Making War Robert J

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Making War Robert J Cornell Law Review Volume 93 Article 11 Issue 1 November 2007 Making War Robert J. Delahunty John Yoo Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Robert J. Delahunty and John Yoo, Making War, 93 Cornell L. Rev. 123 (2007) Available at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr/vol93/iss1/11 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Cornell Law Review by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. RESPONSE MAKING WAR RobertJ Delahuntyt &John Yoott Presidents have long initiated military conflict without specific congressional authorization. For large wars this practice extends at least as far back as the Korean War if not further, and for smaller conflicts the practice can be traced to the very first administrations.1 During the Vietnam War, academic critics turned to the original in- tent of the Constitution's Framers to argue that this form of war mak- ing was illegal. 2 This view became the governing consensus through the 1970s and 1980s and reached its culmination in books by John Hart Ely, Louis Fisher, Michael Glennon, and Harold Koh, among others.3 Simply put, these authors conclude that Congress's power to "declare war" gives it the full and plenary authority to decide whether 4 to initiate military hostilities abroad, except in cases of self-defense. Originalists have quarreled about war powers ever since. We have argued that the original understanding does not prove that the mod- ern practice is illegal.5 If anything, the best reading of the text finds significant support for presidential initiative in war. Unleashing the Dogs of War represents the latest step in the originalist discourse. 6 Pro- t Associate Professor of Law, University of St. Thomas School of Law, Minneapolis, MN. tt Professor of Law, University of California at Berkeley School of Law (Boalt Hall); Visiting Scholar, American Enterprise Institute. We would like to thank Sean Callagy for his research assistance. I SeeJohn C. Yoo, The Continuationof Politics by Other Means: The Original Understand- ing of War Powers, 84 CAL. L. REV. 167, 177-82 (1996). 2 See id. at 188-94. 3 See, e.g., JOHN HART ELY, WAR AND RESPONSIBILITY. CONSTITUTIONAL LESSONS OF VI- ETNAM AND ITS AFTERMATH 3-5 (1993); Louis FISHER, PRESIDENTIAL WAR POWER 185-206 (2d ed., rev. 2004); MICIIAELJ. GLENNON, CONSTITUTIONAL DIPLOMACY 80-84 (1990); Louis HENKIN, CONSTITUTIONALISM, DEMOCRACY, AND FOREIGN AFFAIRS 109 (1990); HAROLD HONGJU KOH, THE NATIONAL SECURITY CONSTITUTION: SHARING POWER AFTER THE IRAN- CONTRA AFFAIR 158-61 (1990); CHARLES A. LOFGREN, "GOVERNMENT FROM REFLECTION AND CHOICE": CONSTITUTIONAL ESSAYS ON WAR, FOREIGN RELATIONS, AND FEDERALISM 3-38 (1986). 4 See, e.g., ELY, supra note 3, at 3. 5 See, e.g., Robert J. Delahunty & John Yoo, The President's Constitutional Authority to Conduct Military Operations Against Terrorist Organizations and the Nations that Harbor or Sup- port Them, 25 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 487 (2002). 6 Saikrishna Prakash, Unleashing the Dogs of War: What the Constitution Means by "Declare War," 93 CORNELL L. REV. 45 (2007). CORNELL LAW REVIEW [Vol. 93:123 fessor Prakash maintains that we can infer the Constitution's alloca- tion of war powers through a broad survey of the eighteenth-century use of the phrase "declare war." This approach, he claims, yields more support for the conventional wisdom than originalists have com- monly thought. Prakash has made an important contribution by bringing more historical sources to bear on the question of the origi- nal understanding of war powers. In this Response, we will carry the dialogue further. First, we will argue that Prakash's interpretive approach imposes an unexplained burden of proof that places little to no importance on the starting point of constitutional interpretation: the text. The best reading of the text rejects Prakash's claim about Congress's power to declare war. We supplement our textualist reading by exploring constitutional structure, which should not tolerate the redundancies created by Prakash's approach. The key point here is that the constitutional structure already gives Congress more than enough constitutional au- thority through the creation and funding of the military, a power that was all the greater in the eighteenth century when the United States had no standing Army or Navy. Second, we address Prakash's use of the historical sources and argue, in short, that he has thrown his net too wide. Accumulating statements where some diplomats and gov- ernment officials used the phrase "declare war" in a broad sense ig- nores the use of the phrase in a constitutional setting. Examination of the important antecedents to the Constitution, developments in eight- eenth-century