Philosophy of Law (Phil 5415)/Jurisprudence Spring 2017 Prof

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Philosophy of Law (Phil 5415)/Jurisprudence Spring 2017 Prof Philosophy of Law (Phil 5415)/Jurisprudence Spring 2017 Prof. Brian Bix Draft Syllabus and Course Summary Law School (Mondale Hall) Room 7 – Mondays, Wednesdays, Fridays, 1:25 – 2:20 pm Required Text: Brian Bix, Jurisprudence: Theory and Context (7th ed., 2015); Other texts will be from (free) Internet-accessible sites Course Objectives: To gain knowledge and understanding of the major legal theorists and schools of jurisprudence and the issues that concern them. More generally, to gain greater proficiency in making, analyzing, and critiquing theoretical arguments. Course grade: 50% final examination; 50% term paper. Jan. 18 Introduction, Jan. 20 The Nature of Jurisprudence and Conceptual Analysis Brian Bix, “Joseph Raz and Conceptual Analysis,” American Philosophical Association Newsletter on Philosophy and Law, vol. 06(2), pp. 1-7 (2007), reprinted at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=948766 Jan. 23 Natural Law Theory (Aquinas) Aquinas on Law (Summa Theologica, I-II, Questions 90-97) http://www.fordham.edu/halsall/source/aquinas2.html Bix, pp. 67-74 Jan. 25 Natural Law Theory, cont. (John Finnis) John Finnis, “Natural Law Theories” (2015), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/natural-law-theories/ Bix, pp. 75-81 1 Jan. 27 Lon Fuller Lon L. Fuller, “Positivism and Fidelity to Law -- A Reply to Professor Hart,” 71 Harvard Law Review 630 (1958) Matthew Kramer, “Scrupulousness Without Scruples: A Critique of Lon Fuller and His Defenders,” 18 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 235 (1998) Both are available from Hein Online, The direct link is here: http://www.heinonline.org/HOL/Welcome Jan. 30 The Obligation to Obey the Law M.B.E. Smith, “Is There a Prima Facie Obligation to Obey the Law?” 82 Yale Law Journal 950 (1973) (Hein Online) Feb. 1 Legal Positivism -- Austin Brian Bix, “John Austin” (2014), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/austin-john/ Feb. 3 Legal Positivism -- Hart H. L. A. Hart, “Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals,” 71 Harvard Law Review 593 (1958) (Hein Online) Bix, pp. 33-49 Feb. 6 Legal Positivism – Debates Within the Hartian Tradition Leslie Green, “Legal Positivism” (2003), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-positivism/ Bix, pp. 49-52 Feb. 8 A Hybrid View: The Planning Theory of Law Scott Shapiro, Summary of Legality 72 Analysis 537-541 (2012), available at http://web.b.ebscohost.com/ehost/detail/detail?sid=767ff98a-3669-4d07-b984- 4bc165d4d33b%40sessionmgr112&vid=0&hid=124&bdata=JnNpdGU9ZWhvc3QtbGl2ZQ%3d %3d#db=a2h&AN=77692646 Jeremy Waldron, “Planning for Legality” (Book Review), 109 Michigan Law Review 883 (2011) (Hein Online) 2 Feb. 10 Hans Kelsen’s Pure Theory of Law Hans Kelsen, “What is the Pure Theory of Law?” 34 Tulane Law Review 269 (1960) Hans Kelsen, “The Pure Theory of Law and Analytical Jurisprudence,” 55 Harvard Law Review 44 (1941) (both Hein Online) Bix, 57-66 Feb. 13 Ronald Dworkin Ronald M. Dworkin, “The Model of Rules,” 35 University of Chicago Law Review 14 (1967) (Hein Online) Feb. 15 Ronald Dworkin, cont. Ronald M. Dworkin, “Law as Interpretation,” 60 Texas Law Review 527 (1982) (Hein Online) Bix, pp. 91-102 [No Class Feb. 17, 20: Law School Winter Break] Feb. 22 Precedent Frederick Schauer, “Precedent,” 39 Stanford Law Review 571 (1987) (Hein Online) Bix, pp. 153-159 Feb. 24 Legal Rights Kenneth Campbell, “Legal Rights” (2013), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-rights/ Leif Wenar, “Rights” (2015), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rights/ Feb. 27 Legal Enforcement of Morality Larry Alexander, “The Legal Enforcement of Morality,’” in R. G. Frey & C. H. Wellman (eds.), A Companion to Applied Ethics 128-141 (Blackwell, 