The Science of Harmonics in Classical Greece by Andrew Barker New York: Cambridge University Press, 2007
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
4 Aristoxenus and Music Therapy
4 Aristoxenus and Music Therapy Fr. 26 Wehrli within the Tradition on Music and Catharsis Antonietta Provenza 1. Introduction The importance of music for the ancient Pythagoreans,1 together with recognition of its therapeutic function, already attested at the * My heartfelt thanks to Professor Carl Huffman and all the participants in the Aristoxenus Conference for their interest in my paper and comments. I will always remember those days at DePauw University as wonderful and happy. I wish also to thank Professor Salvatore Nicosia, my research tutor, for having read and discussed with me this essay at different times. Translations are mine, unless otherwise indicated. 1 Still indispensable for a general overview of Early Pythagoreanism and the ques- tions concerning it is Burkert (1972). Among Burkert’s main emphases are the Pla- tonic contamination of sources on Pythagoreanism since the 4th century BCE and the representation of Pythagoras as a “wise man” with shamanistic features (although the unsuitability of the notion of shamanism for ancient Greek culture has been since highlighted in Bremmer [1983] 29–48 and [2002] 27–40; cf. also Minar [1971]), rather than as a “scientist,” since “scientific Pythagoreanism” is not clearly attested until Philolaus. Most important among the studies opposing Burkert’s “shamanistic” Pythagoras and giving prominence to the “scientific” side of early Pythagoreanism and to its relationship with Near-eastern science are Kahn (1974), van der Waerden (1979) and Zhmud (1997). Also see on Pythagoreanism and its sources: Centrone 91 92 Aristoxenus of Tarentum dawn of Greek literature,2 favored the rise of a long tradition relat- ing to the Pythagoreans and music therapy, which is most famously and richly attested in two Neoplatonic works, The Life of Pythagoras (Vita Pythagorae) by Porphyry of Tyre (ca. -
Jean-Benjamin De Laborde's
Florida State University Libraries Electronic Theses, Treatises and Dissertations The Graduate School 2005 Jean-Benjamin de Labore's Abrégé D'Un Traité Dde Composition: The Merger of Musica Speculativa and Musica Pratica with an Emerging Musica Historica Donald Craig Filar Follow this and additional works at the FSU Digital Library. For more information, please contact [email protected] THE FLORIDA STATE UNIVERSITY COLLEGE OF MUSIC JEAN-BENJAMIN DE LABORE’S ABRÉGÉ D’UN TRAITÉ DE COMPOSITION: THE MERGER OF MUSICA SPECULATIVA AND MUSICA PRATICA WITH AN EMERGING MUSICA HISTORICA By DONALD CRAIG FILAR A Dissertation submitted to the College of Music in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Degree Awarded: Fall Semester, 2005 Copyright © 2005 Donald Craig Filar All Rights Reserved The members of the Committee approve the dissertation of Donald Craig Filar defended on 19 October 2005. ______________________________ Jane Piper Clendinning Professor Directing Dissertation ______________________________ James R. Mathes Committee Member ______________________________ Jeffery Kite-Powell Committee Member ______________________________ William Cloonan Outside Committee Member The Office of Graduate Studies has verified and approved the above-named committee members. ii TABLE OF CONTENTS List of Figures ................................................................................................................vi Abstract ........................................................................................................................vii -
Diogenes of Babylon: a Stoic on Music and Ethics
Diogenes of Babylon: A Stoic on Music and Ethics Linda Helen Woodward UCL Submitted for the degree of Master of Philosophy in Classics 1 Diogenes of Babylon: A Stoic on Music and Ethics I, Linda Helen Woodward, confirm that the work presented in this thesis is my own. Where information has been derived from other sources, I confirm that this has been indicated in the thesis. 2 ABSTRACT The aim of this thesis is to analyse Diogenes of Babylon's musico-ethical theories, to place them into their historical context, and to examine the possible influences on his thought. Earlier treatments of this Stoic's work have been hampered by the lacunose state of Philodemus' surviving text, the major source, and in some cases an opponent's views have been mistakenly attributed to Diogenes. Conversely, the state of the text together with erroneous column numbering, have resulted in part of Diogenes' philosophy being ascribed to his Epicurean opponent. Taking Professor Delattre's recently reconstructed edition of Philodemus’ De musica as my starting point, I attempt to more fully analyse Diogenes' theory of music and ethics. Following a short introductory chapter, I briefly examine Diogenes' other interests, analyse his psychology compared with that of earlier Stoics, and examine how that fits into Diogenes' view on music in education. I outline Diogenes' general view on music, and compare the musical writings of Plato, Aristotle and the early Peripatetics with those of Diogenes, particularly in relation to education, and outline areas that might have influenced the Stoic. I also look at later writings where they can be seen as evidence for Diogenes' work. -