American constitutional thought, and the broader in- tellectual understanding of war and international law during the ratification period shows that "declare war" does not bear the mean- ing that Prakash claims. We close with a more complex account of early war making under the Washington and Jefferson administra- tions, an account that yields lessons which are different from those that Prakash has elicited. Unleashing the Dogs of War's strength is its sheer effort, combing a broad range of sources on the eighteenth-century use of "declare war." But it could benefit from a more sophisticated approach to ana- lyzing historical data. Prakash essentially attempts to assemble every mention of the phrase "declare war" to show that it was universally understood to mean "begin" hostilities. But he cannot deny that im- portant historical figures of the period both used "declare war" in its narrower sense under international law and used other phrases, such as "make," "engage," or "levy," to refer to beginning military conflict. In the face of conflicting historical material, the right way to recon- struct the original understanding is to place the evidence in the right context. Such contexts include the constitutional development dur- ing the Critical Period in favor of a stronger executive, the declining 2007] 0MAKING WAR significance of declaring war in international legal thought, and the nature of warfare during the late eighteenth century. Arriving at the best reading of the original understanding is not just a matter of pil- ing more chits on one side of a scale but of also bringing the right historical analysis to the material. We think that when analysis is ap- plied to evidence, the historical data weigh against the modern ap- proach to war powers. I BURDEN OF PROOF/TEXTUALISM Prakash's argument depends on an unstated burden of proof. He argues that it is "impossible" to arrive at a textual interpretation of the Constitution's power to declare war and that, because of this tex- tual ambiguity, historical evidence must determine the Constitution's allocation of war powers. In other words, Prakash believes that the constitutional text does not count for all that much; the operation of war powers must be deduced from the original understanding of the Constitution held at the time of its ratification. For Prakash, uncertainty in the text is so pervasive that it is per- missible to read constitutional provisions to be redundant, inconsis- tent, or superfluous. His reading, for example, makes superfluous Article I, Section 8's vesting in Congress of the power to "grant Letters of Marque and Reprisal."'7 If the Declare War Clause already gives Congress the complete power to decide whether to start military hos- tilities of all kinds, there is little point in also giving it the lesser power of authorizing a limited naval war. That would clearly be part of Prakash's broad reading of the Declare War Clause. The same goes for the companion clause giving Congress the authority to "make Rules concerning Captures on Land and Water."8 If the Declare War Clause already means that Congress can define the nature of any war, including its goals, limits, and methods, it is redundant to give the Legislature the power to set rules of capture. Prakash can point to no other place where the Constitution grants both a broad power fol- lowed by several lesser included (but unnecessary) versions of the same power in the same sentence. One should resist any reading of the Constitution that renders any of its provisions meaningless. Prakash's approach to the text also causes problems by giving dif- ferent words in the Constitution the same meaning. Under his ap- proach, the power to declare war encompasses all forms of starting war. Article I, Section 10 prohibits the states from having the ability to "engage in war, unless actually invaded, or in such imminent Danger 7 U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8. 8 Id. *CORNELL LAW REVIEW [Vol. 93:123 as will not admit of delay" without the consent of Congress.9 If "de- clare war" has the meaning that Prakash attributes to it, the Framers should not have used "engage." Article III defines "treason" as "levy- ing war."' 10 If "declar[ing] war" encompasses all forms of beginning war, the Framers should likewise have made treason the crime of "de- claring war" against the United States. Prakash admits that "declare" and "levy" overlap but claims that using "levy" twice would have less- ened the power given to Congress. It is difficult to see why-if the Framers sought to give Congress the broadest possible power over war, "levy" would have been, like "engage," the more appropriate choice. These arguments assume that the Framers were "crystal clear" in their use of language, for otherwise they do not negate Prakash's alter- native reading.