2003), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=265451 Bix, pp. 169-179 3 March 1 Justice (Rawls) John Rawls, “Justice as Fairnesss: Political not Metaphysical,” 14 Philosophy and Public Affairs 223 (1985), available from JSTOR, linked from http://www.jstor.org/action/showBasicSearch Bix, pp. 107-115 March 3 Justice (feminist critique, other critiques) Susan Moller Okin, “Justice and Gender: An Unfinished Debate,” 72 Fordham Law Review 1537 (2004) (Hein Online) Bix, pp. 115-122 March 6 Punishment Antony Duff, “Legal Punishment” (2013), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-punishment/ Bix, pp. 123-129 March 8 Legal Realism Oliver W. Holmes, Jr., “The Path of the Law,” 10 Harvard Law Review 457 (1897) Karl Llewellyn, “A Realistic Jurisprudence -- The Next Step,” 30 Columbia Law Review 431 (1930) (both Hein Online) March 10 Legal Realism, cont. Lon L. Fuller, “American Legal Realism,” 82 University of Pennsylvania Law Review 429 (1934) (Hein Online) Bix, pp. 193-204 [March 13-17 No Classes – Spring Break] March 20 Scandinavian Legal Realism Alf Ross, “Tu-Tu,” 70 Harvard Law Review 812 (1957) (Hein Online) Bix, pp. 278-279 4 March 22 Historical Jurisprudence Robert E. Rodes, Jr., “On the Historical School of Jurisprudence,” 49 American Journal of Jurisprudence 165 (2004) Harold Berman, “The Historical Foundations of Law,” 54 Emory Law Journal 13 (2005) (both Hein Online) [Berman also at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=666123] Bix, pp. 275-276 March 24 Economic Analysis of Law (Coase) Ronald Coase, “The Problem of Social Cost,” 3 Journal of Law and Economics 1 (1960) (JSTOR) Bix, pp. 211-216 March 27 Economic Analysis of Law, cont. (overview) Lewis Kornhauser, “Economic Analysis of Law” (2011), in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-econanalysis/ Bix, pp. 205-211, 216-231 March 29 Economic Analysis of Law, cont. (behavioral critique) Cass R. Sunstein, “Behavioral Analysis of Law,” 64 University of Chicago Law Review 1175 (1997) (Hein Online) March 31 Critical Legal Studies I Duncan Kennedy, “Legal Education and the Reproduction of Hierarchy,” 32 Journal of Legal Education 591 (1982) Morton J. Horwitz, “Rights,” 23 Harvard Civil Rights-Civil Liberties Law Review 393 (1988) (both Hein Online) Bix, pp. 235-239 April 3 Critical Legal Studies II Mark Tushnet, “Defending the Indeterminacy Thesis,” 16 QLR [Quinnipiac Law Review] 339 (1996) John Finnis, “On ‘The Critical Legal Studies Movement,’” 30 American Journal of Jurisprudence 21 (1985) (both Hein Online) 5 April 5 Feminist Theory I Robin West, “Re-Imagining Justice,” 14 Yale Journal of Law and Feminism 333 (2002) Martha Albertson Fineman, “Gender and Law: Feminist Legal Theory’s Role in New Legal Realism,” 2005 Wisconsin Law Review 405 (both Hein Online) Bix, pp. 240-247 [April 7 No Class] April 10 Feminist Theory II Catharine A. MacKinnon, “Reflections on Sex Equality Under Law,” 100 Yale Law Journal 1281 (1991) (Hein Online) April 12 Feminist Theory/Critical Race Theory Angela P. Harris, “Race and Essentialism in Feminist Legal Theory,” 42 Stanford Law Review 581 (1990) Derrick Bell, “Racial Realism,” 24 Connecticut Law Review 363 (1992) (both Hein Online) [April 14 No Class] April 17 Critical Race Theory II Mari Matsuda, “Affirmative Action and Legal Knowledge: Planting Seeds in Plowed-Up Ground,” 11 Harvard Women’s Law Journal 1 (1988) Derrick A. Bell, “Who’s Afraid of Critical Race Theory?,” 1995 University of Illinois Law Review 893 (1995) Girardeau A. Spann, “Just Do It,” 67 Law and Contemporary Problems 11 (Summer 2004) (all Hein Online) April 19 Law and Literature I Sanford Levinson, “Law as Literature,” 60 Texas Law Review 373 (1982) (Hein Online) Bix, pp. 257-263 6 [April 21 No Class] April 24 Law and Literature II Robert M. Cover, “Violence and the Word,” 95 Yale Law Journal 1601 (1986) Robin West, “The Literary Lawyer,” 27 Pacific Law Journal 1187 (1996) (both Hein Online) April 25 (Tues.) Law and Culture Naomi Mezey, “Mapping a Cultural Studies of Law,” in Austin Sarat & Patricia Ewick (eds.), The Handbook of Law and Society 39-55 (Wiley & Sons, 2015), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/Papers.cfm?abstract_id=2686760 April 26 Law and Evolutionary Biology, Review Session Owen D. Jones, “Law and Biology: Toward an Integrated Model of Human Behavior,” 8 Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues 167 (1997) (Hein Online) Wednesday, May 10, 8:30 – 10:30 am: Final Exam 7 Paper Topics The task is to read a legal theory article or a chapter from a book on legal theory, offer a short but precise summary, and evaluate the article’s strengths and weaknesses. Suggested authors include (but are not limited to): - H.L.A. Hart - Duncan Kennedy - Jules Coleman - Lon Fuller - Morton Horwitz - Joseph Raz - Hans Kelsen - Richard Delgado - Jerome Frank - John Finnis - Derrick Bell - Richard Posner - Ronald Dworkin - Martha Fineman - Robin West - Oliver Wendell Holmes - Catharine MacKinnon - Wesley Hohfeld If you have a question about the appropriateness of an article or an author, ask me about it. (It is probably best to avoid articles that assigned for reading for the class. If you do select an article that was assigned for the class, the paper will be expected to go significantly beyond the descriptive and critical classroom discussion of that article.) Reference to other authors and other works is not required, but any such references must be adequately documented. Similarly, the paper should also give sufficient documentation to show me the location of quotations reproduced from the article under review and the location of arguments summarized. Prior to writing the paper, you will need to write up an outline. That outline will not be graded, but you will need to set up an appointment with me to discuss it (briefly). The finished paper must be word-processed, and at least 5,000 words long (please use double- spacing, reasonable margins, and a 12-point font; insert page numbers). The paper must be submitted to me (by email digital attachment – as a Word or PDF file) by the end of the day, the last day of the course, April 27.
Recommended publications
  • Family Law by the Numbers: the Story That Casebooks Tell
    SJ Quinney College of Law, University of Utah Utah Law Digital Commons Utah Law Faculty Scholarship Utah Law Scholarship 12-2020 Family Law by the Numbers: The Story That Casebooks Tell Laura T. Kessler Follow this and additional works at: https://dc.law.utah.edu/scholarship Part of the Family Law Commons Draft 11/9/20 forthcoming 62 Ariz. L. Rev. 903 (2020) All rights reserved FAMILY LAW BY THE NUMBERS: THE STORY THAT CASEBOOKS TELL Laura T. Kessler* This Article presents the findings of a content analysis of 86 family law casebooks published in the United States from 1960 to 2019. Its purpose is to critically assess the discipline of family law with the aim of informing our understandings of family law’s history and exposing its ideological foundations and consequences. Although legal thinkers have written several intellectual histories of family law, this is the first quantitative look at the field. The study finds that coverage of marriage and divorce in family law casebooks has decreased by almost half relative to other topics since the 1960s. In contrast, pages dedicated to child custody and child support have increased, more than doubling their relative share. At the same time, the boundaries of family law appear to remain quite stubborn. Notwithstanding sustained efforts by family law scholars and educators to restructure the field of family law so that it considers additional domains of law affecting families (such as tax, business, employment, health, immigration, and government benefits), the core of the academic field of family law has remained relatively static in the past 60 years.