Aristoxenus Elements of Rhythm: Text, Translation, and Commentary with a Translation and Commentary on Poxy 2687
© 2009 Christopher C. Marchetti ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ARISTOXENUS ELEMENTS OF RHYTHM: TEXT, TRANSLATION, AND COMMENTARY WITH A TRANSLATION AND COMMENTARY ON POXY 2687 by CHRISTOPHER C. MARCHETTI A Dissertation submitted to the Graduate School-New Brunswick Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Program in Classics written under the direction of Prof. Thomas Figueira and approved by ________________________ ________________________ ________________________ ________________________ New Brunswick, New Jersey May, 2009 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Aristoxenus’ Elements of Rhythm: Text, Translation, and Commentary with a Translation and Commentary on POxy 2687 By Christopher C. Marchetti Dissertation Director: Prof. Thomas Figueira Aristoxenus of Tarentum makes productive use of Aristotelian concepts and methods in developing his theory of musical rhythm in his treatise Elements of Rhythm. He applies the Aristotelian distinction between form and material and the concept of hypothetical necessity to provide an explanation for why musical rhythm is manifested in the syllables of song, the notes of melody, and the steps of dance. He applies the method of formulating differentiae, as described in Aristotle’s Parts of Animals, to codify the formal properties of rhythm. Aristoxenus’ description of the rhythmic foot presents several interpretive challenges. Our text is fragmentary, and we lack Aristoxenus’ definitions of several key terms. This study seeks to establish the meanings of these terms on the basis of a close examination of the structure of Aristoxenus’ argument. Parallel passages in Aristides Quintilianus’ On Music are considered in detail for ii their consistency or lack thereof with Aristoxenian usage. -
The Science of Harmonics in Classical Greece
This page intentionally left blank THE SCIENCE OF HARMONICS IN CLASSICAL GREECE The ancient science of harmonics investigates the arrangements of pitched sounds which form the basis of musical melody, and the principles which govern them. It was the most important branch of Greek musical theory, studied by philosophers, mathematicians and astronomers as well as by musical specialists. This book examines its development during the period when its central ideas and rival schools of thought were established, laying the foundations for the speculations of later antiquity, the Middle Ages and the Renaissance. It concentrates particularly on the theorists’ methods and purposes and the controversies that their various approaches to the subject pro- voked. It also seeks to locate the discipline within the broader cultural environment of the period; and it investigates, sometimes with sur- prising results, the ways in which the theorists’ work draws on and in some cases influences that of philosophers and other intellectuals. andrew barker is Professor of Classics in the Insititute of Archae- ology and Antiquity at the University of Birmingham. THE SCIENCE OF HARMONICS IN CLASSICAL GREECE ANDREW BARKER CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 8RU, UK Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521879514 © Andrew Barker 2007 This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provision of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. -
Platonic Legacy (4Th Century BC) - Part 3
Platonic Legacy (4th century BC) - part 3 http://www.rhuthmos.eu/spip.php?article1946 Platonic Legacy (4th century BC) - part 3 - Recherches - Vers un nouveau paradigme scientifique ? - Sur le concept de rythme - Date de mise en ligne : Wednesday 9 November 2016 Copyright © Rhuthmos - All rights reserved Copyright © Rhuthmos Page 1/11 Platonic Legacy (4th century BC) - part 3 Previous chapter Rhythm in Music - Aristoxenus' Elements of Rhythmics (4th cent. BC) The 쟼¹ºp ÃÄ¿¹ÇµÖ± - Elements of Rhythmics was probably not the first book ever written on musical rhythm in the West but certainly the first that was preserved at least partly (a section of Book 2) (for recent editions Pearson, 1989; Marchetti, 2009). It was part of a larger work comprising some Elementa harmonica which also survive incomplete. Strikingly, Aristoxenus thinks of rhythm in an opposite way to the Moderns who consider first the whole (rhythm) and divide it into primary and secondary segments (measures and notes). He begins with what he calls the "khrónoi prôtoi - primary time-lengths." It is necessary that there be some smallest [time-lengths] [»±Ç¯ÃĿŠÄö½ ÇÁ̽ɽ - elakhístous tôn khrónôn], in which the singer will place each of his notes. The same account obviously holds concerning syllables and bodily gestures. This [time-length] [ÇÁ̽ó - khrónoi], into which in no way can be placed two notes, two syllables, nor two steps, we will call primary [time-length] [ÀÁöÄ¿½ ÇÁ̽¿½ - prôton khrónon] (Aristoxenus, Elements of Rhythm, 2.11-12, trans. Marchetti, my mod.) Let the primary [time-length] [ÀÁöĿ ¼r½ Äö½ ÇÁ̽ɽ - prôtos mèn tôn khrónôn] be defined as that which is not able to be subdivided by any of the rhythmized objects; the diseme as that which is measured out by two of these, the triseme as that measured out by three, the tetraseme as that measured out by four. -
MTO 22.4: Rehding, Instruments of Music Theory