Recommended publications
  • The Pre-History of Self-Determination: Union and Disunion of States in Early Modern International Law
    THE PRE-HISTORY OF SELF-DETERMINATION: UNION AND DISUNION OF STATES IN EARLY MODERN INTERNATIONAL LAW Han Liu* TABLE OF CONTENTS ABSTRACT ................................................................................................................ 2 I. INTRODUCTION ...................................................................................................... 2 II. THE STATE AND THE NATION STATE ................................................................... 7 III. TERRITORIAL ACCESSION IN EARLY MODERN EUROPE ...................................... 9 A. The King and the Sovereign .......................................................................... 9 B. Land and Territory ....................................................................................... 15 1. Division of Realms ................................................................................... 17 2. Land and Sovereignty............................................................................... 18 3. Dynastic-Patrimonial Territoriality .......................................................... 20 4. Shape of Early Modern Territory ............................................................. 22 C. Aggregating Land: Conquest and Inheritance.............................................. 24 IV. OUTSIDE EUROPE: LAND APPROPRIATION AND COLONIAL EXPANSION........... 27 A. Just War as Civilizing Process: Vitoria’s Catholic Argument ..................... 29 B. Conquest or Settlement: Locke, Vattel, and the Protestant Argument ........ 31 V. THE JURIDICIAL
    [Show full text]
  • Virtual Currencies in the Eurosystem: Challenges Ahead
    STUDY Requested by the ECON committee Virtual currencies in the Eurosystem: challenges ahead Monetary Dialogue July 2018 Policy Department for Economic, Scientific and Quality of Life Policies Authors: Rosa María LASTRA, Jason Grant ALLEN Directorate-General for Internal Policies EN PE 619.020 – July 2018 Virtual currencies in the Eurosystem: challenges ahead Monetary Dialogue July 2018 Abstract Speculation on Bitcoin, the evolution of money in the digital age, and the underlying blockchain technology are attracting growing interest. In the context of the Eurosystem, this briefing paper analyses the legal nature of privately issued virtual currencies (VCs), the implications of VCs for central bank’s monetary policy and monopoly of note issue, and the risks for the financial system at large. The paper also considers some of the proposals concerning central bank issued virtual currencies. This document was provided by Policy Department A at the request of the Committee on Economic and Monetary Affairs. This document was requested by the European Parliament's Committee on Economic and Monetary Affairs. AUTHORS Rosa María LASTRA, Centre for Commercial Law Studies, Queen Mary University of London Jason Grant ALLEN, Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin Centre for British Studies, University of New South Wales Centre for Law Markets and Regulation ADMINISTRATOR RESPONSIBLE Dario PATERNOSTER EDITORIAL ASSISTANT Janetta CUJKOVA LINGUISTIC VERSIONS Original: EN ABOUT THE EDITOR Policy departments provide in-house and external expertise to support EP committees
    [Show full text]
  • Denationalisation of Money -The Argument Refined
    Denationalisation of Money -The Argument Refined An Analysis ofthe Theory and Practice of Concurrent Currencies F. A. HAYEK Nohel Laureate 1974 Diseases desperate grown, By desperate appliances are reli'ved, Or not at all. WILLIAM SHAKESPEARE (Hamlet, Act iv, Scene iii) THIRD EDITION ~~ Published by THE INSTITUTE OF ECONOMIC AFFAIRS 1990 First published in October 1976 Second Edition, revised and enlarged, February 1978 Third Edition, with a new Introduction, October 1990 by THE INSTITUTE OF ECONOMIC AFFAIRS 2 Lord North Street, Westminster, London SWIP 3LB © THE INSTITUTE OF ECONOMIC AFFAIRS 1976, 1978, 1990 Hobart Paper (Special) 70 All rights reseroed ISSN 0073-2818 ISBN 0-255 36239-0 Printed in Great Britain by GORON PRO-PRINT CO LTD 6 Marlborough Road, Churchill Industrial Estate, Lancing, W Sussex Text set in 'Monotype' Baskeroille CONTENTS Page PREFACE Arthur Seldon 9 PREFACE TO THE SECOND (EXTENDED) EDITION A.S. 11 AUTHOR'S INTRODUCTION 13 A NOTE TO THE SECOND EDITION 16 THE AUTHOR 18 INTRODUCTION TO THE THIRD EDITION Geoffrey E. Wood 19 THE PRACTICAL PROPOSAL 23 Free trade in money 23 Proposal more practicable than utopian European currency 23 Free trade in banking 24 Preventing government from concealing depreciation 25 II THE GENERALISATION OF THR UNDERLYING PRINCIPLE 26 Competition in currency not discussed by economists 26 Initial advantages of government monopoly in money 27 III THE ORIGIN OF THE GOVERNMENT PREROGATIVE OF MAKING MONEY 28 Government certificate of metal weight and purity 29 The appearance of paper money 31
    [Show full text]
  • Contracts Then and Now: an Appreciation of Friedrich Kessler