    [Show full text]
  • The Virtue of Vulnerability
    THE VIRTUE OF VULNERABILITY Nathalie Martin* My vulnerability to my own life is irrefutable. Nor do I wish it to be otherwise, As vulnerability is a guardian of integrity. Anne Truitt, sculptor and psychologist Ten years ago, vulnerability scholar Martha Fineman began examining how vulnerability connects us as human beings and what the universal human condition of vulnerability says about the obligations of the state to its institutions and individuals.1 Central to Fineman’s work is recognition that vulnerability is universal, constant, and inherent in the human condition.2 Fineman has spent the past decade examining how structures of our society will manage our common vulnerabilities, in hopes of using these vulnerabilities to move society toward a new vision of equality.3 While Fineman focuses on how vulnerability can transform society as a whole, here I examine the role of vulnerability in transforming individual relationships, particularly the attorney-client relationship. I argue that lawyers can benefit greatly by showing their vulnerabilities to clients. As a common syllogism goes, “All men are mortal. Socrates is a man. Therefore, Socrates is mortal.”4 Similarly, we could say that a particular * I am grateful for Nancy Huffstutler, who first brought the virtue of vulnerability into my conciseness, to my colleagues Jennifer Laws and Ernesto Longa for their fine research assistance, my friend John Brandt for teaching me what doctors know about vulnerability, for my friends Jenny Moore and Fred Hart, and my beautiful husband Stewart Paley. I also thank my wonderful editor, William Dietz. 1. Martha A. Fineman, The Vulnerable Subject: Anchoring Equality in the Human Condition, 20 YALE J.L.
    [Show full text]
  • September 26, 2018 Senate Majority
    September 26, 2018 Senate Majority Leader Mitch McConnell Senate Majority Whip John Cornyn Senate Judiciary Committee Chair Chuck Grassley Dear Senators, We write as law professors who have significant experience teaching, researching, and writing about issues of gender violence and representing gender violence survivors in family, civil, and criminal courts. We write to express our profound concern about the process for evaluating the allegations of Judge Kavanaugh’s sexual misconduct, especially in light of the recently emerging claims. The Senate should seek to review all available evidence, including witness testimony relating to all of the allegations raised, in order to evaluate both the competing accounts of underlying events and the nominee’s reflection on those accounts. The allegations should be fully and sensitively investigated by experts who are trained in trauma-informed interviewing techniques before the hearing is held. In this instance, as Dr. Ford has requested, the investigation should be performed by the FBI. There should be no rush in undertaking this important task. All those concerned both with the gravity of the allegations and the integrity of the Court and our systems of governance should prioritize investigation over politics. Particularly given the most recent information about additional allegations, it is incumbent upon the Committee to extend or continue the hearings and a final vote until a thorough investigation of all allegations is completed. The Senate’s approach to the allegations raised by Dr. Christine Blasey Ford, Deborah Ramirez, and now, Julie Swetnick, is deeply troubling. Public statements prejudging the credibility of witnesses and the outcome of the proceedings reflect the very type of biases that have no place in any investigation and that run counter to the purpose of these hearings.
    [Show full text]
  • Vulnerability and Inevitable Inequality Martha Albertson Fineman 1
    Vulnerability and Inevitable Inequality Martha Albertson Fineman 1. Introduction My work over the past several decades has grappled with the limitations of equality. This struggle has resulted in the development of a legal paradigm that brings vulnerability and dependency, as well as social institutions and relationships, together into an analysis of state responsibility. This analysis goes well beyond concern with formal equality and impermissible discrimination. What follows is an account of the development of a theory based on human vulnerability in which the state is theorized as the legitimate governing entity and is tasked with a responsibility to establish and monitor social institutions and relationships that facilitate the acquisition of individual and social resilience. The theory is based on a descriptive account of the human condition as one of universal and continuous vulnerability. The Anglo-American liberal legal imagination often obscures or overlooks this reality.1 The potential normative implications of the theory are found in the assertion that state policy and law should be responsive to human vulnerability. However, the call for a responsive state does not dictate the form responses should take, only that they reflect the reality of human vulnerability. Thus, this approach to law and policy allows for the adaptation of solutions appropriate to differing legal structures and political cultures. 1 Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3087441 Vulnerability theory provides a template with which to refocus critical attention, raising new questions and challenging established assumptions about individual and state responsibility and the role of law, as well as allowing us to address social relationships of inevitable inequality.
