $60.00 (hbk), ISBN 9780199550821. Reviewed by Owen Goldin, Marquette University From Empedocles to Wittgenstein is a collection of essays written by Kenny during the last few years. In his preface Kenny tells us that most are attempts to justify somewhat controversial positions taken in his introductory A New History of Western Philosophy.[1] Most, but not all, have been previously published; some have been revised for this collection. As the title declares, all have their source in issues in the history of philosophy. Together they document the most recent phase in the evolution of the thought of one of the most significant philosophers working today. "Seven Concepts in Creation" offers a synoptic view of the philosophic contours of what Kenny identifies as the seven major concepts of creation found in the Western tradition: "the Platonic concept, the Mosaic concept, the Augustinian concept, the Avicennan concept, the Thomist concept, the Scotist concept, and the Cartesian concept" (12). Kenny presents a taxonomy of these by way of seven aspects of those accounts: what they say of the nature of the creator, what existed prior to creation, whether there was a blueprint for creation (and if so, what it was), the reason for creation, the things created, and when creation took place.
    [Show full text]
  • Fundamentalism Themenheft 8
    Themenheft 8 Herbert Rainer Pelikan Fundamentalism Themenheft 8 Herbert Rainer Pelikan Fundamentalism Extreme Tendencies in modern Christianity, Islam and Judaism (= Evang. Rundbrief, SNr. 1/2003) Wien 2003 Vorwort Der Begriff Fundamentalismus ist ein Thema der aktuellen Diskussion; Grund genug, sich damit auch aus ethischer Sicht zu beschäftigen. Fundamentalismus, der sich nach der iranischen Ayatollah-Revolution (1979) verbreite- te, ist heute fast ein Schimpfwort geworden. Fundamentalismus ist keineswegs ein speziell christliches oder islamisches Phänomen, son- dern die Gefahr einer jeden - auch säkularen - Weltanschauung und Religion. Anstelle eines vertrauenden und Wachstumsfähigen Glaubens wird ein absoluter und endgültiger Wahrheits- standpunkt bezogen, der nicht in der Diskussion einsichtig gemacht, sondern nur mit Macht behauptet wird. Fundamentalismus ist ein sehr ambivalentes Thema. Denn grundsätzlich ist es ja zu begrüßen, wenn Menschen ihr Leben auf einem festen Funda- ment aufbauen. Das gilt ja auch für den Glauben, wie das Gleichnis Jesu Vom Hausbau (Mt. 7, 24-29) sehr deutlich zeigt: 24 Darum, wer diese meine Rede hört und tut sie, der gleicht einem klugen Mann, der sein Haus auf Fels baute. 25 Als nun ein Platzregen fiel und die Wasser kamen und die Winde wehten und stießen an das Haus, fiel es doch nicht ein; denn es war auf Fels gegrün- det. 26 Und wer diese meine Rede hört und tut sie nicht, der gleicht einem törichten Mann, der sein Haus auf Sand baute. 27 Als nun ein Platzregen fiel und die Wasser kamen und die Winde wehten und stießen an das Haus, da fiel es ein und sein Fall war groß. Ins Politische übertragen könnte man hier von einem Hochhalten einer Werteorientierung in positiver Abgrenzung gegenüber einem Opportunismus sprechen.
    [Show full text]
  • Suggestions for Further Reading
    MP_D01.qxd 11/23/06 2:43 AM Page 382 Suggestions for Further Reading GENERAL SURVEYS OF MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY Armstrong, A. H., ed. 1970. The Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Copleston, Frederick. 1950. A History of Philosophy, vol. 2: Medieval Philosophy: From Augustine to Duns Scotus. Westminster, MD: The Newman Press (many subsequent reprintings by various presses). Copleston, Frederick. 1953. A History of Philosophy, vol. 2: Late Medieval and Renaissance Philosophy. Westminster, MD: The Newman Press (many subsequent reprintings by various presses). Gilson, Étienne. 1955. History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages. New York: Random House. Gracia, Jorge J. E., and Timothy B. Noone, eds. 2003. A Companion to Philosophy in the Middle Ages. Blackwell Companions to Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell. Kenny, A. 2005. A New History of Western Philosophy, vol. 2: Medieval Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Kretzmann, Norman, et al., eds. 1982. The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy: From the Rediscovery of Aristotle to the Disintegration of Scholasticism, 1100–1600. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Luscombe, David E. 1997. History of Western Philosophy, vol. 2: Medieval Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Marenbon, John. 1981. From the Circle of Alcuin to the School of Auxerre: Logic, Theology and Philosophy in the Early Middle Ages. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Marenbon, John. 1983. Early Medieval Philosophy (480–1150): An Introduction. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Marenbon, John. 1991. Later Medieval Philosophy (1150–1350): An Introduction. London: Routledge. Marenbon, John, ed. 1998. The Routledge History of Philosophy, vol. 3: The Middle Ages. London: Routledge. McGrade, A.