    Contracts Then and Now: An Appreciation of Friedrich Kessler George L. Prieste Succeeding generations of Contracts scholars too young to have attended Friedrich Kessler's Contracts course' can only imagine its content from Fritz's powerful writings and from his enduring casebook. 2 The modem Contracts course as taught today, however, is surely different. Today, Contracts is a course addressing the regulation of private transactions in which our courts, as self-conscious social engineers, are evaluated in terms of their ability to define rules that optimally assign risks and informational burdens in order to broadly enhance societal welfare. There is little question today that the role of courts in resolving contract disputes is to regulate underlying behavior and to protect parties in unequal bargaining positions. Courts must also define what are called "default" rules-rules to control where the parties' meaning or intent is unclear-with attention to problems of monopoly or economic power, differential informational advantages, and relative risk-bearing ability.' These are not unimportant issues to a modem society, and the concepts and principles of modem Contracts are necessary implements in every lawyer's tool chest. Nevertheless, as a course in applied regulation, Contracts today is not always a class favorite and, to many, lacks the drama and apparent relevance of more popular Yale Law School courses, such as those on discrimination, free speech, or constitutional interpretation. The Contracts course taught by Fritz Kessler, in contrast, was hardly lacking in drama or relevance. Kessler saw the various doctrines of contract law and the principle of freedom of contract as intimately tied to the great issues of the modem world: the apparent decline of modem capitalism; the threatened capture of democracy by industrial interests; and the exploitation t John M.
    [Show full text]
  • Article the Study of International Law in the Spanish Short Nineteenth
    ! ! Article The Study of International Law in the Spanish Short Nineteenth Century (1808- 1898) ! Ignacio de la Rasilla del Moral* ! ! Si hubo un tiempo en que pensar o esperar, fue soñar o creer, ! hoy esperar es pensar. Pensemos y esperemos.! Concepción del Arenal, Ensayo sobre el Derecho de Gentes (1879)! ! ! ! Table of Contents ! Introduction .............................................................................. 122 I. International Law in Spain Before and After the Independence of the Latin American Republics ....................... 125 II. From the 1850s to the First “Professional” Generation of 1883 .......................................................................................... 132 III. The First Professional Generation and the Return of Vitoria ....................................................................................... 139 Conclusion ................................................................................ 148 !!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!! * Lecturer in Law at Brunel Law School (Brunel University, London) where he teaches Public International Law, European Union Law and Public Law of the United Kingdom. LL.B. (Complutense, Madrid), M.A. & Ph.D. (The Graduate Institute, Geneva). LL.M. (Harvard). Post- Doctoral Max Weber Fellow in Law, European University Institute in Florence (2011-2012). Adjunct Professor of International Human Rights Law, New York University (NYU-Florence) in the Spring of 2012. The author was awarded a Summer Academic Fellowship by Harvard
    [Show full text]
  • THE TASK of LAW. by Roscoe Pound. Franklin and Marshall College, Lancaster, Pa., 1944
    December, 1944 BOOK REVIEWS THE TASK OF LAW. By Roscoe Pound. Franklin and Marshall College, Lancaster, Pa., 1944. Pp. 94. Price: $1.50. This slender volume, comprising the North Law Lectures delivered at Franklin and Marshall in 1941, epitomizes the contributions of Professor Roscoe Pound to jurisprudence and the philosophy of law. The reader who is even moderately familiar with Dean Pound's books and articles published over a period of some four decades will recognize here all of the major ideas which he has expounded or advocated. To the reader who is unfamiliar with Dean Pound's previous work, this compressed treatment may seem somewhat didactic and abstract. The limitations of time and space imposed upon the author did not permit him to vivify his broad conceptions with numerous concrete illustrations. For these the reader will need to go to his previous writings, to which, unfortunately for that purpose, no references are here given. The present review will endeavor to indicate some of these major contributions, and some additions to them which appear in the present volume. The urge to probe beneath the surface aspects of a politically organized society has moved two different classes of men to produce writings on juris- prudence, or the philosophy of law. One class consists of those who moved from general theories about the universe, the realm of philosophical specu- lation, into the realm of law and politics. The other consists of those who, engaged originally and primarily in the study and practical work of law and politics, moved from the concrete to the general.