    [Show full text]
  • Phil of Law 2014 Syllabus
    Princeton University Politics 563/Philosophy 526 Spring 2014 Philosophy of Law Robert P. George and Michael Smith This seminar will consider a range of issues in philosophy of law with particular emphasis on various dimensions of the relationship between law and morality. Requirements: Students are required to read each week's assignments carefully and participate regularly in seminar discussions. Each student must make a presentation to the seminar. Two written work options are available: (1) a long (7000 word) paper on any topic addressed in the seminar or (2) two shorter (3500), critical essays on issues we have explored. These may, but need not, be related to the topic of one’s presentation. Those readings marked with an asterisk (*) are on e-reserve. The following books (all available in paperback editions) are worth purchasing: Ronald Dworkin, Law’s Empire John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights, 2nd edition Lon L. Fuller, The Morality of Law H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, 2nd edition Joseph Raz, Practical Reason and Norms Week 1: Organizational Meeting *O. W. Holmes, “The Path of the Law,” in The Essential Holmes, ed. Richard Posner, pp. 160-77 *John Austin, “The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, “ in The Philosophy of Law, eds. F. Schauer, W. Sinnot-Armstrong, pp. 32-39 *Carl Llewellyn, “The Bramble Bush, a Realistic Jurisprudence, and the common Law Tradition,” in The Philosophy of Law, eds. F. Schauer, W. Sinnot-Armstrong, pp. 53-62 Week 2: Hart's Concept of Law H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, chs. I-VI *Jonathan Cohen, "Critical Notice of Hart's The Concept of Law," in Mind, Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel's Philosophy of Right As a Theory of Justice
    Copyrighted Material I egel’s Philosophy of Right as a H heory of ustice T J Although many contemporary philosophers have embraced Hegelian philosophy to a surprising degree—which may even help to bridge the gulf between the Analytic and Continental traditions—Hegel’s Elements of the Philosophy of Right has so far failed to exert the slightest influence on the current debates in political philosophy. Rather, in recent years—after the abrupt end of the Marxist phase and its reduction of modern right to a mere superstructure—philosophers returned on a broad front to the rationalist paradigm of the Kantian tradition, which es- sentially dominates the debate from Rawls to Habermas; and however hard these two authors in particular try to embed their Kantian concepts of justice in a realistic, almost social-scientific approach, the theoretical model of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right plays no decisive part in their thought. Nor has the situation changed much in response to the countermovement in political philosophy that came into being through the somewhat arti- ficial grouping of theoreticians as diverse as Charles Taylor, Michael Walzer, or Alasdair MacIntyre under the heading of “communitarianism.” Despite a strong tendency to award a privileged position to ethics as opposed to a formalistic prin- ciple of morality, or to communal values as opposed to arbi- trary individual freedom, no real attempt has been made in these circles to render Hegel’s Philosophy of Right fruitful for the discourse of political philosophy. Indeed, the fact that authors Copyrighted Material chapter 1 such as Michael Walzer, Alasdair MacIntyre, or Joseph Raz are trying to keep the greatest possible distance from the political philosophy of Hegel has acquired an almost symptomatic sig- nificance by now.