Volume 22, Number 4, December 2016 Copyright © 2016 Society for Music Theory * Alexander Rehding NOTE: The examples for the (text-only) PDF version of this item are available online at: http://www.mtosmt.org/issues/mto.16.22.4/mto.16.22.4.rehding.php KEYWORDS: history of music theory, critical organology, sound studies, acoustics, epistemic thing, Pythagoras, Gaffurius, Vicentino, Cowell, monochord, archicembalo, siren, rhythmicon. ABSTRACT: This article explores musical instruments as a source for the historical study of music theory. The figure of Pythagoras, and his alleged penchant for the monochord, offers a way into this exploration of the theory-bearing dimensions of instruments. Musicians tend to think of instruments primarily in terms of music-making, but in other contexts instruments are, more broadly, tools. In the context of scientific experimentation, specifically, instruments help researchers come to terms with “epistemic things”—objects under scrutiny that carry specific (but as yet unknown) sources of knowledge within them. Aspects of this experimental practice can productively be transferred to the study of music theory and are explored in two test cases from different periods of musical theorizing (and instrument building): Nicola Vicentino’s archicembalo from mid-sixteenth century Italy, and Henry Cowell’s rhythmicon from early twentieth-century America. Received July 2016 1. Pythagoras musicus [1.1] With his emblematic monochord Pythagoras ruled music and the cosmos. As its name suggests, the monochord (monos = single, chordê = string) is a very simple instrument, consisting of little more than a string stretched out from one side of a wooden plank to the other so it can freely vibrate. -
The Shaping of Deduction in Greek Mathematics
The aim of this book is to explain the shape of Greek mathemati- cal thinking. It can be read on three levels: first as a description of the practices of Greek mathematics; second as a theory of the emergence of the deductive method; and third as a case-study for a general view on the history of science. The starting point for the enquiry is geometry and the lettered diagram. Reviel Netz exploits the mathematicians’ practices in the construction and let- tering of their diagrams, and the continuing interaction between text and diagram in their proofs, to illuminate the underlying cognitive processes. A close examination of the mathematical use of language follows, especially mathematicans’ use of repeated formulae. Two crucial chapters set out to show how mathemati- cal proofs are structured and explain why Greek mathematical practice manages to be so satisfactory. A final chapter looks into the broader historical setting of Greek mathematical practice. R N is a Research Fellow at Gonville and Caius College, Cambridge, and an Affiliated Lecturer in the Faculty of Classics. Abbreviations THE SHAPING OF DEDUCTION IN GREEK MATHEMATICS Edited by Q S (General Editor) L D, W L, J. B. S and J T The books in this series will discuss the emergence of intellectual traditions and of related new disciplines. The procedures, aims and vocabularies that were generated will be set in the context of the alternatives available within the contemporary frameworks of ideas and institutions. Through detailed studies of the evolution of such traditions, and their modification by different audiences, it is hoped that a new picture will form of the development of ideas in their concrete contexts. -
The Intelligible Creator-God and the Intelligent Soul of the Cosmos in Plato’S Theology and Metaphysics
University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations Summer 2010 The Intelligible Creator-God and the Intelligent Soul of the Cosmos in Plato’s Theology and Metaphysics Jason G. Rheins University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the Ancient Philosophy Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, History of Religion Commons, History of Science, Technology, and Medicine Commons, Metaphysics Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Rheins, Jason G., "The Intelligible Creator-God and the Intelligent Soul of the Cosmos in Plato’s Theology and Metaphysics" (2010). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 184. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/184 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/184 For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Intelligible Creator-God and the Intelligent Soul of the Cosmos in Plato’s Theology and Metaphysics Abstract ABSTRACT THE INTELLIGIBLE CREATOR-GOD AND THE INTELLIGENT SOUL OF THE COSMOS IN PLATO’S THEOLOGY AND METAPHYSICS Jason G. Rheins Charles H. Kahn and Susan Sauvé Meyer When Plato discusses the World-soul, cosmic intellect (nous), and the Demiurge, he approaches them theologically, i.e. as being the subjects of an account of the nature of the gods, but few works in the last half-century or more have addressed the ‘players’ in Plato’s theology as such. The major strata in the hierarchy of divine beings were referred to in the Neo-Platonist tradition as “hypostases”. My question is this: between intellect, the World-soul, the Demiurge, and even the Forms how many hypostases did Plato posit, what were their nature, and what overall functions did they play in his philosophical system? I analyze Plato’s various accounts of those divine things that are immanent in the world of change (e.g.