    [Show full text]
  • THE PROBLEM of PROVING FOREIGN LAW by ARTHUR NUSSBAUM T
    THE PROBLEM OF PROVING FOREIGN LAW By ARTHUR NUSSBAUM t THE FACT THEORY. JUDICIAL NOTICE THE phrase "foreign law is a fact," or "foreign law must be proved as a fact," is well known both in common law countries1 and on the Continent,' and traceable back at least to the eighteenth century.' During the last century this "fact" theory has lost much of its popularity in civil law countries, but in America and in other common law jurisdic- tions it still dominates cases,4 legislation,' and literary discussion." In- "the funda- deed, Professor Beale has recently called the fact theory 7 mental premise" underlying the rules for proving foreign law. Each law can be considered as a fact insofar as it is a controlling force in society; but when law and fact are contrasted, foreign law is, of course, law. However, foreign law is not always on equal terms with the law of the forum. Although courts are expected to know their own law, they cannot be expected to know the law of other countries. Hence litigating parties must prove the applicable foreign law to the court. t Research Professor of Public Law, Columbia University. 1. See, e.g., Church v. Hubbard, 2 Cranch 187 (U. S. 1804) ; Nashua Say. Bank v. Anglo-American Co., 189 U. S. 221 (1903); Los Angeles Iv. See. Corp. v. Joslyn, 12 N. Y. S. (2d) 370 (Sup. Ct. 1939); Guaranty Trust Co. v. Hannay & Co. [1918] 2 K. B. 623, 667 (C. A.); Lazard Bros. v. Midland Bank [1933] A. C. 289, 297 (H.
    [Show full text]
  • Lauterpacht and Beyond: Jewish/German Authorship and the History of International Law”
    Developments Conference Report—The Intellectual History of International Law as a Research Field—“Lauterpacht and Beyond: Jewish/German Authorship and the History of International Law” By Felix Lange* A. Introduction Publications on the history of international law written during the Cold War can almost be counted on one hand.1 A pragmatically-oriented generation studied practical areas like UN Charter law, international trade law, or international environmental law, while the theory and history of international law played only a secondary role.2 An intellectual history of international law, asking which ideas and concepts inspired and formed international law writing, hardly received any attention.3 Since the 1990s, researchers have more frequently turned to the historical roots of international law thinking. With the end of the Cold War, the European Journal of International Law started to publish articles on the life and work of influential European international lawyers from the 20th century like George Scelle, Hersch Lauterpacht, Dionisio Anzilotti, Alfred Verdross, Hans Kelsen, and Alf Ross.4 Furthermore, international * LL.M. (New York University); M.A., Modern and Contemporary History (University of Freiburg). 1 Ingo Hueck, The Discipline of the History of International Law - New Trends and Methods on the History of International Law, 3 J. HIST. INT’L L. 194 (2001); Alexandra Kemmerer, The Turning Aside: On International Law and Its History, in PROGRESS IN INTERNATIONAL LAW, 71, 71–94 (Russell Miller & Rebecca Bratspies eds., 2008); for the few studies during this period, see ARTHUR NUSSBAUM, A CONCISE HISTORY OF THE LAW OF NATIONS (2d ed. 1954); WILHELM GREWE, EPOCHEN DER VÖLKERRECHTSGESCHICHTE (1984).
    [Show full text]
  • Philip Jessup, Transnational Law (New Haven: Yale University Press
    IGLP 2012 – IELR Stream various states."5 But while I agree with him that states are not the only subjects of international law,6 I do not go to the other extreme and say with Scelle that individuals are the only subjects. Philip Jessup, Transnational Law (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1956), Corporate bodies, whether political or nonpolitical, have certainly been treated in orthodox pages 1-8. theory as fictions, but their essential reality as entities is now well accepted and law deals with them as such.7 Scelle agrees that states have characteristic features distinguishing them from 8 1. THE UNIVERSALITY OF THE HUMAN PROBLEMS other organizations, but for him these features are not of a legal order but historico-politique, a distinction which is not drawn here. The subject to which these chapters are addressed is the law applicable to the complex interrelated world community which may be described as beginning with the individual and Transnational situations, then, may involve individuals, corporations, states, organizations of reaching on up to the so-called "family of nations" or "society of states." Human society in its states, or other groups. A private American citizen, or a stateless person for that matter, whose development since the end of the feudal period has placed special emphasis on the national state, passport or other travel document is challenged at a European frontier confronts a transnational and we have not yet reached the stage of a world state. These facts must be taken into account, situation. So does an American oil company doing business in Venezuela; or the New York but the state, in whatever form, is not the only group with which we are concerned.