    [Show full text]
  • Encounters with Vulnerability
    Encounters with Vulnerability: The victim, the fragile, the monster, the queer, the abject, the nomadic, the feminine, the shameful, and the rest … Conference Proceedings Review by Nayeli Urquiza Haas and Arturo Sánchez García PECANS Interdisciplinary workshop for postgraduates and early career academics in the area of law, gender and sexu- ality (Nov 22nd, 23rd 2013 at Newcastle University) The concept of vulnerability is receiving increasing attention in dialogues about the representation of the body in feminist theory, embodiment in phenomenol- ogy, in ideas of relationality in affect theories, and imaginaries of governance for law and rights, among others. There are synergies in those that might derive from a common interest in evoking the figure of wounding or ‘vulnus’ in Latin and the ethical and political possibilities it enables: the metaphor of the open body and the experience of pain that it references radical openness of embodied experi- ences (Turner 2006). As an ontological and political concept, the notion of vul- nerability discloses the limits of humanist philosophies. Typically the anthropo- centric idea of ‘human’ in – Western liberal politics – have produced a fiction of disembodied subjectivity that has imposed itself as the measure for everyone. The ‘vulnerable subject’ holds a hope for the reconciliation of embodied subjectivity in representation, regulation, and normalisation (Fineman 2008). In those terms, in this workshop we were urged to re-think and re-encounter the different forms of relating to ourselves and others. There are caveats in the powerful concept of vul- nerability. One of them is an ubiquity (Murphy 2012) that enables a heuristic that reveals, among other things, the ambivalent potential in human and non-human Graduate Journal of Social Science February 2015, Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Generations of Scandinavian Legal Realists
    62 RETFÆRD ÅRGANG 32 2009 NR. 1/124 Two Generations of Scandinavian Legal Realists CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Helsingin yliopiston digitaalinen arkisto JOHAN STRANG Johan Strang Abstract: The discussion on the implications of Scandinavian Legal Realism would benefit con- siderably from more careful historical attention to the different political and philosophical ambi- tions of the theoreticians that followed Axel Hägerström. The scholars, who were later gathered under the label Scandinavian Legal Realism, did not represent a static theoretical position that remained unchanged from the 1910s to the 1950s; rather, their aims and ambitions varied with changing political and philosophical circumstances. The purpose of this article is to propose a distinction between two generations of Scandinavian Legal Realists. While the goal of the first generation (Vilhelm Lundstedt and Karl Olivecrona) fell little short of revolutionising the field of jurisprudence, transforming law into a vehicle for political and social reform, one of the main objectives of the second generation (Alf Ross and Ingemar Hedenius) was to take the edge off the radicalism of their predecessors. Key Words: Scandinavian Legal Realism; politics, democracy; Uppsala philosophy; logical em- piricism; Alf Ross; Ingemar Hedenius If Scandinavian Legal Realism could be reduced to one basic tenet, the idea that the law is a social phenomenon ultimately relying only on the sanction of man himself would be one prominent candidate. This was a basic line of thought for the founder of the school, Axel Hägerström (1868-1939), as well as for his followers Vilhelm Lundstedt (1882-1955), Karl Olivecrona (1897-1980), Alf Ross (1899-1979) and Ingemar Hedenius (1908-1982).
    [Show full text]
  • Holmes, Cardozo, and the Legal Realists: Early Incarnations of Legal Pragmatism and Enterprise Liability
    Holmes, Cardozo, and the Legal Realists: Early Incarnations of Legal Pragmatism and Enterprise Liability EDMUND URSIN* TABLE OF CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................. 538 II. SETTING THE STAGE: TORT AND CONSTITUTIONAL LAW AT THE TURN OF THE TWENTIETH CENTURY ............................................................................ 545 III. HOLMES AND THE PATH OF THE LAW ................................................................. 550 A. Holmes and the Need for Judicial Creativity in Common Law Subjects ............................................................................................ 550 B. The Path Not Followed ............................................................................ 554 IV. THE INDUSTRIAL ACCIDENT CRISIS, THE WORKERS’ COMPENSATION SOLUTION, AND A CONSTITUTIONAL CONFRONTATION ....................................... 558 A. The Industrial Accident Crisis and the Workers’ Compensation Solution ............................................................................ 558 * © 2013 Edmund Ursin. Professor of Law, University of San Diego School of Law. Thanks to Richard Posner for valuable comments on an earlier draft of this Article and to Roy Brooks and Kevin Cole for always helpful comments on previous articles upon which I expand in this Article. See Edmund Ursin, Clarifying the Normative Dimension of Legal Realism: The Example of Holmes’s The Path of the Law, 49 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 487 (2012) [hereinafter Ursin, Clarifying];
    [Show full text]
  • The Concept of Law Revisited
    Michigan Law Review Volume 94 Issue 6 1996 The Concept of Law Revisited Leslie Green Osgoode Hall Law School, York University Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr Part of the Public Law and Legal Theory Commons Recommended Citation Leslie Green, The Concept of Law Revisited, 94 MICH. L. REV. 1687 (1996). Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr/vol94/iss6/15 This Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Michigan Law Review at University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Michigan Law Review by an authorized editor of University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. IBE CONCEPT OF LAW REVISITED Leslie Green* THE CONCEPT OF LAW. Second Edition. By H.L.A. Hart. With a Postscript edited by Penelope A. Bulloch and Joseph Raz. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 1994. Pp. xii, 315. $26. Law is a social construction. It is a historically contingent fea­ ture of certain societies, one whose emergence is signaled by the rise of a systematic form of social control and elite domination. In one way it supersedes custom, in another it rests on it, for law is a system of primary social rules that direct and appraise behavior, together with secondary social rules that identify, change, and en­ force the primary rules. Law may be beneficial, but only in some contexts and always at a price, at the risk of grave injustice; our appropriate attitude to it is therefore one of caution rather than celebration.