    [Show full text]
  • Human Factors
    Chapter 14 Human Factors Introduction Why are human conditions, such as fatigue, complacency, and stress, so important in aviation maintenance? These conditions, along with many others, are called human factors. Human factors directly cause or contribute to many aviation accidents. It is universally agreed that 80 percent of maintenance errors involve human factors. If they are not detected, they can cause events, worker injuries, wasted time, and even accidents. [Figure 14-1] 14-1 maintenance errors are parts installed incorrectly, missing Human Factors parts, and necessary checks not being performed. In Mental comparison to many other threats to aviation safety, the State Emotional mistakes of an aviation maintenance technician (AMT) can be State more difficult to detect. Often times, these mistakes are present but not visible and have the potential to remain latent, affecting the safe operation of aircraft for longer periods of time. Human AMTs are confronted with a set of human factors unique Capabilities within aviation. Often times, they are working in the evening Physical or early morning hours, in confined spaces, on platforms that State are up high, and in a variety of adverse temperature/humidity conditions. The work can be physically strenuous, yet it also Human requires attention to detail. [Figure 14-2] Because of the Limitations nature of the maintenance tasks, AMTs commonly spend more time preparing for a task than actually carrying it out. Proper Environmental documentation of all maintenance work is a key element, and Conditions Human-Machine AMTs typically spend as much time updating maintenance Interface logs as they do performing the work.
    [Show full text]
  • The Essence of Morality
    European Review, Vol. 21, No. S1, S123–S126. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Academia Europæa 2013. The online version of this article is published within an Open Access environment subject to the conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution license ,http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/.. doi:10.1017/S106279871300015X The Essence of Morality ANTHONY KENNY St John’s College, Oxford, OX1 3JP, UK. E-mail: [email protected] There are three elements that are essential to a system of morality: a moral community, moral values, and a moral code. There cannot be a purely private morality any more than a purely private language. The moral life of the community consists of the shared pursuit of non-material values: this is what distinguishes morality from economics. This pursuit is carried out within a framework that excludes certain types of behaviour: it is this that distinguishes morality from aesthetics. Moral laws are created by the moral community in a way similar to the way in which grammar and syntax are created by the linguistic community. There are three elements that are essential to morality: a moral community, a set of moral values, and a moral code. All three are necessary, and none on its own is sufficient. First, it is as impossible to have a purely private morality as it is to have a purely private language, and for very similar reasons. Secondly, the moral life of the community consists of the shared pursuit of non-material values, such as fairness, truth, comradeship, freedom. It is the nature of the values pursued that distinguishes morality from economics.
    [Show full text]
  • Human Error and Accident Causation Theories, Frameworks and Analytical Techniques: an Annotated Bibliography
    Publications 9-2000 Human Error and Accident Causation Theories, Frameworks and Analytical Techniques: An Annotated Bibliography Douglas A. Wiegmann University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign Aaron M. Rich University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign Scott A. Shappell Federal Aviation Administration, Civil Aeromedical Institute, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://commons.erau.edu/publication Part of the Aviation Safety and Security Commons, and the Human Factors Psychology Commons Scholarly Commons Citation Wiegmann, D. A., Rich, A. M., & Shappell, S. A. (2000). Human Error and Accident Causation Theories, Frameworks and Analytical Techniques: An Annotated Bibliography. , (). Retrieved from https://commons.erau.edu/publication/736 This Report is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Publications by an authorized administrator of Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Aviation Research Lab Institute of Aviation University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign ARL 1 Airport Road Savoy, Illinois 61874 Human Error and Accident Causation Theories, Frameworks and Analytical Techniques: An Annotated Bibliography Douglas A. Wiegmann and Aaron M. Rich Aviation Research Lab and Scott A. Shappell Civil Aeromedical Institute Technical Report ARL-00-12/FAA-00-7 September 2000 Prepared for Federal Aviation Administration Oklahoma City, OK Contract DTFA 99-G-006 1 ABSTRACT Over the last several decades, humans have played a progressively more important causal role in aviation accidents as aircraft have become more. Consequently, a growing number of aviation organizations are tasking their safety personnel with developing safety programs to address the highly complex and often nebulous issue of human error.
    [Show full text]
  • Habitus in the Roman Catholic Tradition: Context and Challenges
    chapter 2 Habitus in the Roman Catholic Tradition: Context and Challenges Brian Patrick Green St. Thomas Aquinas defines habitus, following Aristotle, Augustine, and Aver- roes, respectively, as “a disposition whereby someone is disposed, well or ill,” as “that whereby something is done when necessary,” and as “that whereby we act when we will.”1 Aquinas also defines habitus as “a disposition in re- lation to a thing’s nature, and to its operation or end, by reason of which disposition a thing is well or ill disposed thereto.”2 Contemporary commenta- tors have at tempted to help clarify this tangle of meanings, with Craig St even Titus saying that “Aquinas defines habitus as an acquired quality that we alter only with difficulty. It is a disposition to act which has become second nature (connaturalis),”3 and Anthony Kenny (quoted approvingly by Brian Davies) say- ing that “a habitus for Aquinas is ‘half-way between a capacity and an action, between pure potentiality and full actuality.’”4 Clearly, there is much complexity underlying the concept of habitus. The philosophical and theological concept represented by the Latin word habitus has its roots in both Aristotle and the Bible.5 Humans have known for a long time that what one does becomes who one is, and, when this is applied to morally relevant behavior, what we do makes us better or worse as persons. The medieval Scholastic phrase, “agere sequitur esse,” describes this linkage 1 Aquinas 1947, i–ii, 49.2–3. Bonnie Kent helpfully points out, however, that Averroes does not say exactly what Aquinas attributes to him (and Aquinas knew that, using the correct quotation of Averroes in the Summa Contra Gentiles), and so we ought to consider the defi- nition Aquinas attributes to Averroes as rather attributable to Aquinas himself (Kent 2013, 107–108).
    [Show full text]