    [Show full text]
  • Treaty Textualism
    Article Treaty Textualism Andrew Tuttt I. IN TRO DU CTIO N ............................................................................................................................ 284 II. THE MOVE TO "ORIGINAL METHODS" ORIGINALISM.................................................................. 289 III. THE ORIGINAL UNDERSTANDING OF TREATY INTERPRETATION................................................. 292 A. The "Most Highly Qualified Publicists" and the Late Eighteenth-Century Law of N atio n s..............................................................................................................................2 92 B. Interpretation According to Vattel, Grotius, Pufendorf, Burlamaqui, Rutherforth, B acon, and B lackstone ..................................................................................................... 295 1. V attel's The Law of N ations.................................................................................. 295 2. Grotius's The Rights of War and Peace................................................................ 299 3. Pufendorf s Of the Law of Nature and Nations .................................................... 302 4. Burlamaqui's The PrinciplesofNatural and PoliticLaw .................................... 305 5. Other Authorities (Blackstone, Lee, Bacon, Bynkershoek, Rutherforth and W o lff) .................................................................................................................... 30 7 C. Intepretation as a Distinctive Concern in the Framing and Ratification.........................
    [Show full text]
  • The Reception of Vattel's Law of Nations in the American Colonies: from James Otis and John Adams to the Declaration of Independence
    Article The Reception of Vattel's Law of Nations in the American Colonies: From James Otis and John Adams to the Declaration of Independence GERBER, Dominik Andréas, OSSIPOW, William Abstract The treatise of the Swiss philosopher and jurist Emer de Vattel, The Law of Nations (1758), is well known in the United States and has attracted sustained scholarly atten- tion. Against the widespread assumption that the reception of The Law of Nations in America only started in 1775, this article establishes that Vattel's treatise was available on American soil already in 1762. This finding paves the way for inquiry into Vattel's intellectual authority in the revolutionary context from the early pamphleteers to the Declaration of Independence. Following a reception-based methodology that facilitates robust inferences from patterns of intertextuality, this study aims to make up for the gap in Vattel's historiography regarding the crucial period between 1762 and 1776. New England, and the Boston area in particular, turn out to be the hotbeds of Vattel's reception. A special emphasis is put on the central role of John Adams as a transmitter of Vattel's thought in the colonial discourse in spring 1776. In the great political docu- ments of this time, most of which were written by Adams or by patriots close to him, such as [...] Reference GERBER, Dominik Andréas, OSSIPOW, William. The Reception of Vattel's Law of Nations in the American Colonies: From James Otis and John Adams to the Declaration of Independence. American Journal of Legal History, 2017, p. 1-35 DOI : 10.1093/ajlh/njx023 Available at: http://archive-ouverte.unige.ch/unige:99834 Disclaimer: layout of this document may differ from the published version.
    [Show full text]
  • PUBLIC POLICY and the POLITICAL CRISIS in the CONFLICT of LAWS by ARTHUR NUSSBAUM T I
    PUBLIC POLICY AND THE POLITICAL CRISIS IN THE CONFLICT OF LAWS By ARTHUR NUSSBAUM t I. THE ACTUAL USE OF THE PUBLIC POLICY CONCEPT SINCE the appearance of Professor Lorenzen's pioneering studies on the conflict of laws,1 that is, during approximately the last two decades, many of the basic problems of the subject have received abundant and illuminative investigation in this country. Yet the significance of one important problem, that of public policy, which has recently come to the fore as a result of the world political crisis, with its accompanying in- congruities and tensions in respect to the various municipal laws, seems hardly to have been recognized in recent legal literature. The purpose of the present Article is to suggest the necessity of a reexamination of the entire doctrine in the light of recent developments. Although utilization of the public policy concept in Anglo-American law is wide and varied, much confusion can be avoided if the various legal uses of this concept are kept separate. One such use is affirmative: public policy is relied upon in order to solve doubts as to the interpre- tation of legal rules. This affirmative or interpretative function is par- ticularly important in respect to statutory provisions of a penal char- acter.2 Two other uses of the concept are negative or limitative. (1) Public policy limits freedom of contracts, invalidating, for instance, yellow-dog contracts or agreements in restraint of trade.' Comparable to the contract use is the use of public policy in invalidating testamentary provisions, for instance, because of the presence of illicit conditions.4 ' Research Professor of Public Law, Columbia University.
    [Show full text]