    [Show full text]
  • Alf Ross 1899–1979: a Biographical Sketch
    MFK-Mendip Job ID: 9777BK--0033-5 3 - 661 Rev: 30-09-2003 PAGE: 1 TIME: 06:44 SIZE: 61,11 Area: JNLS OP: AB ᭧ EJIL 2003 ............................................................................................. Alf Ross 1899–1979: A Biographical Sketch Knud Waaben* Alf Ross was born on 10 June 1899 in Copenhagen, the son of a civil servant in a government department. He graduated from high school in 1917. His first choice was to study at the Technical University, but he left it after one term and turned to law. He finished his legal studies in the summer of 1922 with remarkable results, obtaining the rare distinction then called laudabilis et qvidem egregie. Following graduation, he took up employment in a barrister’s office, but the practical occupations of a trainee did not satisfy him and he preferred to devote his time to further studies in law. Ross was well deserving of the scholarship he received from the Law Faculty for studies abroad. These awards would normally enable a young lawyer to spend about two years in foreign universities, usually in Germany, France and England. In 1923, Ross set out on a study tour which lasted two and a half years. In this same year he married Else-Merete Helweg-Larsen, a student at the Faculty of Humanities, who later became a high school teacher. She was a member of Parliament in 1960–73, representing a small liberal party which held considerable influence over the formation of political majorities after general elections. Ross’ journey took him to France, England and Austria. He may have gone abroad, as many young people did, without a detailed plan of study, but rather with an open mind to learn all he could from foreign law, court visits and perhaps from discussions with professors.
    [Show full text]
  • APA Newsletters
    APA Newsletters Volume 06, Number 2 Spring 2007 NEWSLETTER ON PHILOSOPHY AND LAW FROM THE EDITOR, STEVEN SCALET ARTICLES BRIAN H. BIX “Joseph Raz and Conceptual Analysis” JULES L. COLEMAN “Law and Political Morality” TIMOTHY ENDICOTT “Interpretation, Jurisdiction, and the Authority of Law” KENNETH EINAR HIMMA “Revisiting Raz: Inclusive Positivism and the Concept of Authority” LIAM MURPHY “Razian Concepts” STEPHEN PERRY “Two Problems of Political Authority” © 2007 by The American Philosophical Association ISSN: 1067-9464 APA NEWSLETTER ON Philosophy and Law Steven Scalet, Editor Spring 2007 Volume 06, Number 2 relating to such theories. In particular, I will look at the role of conceptual analysis in legal theory, focusing on some recent FROM THE EDITOR work by Joseph Raz.1 I. Overview Edition in Tribute to Joseph Raz It was a commonplace in the history of jurisprudence to focus on the inquiry, what is law? It is worth taking a few moments Joseph Raz is professor at Columbia University Law School to consider the question more closely. and research faculty at Oxford University. His writings influence generations of scholars and his many students are now among First and foremost, there is a potential confusion (heightened 2 the leading scholars in philosophy of law. in English more than in other major languages ), as “law,” even if focused on matters jurisprudential (and not speaking of physical For this edition of the Newsletter we invited leading political laws, the laws of games, social conventions, etc.), can refer to and legal philosophers to analyze some aspect of Professor a number of different, if related, matters: most prominently, Raz’s ideas.
    [Show full text]